1 Introduction

Irregular migrants and asylum seekers in Europe are increasingly subjected to detention and spatial restrictions, such as containment, dispersal and forced transfers within the territory.Footnote 1 Prominent examples are the confinement of asylum seekers at the Greek islandsFootnote 2 and the German residenzpflicht.Footnote 3 It is also visible in the Netherlands, where migrants with minor children, lacking legal residence, are housed in state-funded shelters, so-called ‘family locations’ (gezinslocaties). The families living in these shelters are subjected to forced transfers, a daily reporting duty and a geographical restriction (prohibition to leave the territory of the municipality in which the shelter is located).

Legal literature on the position of migrants without legal residence focusses mainly on migrants’ formal exclusion from state funded benefits. It examines whether and to what extent the state is legally obliged to provide migrants without legal residence with shelter, health care, education or other kind of basic needs. If attention is payed to their inclusion in these kinds of benefits, this is mainly done from a human rights or comparative perspective. It is emphasized how states, by providing only limited and highly conditional benefits to migrants without legal residence, fail in meeting their positive obligations under human rights law or in reaching some level of harmonization within the EU.Footnote 4 The coercion involved in such inclusionary practises is rarely analysed as such.

While human rights law is a relevant framework for assessing such practises, it has also been argued that human rights law can only provide limited protection for irregular migrants, since human rights ‘seduce us to locate responsibility for the absence of protection with the individual undocumented migrant rather than the state’Footnote 5; because in the context of migration, equal human rights protection should always be weighed against the sovereignty of the state;Footnote 6 or since human rights can be used to justify restrictive migration policies.Footnote 7 In line with this, as this paper will also show, many of the relevant human rights provisions only apply to migrants who are ‘lawfully within the territory’, and, consequently, exclude migrants without legal residence entirely from their scope of application.

For this reason, I propose an alternative normative framework to evaluate practices in which the provision of basic needs is made conditional on irregular migrants’ subjection to coercion: the concept of freedom as non-domination. In this paper, I conceptualize non-domination from a rule of law perspective. To this end, I start from Lovett’s procedural account of arbitrarinessFootnote 8 but complement this with Benton’s focus on unaccountable powerFootnote 9 and Palombella’s argument for ‘duality of law’ as a fundamental requirement of the rule of law.Footnote 10 In the second part of this paper, I apply this normative framework to coercive practices in the family locations for irregular migrants in the Netherlands in order to demonstrate the practical relevance and consequences of the theory. It focusses in particular on the daily reporting obligation to which migrants living in family locations are subjected. This case study serves as an example of the coercive practices and spatial restrictions that migrants without lawful residence are increasingly subjected to throughout Europe.Footnote 11 It shows that the concept of freedom as non-domination as conceptualized in this paper goes beyond the limited protection that human rights law can provide against these kind of coercive bordering practices.

2 The Rule of Law: a Republican Perspective

2.1 Non-Domination and the Rule of Law

The concept of freedom as non-domination is an historical concept that has its origins in the classical republican tradition, with figures such as Machiavelli, Milton, Montesquieu, Blackstone, Jefferson and Madison. There has recently been renewed interest in the concept of freedom as non-domination by, what is often called, ‘neo-republicanism’.Footnote 12 Freedom in terms of non-domination is about the absence of mastery by others and can, therefore, be contrasted with both freedom as non-interference (negative freedom) and freedom as self-mastery (positive freedom).Footnote 13 In neorepublican theory, mastery, or ‘domination’, is understood as subjection to a threat of arbitrary, or uncontrolled, interferences. Domination is the kind of power no oneFootnote 14 should be subjected to, even if this power is not being used or only used for legitimate reasons.Footnote 15

With regard to the issue of what type of control or constraint is required to prevent an interference from becoming domination, two main views have been put forward: a substantive (or democratic) one and a procedural one. Following Arnold and Harris,Footnote 16 the substantive view can be divided into ‘interest substantivism’, where power is sufficiently constrained if the power holder is forced to track the interests of the power subjectsFootnote 17; and ‘control substantivism’, where power is sufficiently constrained if it is governed by the direct influence of the power subjects.Footnote 18 The procedural view is mainly developed by Lovett. This view equates republican freedom with the traditional idea of the rule of law, ‘provided of course that we are willing to loosen and extend this idea considerably’.Footnote 19 Since migrants usually lack the right to vote and cannot, therefore, exercise full democratic control, the procedural ‘rule of law’ view seems, at first sight, most relevant to reduce migrants’ domination.

Much has been written about the rule of law. It is widely accepted as a fundamental value and a crucial element of the legitimacy of a state. It has been described as ‘the most powerful and often repeated political ideal in contemporary global discourse’Footnote 20 and as the ‘the most important political ideals of our time’.Footnote 21 Most of the literature on the rule of law does not, however, (elaborately) deal with the virtues or functions of the rule of law. Instead, it focusses on the requirements for legal systems that result from the rule of law. Lists of features or elements of the rule of law are drawn up, often distinguishing thin (minimalist, formal) and thick (maximalist, substantive) versions of the rule of law. Thick versions of the rule of law usually include values such as democracy and recognition of social and civil human rights; whereas thin versions merely require procedural safeguards and legality. It is, however, widely accepted that both these versions experience difficulties is justifying their importance.Footnote 22

Lovett argues why in his conceptualization, the rule of law is not redundant (as in thick versions of the rule of law) nor relatively trivial (as in thin versions of the rule of law). He defends the procedural view on arbitrariness, or, in other words, the value of the rule of law, by arguing that the law can govern the use of coercive force effectively and reliably in a way alternative practices cannot.Footnote 23 In his conceptualization of the rule of law, people should not be exposed to coercive force except as the consequence of their having failed to observe a legally valid prescriptive rule. In that way, people can avoid being exposed to coercive force by observing the rule without depending on the good will of other human agents.Footnote 24

This implies, according to Lovett, that three broad criteria should be met for a society to have the rule of law:

  1. 1.

    Every use of coercive force in that society is governed by rules (i.e. not a command).

  2. 2.

    The rules governing the use of coercive force in that society must be effective and reliable (i.e. there must be a high degree of probability that it will be observed and this probability must be robust).

  3. 3.

    It must be common knowledge in that society both (a) what rules govern the use of coercive force, and (b) that those rules are effective and reliable (i.e. the rules must be published, sufficiently clear and reasonably stable).Footnote 25

Lovett’s proceduralism has been criticised in the context of discriminatory laws and regulations (apartheid regimes, discriminatory admission policies)Footnote 26 and, most relevant for the topic of this paper, in the context of ‘total institutions’. These critiques have in common that Lovett’s procedural account of arbitrariness does not prevent situations of ‘rule-bound domination’,Footnote 27 where the rules themselves are a source of domination. Drawing on Goffman’s definition of total institutions, according to which total institutions are closed to the outside world, where every sphere of the inmates’ lives is highly regimented and homogenised, Lazar for example stresses that such institutions need not be arbitrary in the procedural sense. Such institutions can be governed in conformity with the conditions for the rule of law as provided by Lovett. Nevertheless, it is common knowledge that such institutions causes its residences ‘radical and intolerable levels of anxiety and stress, a degradation of self and of agency’, which is a similar bundle of psychological effects as present in paradigm cases of domination, such as slavery. Lazar concludes for this reason that wholly procedural accounts of arbitrariness should be rejected.Footnote 28 In the same vein, Arnold and Harris argue that a procedural account would prefer, for example, an university admission policy that clearly stipulates that all minority students should be rejected over an admission policy where administrators have discretion whether to expel students. They conclude as well that, with such ‘absurd results’, proceduralism should be rejected.Footnote 29

Lovett responds to this criticism in his more recent work, albeit not directly. He explains that in his conceptualization, the rule of law should not be understood as a virtue of legal systems, but rather as a virtue of social orderings: ‘societies enjoy the rule of law to the extent that all public and private uses of coercive force are managed through the mode of law’.Footnote 30 This means that the law must do more than merely ‘grant a stamp of legal approval’ to the use of coercive force. It must ‘articulate a set of impersonal public rules such that, provided people undertake a reasonable effort to follow those rules, they will not ordinarily be subjected to violence or physical restraint at the hands of others’.Footnote 31 In other words, discretionary use of coercive force should be reduced; merely approving it by law is not enough. In this way, a discriminatory admission policy or an apartheid or slave law regime does not meet these criteria, as it merely authorizes the use of coercive force, it does not ensure that people can avoid being subjected to violence or physical restraint by following the rules.Footnote 32

This begs the question, however, whether all situations in which observing a rule implies subjecting oneself to coercive force i.e. where observing a rule involves considerable physical restraint, cannot be reconciled with the rule of law. This would be rather far-stretching as following a rule often involves some kind of restraint. This resembles the second kind of critique of Arnold and Harris, who argue that proceduralism is also excessively demanding in requiring that every kind of discretion should be banned.Footnote 33

Again, in his more recent work Lovett provides a response to this criticism, by distinguishing between different sorts of discretion and stressing that not every kind of discretion is in violation with the idea of the rule of law. Under certain conditions, ‘rule-implementing discretion’, i.e. the discretionary judgement that is necessary to apply any given rule to a particular situation,Footnote 34 can be reconciled with the rule of law. This is, however, not true for cases of ‘strong discretion’, where constraints are absent altogether, and for ‘accountability discretion’. To prevent accountability discretion, Lovett stresses the need for accountability mechanisms for rule makers.Footnote 35 He does, however, not elaborately conceptualize such accountability mechanisms. On this point, I believe that Benton’s theory is relevant, as she deals with accountability mechanisms much more elaborately. She provides an alternative model of arbitrariness, entirely based on accountability instead of control. She defines arbitrary power as unaccountable power and proposes to identify accountability gaps. These exist, according to Benton:

where there are insufficient checking mechanisms which require that:

  • state power is justified to all subjects of the power (justification);

  • subjects of the power are able to complain if their interests are not being met (contestation); and

  • power-holders are duly punished if they fail to track the interests of power-subjects (retribution).Footnote 36

Benton stresses the limited and mostly procedural nature of these requirements. Accountability mechanisms should be seen, in her view, as ‘systematic questions asked of the exercise of power’. She argues that it is the existence of the questions rather than a positive answer to them that makes power non-arbitrary.Footnote 37

In my view, Benton’s theory does not depart that far from Lovett’s theory on the rule of law. Lovett stresses the need for accountability mechanisms for rule-makers (legislators, administrative agencies and judges) as well and argues that ‘accountability discretion’ (cf. Benton’s accountability gaps) cannot be reconciled with the rule of law. However, Benton’s conceptualization of accountability mechanisms is more demanding then Lovett’s definition. Lovett does not require accountability mechanisms to justify the use of power or to include possibilities to contest but limits it to requiring the punishment of rule-makers for not following public and orderly procedures that define and limit the scope of the legislative authority.Footnote 38

In this way, Benton’s concept of unaccountable power serves as a relevant addition to Lovett’s theory that can help meet the critique that his theory covers not enough (e.g. apartheid, discriminatory admission policies) and, at the same time, covers too much (every kind of discretionary use of (coercive) power). The next section will discuss Benton’s definition of accountability mechanisms in more detail.

2.2 Protection Against Dependence on Unaccountable Power: Judicial Control

The foregoing section showed that accountability mechanisms should ensure that the rules are justified to the subjects of the coercive power; that there are means to contest the rules; and that there is a possibility to impose a sanction on the rule-makers for not following the correct procedures for law-making or for failing to track the interests of power subjects.

Contestation requires, as Benton argues, that accountability is at least to some extent self-initiated or self-controlled; external checking mechanisms are not enough. The importance and need of this element of ‘voice’ increases to the extent that exit from the power of the state becomes prohibitively costly or infeasible.Footnote 39 By emphasizing the relevance of the possibility to exit the power of the state, Benton refers to Lovett’s theory on domination.Footnote 40 According to Lovett, domination should be understood structurally: it must as a minimum include some level of dependency of a person or group on the power-holder. The level of dependency should be measured by taking into account the ‘net expected costs (i.e. expected costs less any expected gains) of exiting, or attempting to exit, a social relationship’.Footnote 41 Lovett stresses that the concept of ‘exit costs’ should be understood broadly; it is not limited to material costs, instead, exit costs are often to some extent psychological and thus subjective.Footnote 42 For Lovett, joined by Benton, dependency is a necessary condition for domination and the greater the dependency of the subjected person is, the more severe the domination will be.

Accountability mechanisms can have many forms. Benton mentions regular and open elections and a free press as examples of mechanisms that can help ensure justification and retribution.Footnote 43 Even for migrants, who do not have the right to vote, such political accountability mechanisms will help to slightly reduce the accountability gap, since representatives might have good reasons to track their interests, as potential future voters, or the interests of their family or community members who can vote.Footnote 44 However, in order to ensure the possibility to contest, which should be to some extent self-initiated, other mechanisms are necessary. Benton mentions diplomatic protection and human rights courts as examples of such mechanisms.Footnote 45

Given the limits of diplomatic protection,Footnote 46 I would argue that for ensuring self-initiated possibilities to contest, legal accountability mechanisms, in other words judicial control, are necessary. Even though Benton does not elaborately discuss judicial control as an important accountability mechanism, I believe judicial control fits her emphasis on the importance of asking systematic questions of the exercise of power very well.Footnote 47 As Kumm has argued, human rights or constitutional courts often employ a proportionality test. In that process, courts do not primarily interpret authority, but they ask questions and asses the coherence of the arguments and the answers that the parties provide.Footnote 48

A right to contest coercive rules can be further operationalized by making a distinction between two aspects: (1) subjects of such rules should have access to legal remedies and (2) there should be legal grounds on the basis of which the rules can be contested, which constrain the discretion of the rule-makers. For this latter aspect, the idea of ‘duality of law’, as emphasized by Palombella as a fundamental element of the rule of law, is relevant.

2.3 Duality of Law

Palombella discusses the normative meaning of the rule of law by tracing it back to its (mainly English) origins and contrasting it with the continental concept of the Rechtsstaat. The original concept of the Rechtsstaat, he argues, simply meant that law is the structure of the state, not an external limitation to it. In the Rechtsstaat, with its strong emphasis on legality, ‘[l]aw turns out to be the authentic voice of the State, through which it expresses its own will: it is not the constraint but rather the “form” of the State’s will’Footnote 49 In contrast, under the rule of law, the state is subordinated to an autonomous law that is not entirely its own. Palombella clearly summarizes this distinction by stating that ‘while the Rechtsstaat or l’Etat de droit defeated the ultimate absolute power of the King, because it was the King’s, the rule of law defeated it because it was absolute’.Footnote 50

The rule of law depends, according to Palombella, on a ‘foundational balance’ between gubernaculum and jurisdictio. Gubernaculum is the legitimate sovereign law, at the disposal of the powerful ruler, embracing instrumental aims and government policies, whereas jurisdictio, ‘the fundamental law of the land’, is a law otherwise developed, that the ruler cannot change at his will.Footnote 51 This other, autonomous law should be located somehow outside the purview of the government, be it granted by the long standing tradition of common law or customary law as reflected in case law or by the creation of a constitutional higher law or convention.Footnote 52 It is not a static law, instead, jurisdiction is a ‘complex and collective construct, made by many hands, trough the wisdom of decades or centuries, and, therefore, itself artificial’.Footnote 53 The rule of law ideal requires respect for and protection of the opposition between these two sides of the law.Footnote 54

For Palombella, legality is a necessary but insufficient element of the rule of law. At the same time, he stresses that the rule of law cannot be conflated with the rule of ‘good law’. Instead, the rule of law requires protection of social normativity from being monopolized by one legal source. In other words, the law should not be dictated by an unconstrained choice made by the will of the rulers and reflect exclusively one conception of the ‘good’; it should be contrasted and weighed against a legally separate and independent defense of the ‘right’.Footnote 55

In short, the rule of law, as argued by Palombella, is about the non-monopolization of legal sources and the safeguard of the tension between the legitimate sovereign law and a law otherwise developed.Footnote 56 Palombella links this conceptualization of the rule of law with the ideal of non-domination. When the rule of law is embedded in the equilibrium of the relation between jurisdictio and gubernaculum, non-arbitrariness on the part of the government obtains and in this situation, ‘the ideal of the rule of law can be described as a non-domination principle’.Footnote 57 By insisting on this requisite balance-relation, the rule of law ideal prevents the law from ‘turning itself into a sheer tool of domination’,Footnote 58 as not even the democratic sovereign ‘should be allowed to be the ultimate, and thus discretionary, “master” of laws’.Footnote 59

2.4 Conclusion

Drawing on Lovett, Benton and Palombella, I suggest a particular conceptualization of the ideal of freedom as non-domination to evaluate coercive practises against irregular migrants. This conceptualization can be summarised as follows:

Domination is the situation in which a person is:

  • subjected to coercive rules;

  • from which s/he can only exit at high costs; and

  • that have no legal basis and/or cannot be contested in court on the basis of laws stemming from legal sources that are somehow independent from the sovereign power.

In other words: in order to prevent domination, the use of coercive force should be governed by sufficiently reliable and clear public rules. In addition, mechanisms should exist for holding rule-makers accountable. Such accountability mechanisms should at least to some extent be self-initiated or self-controlled. The less possibilities there are to exit the power of the rule-maker, the more important this element of ‘voice’ is. Judicial control is an important way to ensure a self-initiated possibility to contest coercive rules. For that reason, access to a remedy should be available, as well as grounds of contestation, stemming from jurisdictio, i.e. a legal source that is not primarily developed by the sovereign power.

The next section will apply this normative framework to coercive practices in shelters for irregular migrants in the Netherlands in order to demonstrate the practical relevance and consequences of the theory.

3 The Rule of Law and Family Shelters in the Netherlands

3.1 Background

In 1998, the Dutch ‘Linkage Act’Footnote 60 entered into force. This act ‘linked’ migrants’ legal status to their entitlement to governmental benefits. Migrants without any kind of legal status or temporary permission to stay were excluded from all state-funded benefits, with the exception of public health and emergency medical care, education for minors and legal aid. The new Aliens Act of 2000 introduced the automatic loss of shelter, four weeks after the final rejection of an asylum application. As a result, rejected asylum seekers were put on the street if they lost their appeal against the rejection of their application, irrespective of whether the authorities were able to actually deport them. In 2007, an exception was created to this full exclusion, for migrants who were about to be expelled and who cooperated with their return procedure. They received shelter in a so-called ‘freedom restricting location’ (vrijheidsbeperkende locatie, VBL) for a maximum of 12 weeks.Footnote 61

In 2012, the Dutch Supreme Court (Hoge Raad) made an end to this (almost) full exclusion from state-funded shelter for migrants with minor children. The case was about a single mother with three minor children who stayed in a VBL. They received shelter under the condition of cooperating in their return to Angola. When the mother refused to cooperate, the authorities wanted to evict the family from the VBL. The lawsuit was about the question whether this eviction was lawful. The Court of Appeal of the Hague ruled in 2011 that this eviction was unlawfulFootnote 62 and the Hoge Raad upheld this judgment.Footnote 63

In response to these judgments, the Dutch government set up special family shelters (gezinslocaties) in remote places where families with minor children would be housed until the youngest child turns 18. The decision to accommodate these migrants in family locations was announced in a letter to parliament.Footnote 64 The provision of this shelter does not have a basis in Dutch law; there is no Act that provides for the possibility of providing shelter to migrants without legal residence.Footnote 65 On the contrary; it is in clear violation with the Linkage act of 1998 to do so. The absence of a legal basis for the provision of shelter in the family locations has been confirmed by the Council of State.Footnote 66 This means that the authorities have a significant amount of discretion. There is no law that defines and limits the scope of the authorities’ power or indicates the aims or goals it is meant to serve.

Yet, in addition to and connected with providing shelter and basic living conditions, the authorities apply measures containing different degrees of coercion to migrants living in family locations. Migrants who are accommodated in family locations are subjected to forced transfersFootnote 67 and to a ‘freedom restricting measure’. This measure, based on the Aliens Act 2000,Footnote 68 implies that they cannot leave the territory of the municipality in which the family location is established. In addition, they have a weekly reporting obligation with the Aliens policeFootnote 69 and a daily reporting obligation (inhuisregistratie) with the authorities of the shelter. In this way, the legal recognition of migrants’ deservingness of shelter resulted in a bordering practise involving significant state coercion, surveillance and control.

3.2 Daily Reporting Obligation

Migrants living in family locations have to report themselves daily at noon. For children attending school, an exception can be granted. In response to a lot of criticism from NGO’s, the reporting duty was revoked for Sundays and public holidays,Footnote 70 and the intention was announced to move the reporting duty on Saturdays towards the end of the afternoon.Footnote 71 In a letter to parliament, the minister justified the daily reporting obligation by stressing the need for the authorities of the shelter to establish the families’ presence in the shelter, which ensures their availability for the return procedure. Their presence in the shelter is not only important for organizing formal ‘return meetings’, but also to ‘stay informally in touch with the families’.Footnote 72

The daily duty to report with the authorities of the shelter has not been laid down in any kind of law or regulation, nor are the consequences of failing to report. This has been confirmed by the Council of State.Footnote 73

In response to a freedom of information request by journalists about violent situations in asylum seekers’ centres, the organization that is managing the family locations, the COA, published an internal regulation about dealing with incidents and sanctions in family locations at its website (Regeling afhandelen incidenten en maatregelen gezinslocaties).Footnote 74 From this internal regulation, it appears that if a migrant does not meet his/her daily reporting obligation, this results in an official warning, the second time in a deduction of the weekly financial benefit and the third time in a deduction of the weekly financial benefit ánd a notification to the Aliens police. The Aliens police can decide, on the basis of such an ‘incident’, that there are sufficient grounds to detain the family, in order to prevent the family from absconding.Footnote 75 Accordingly, the enforcement of the daily reporting obligation has a strong coercive character; violation of the obligation has serious consequences for the migrants.Footnote 76

The absence of a legal basis for this coercive measure constitutes, in itself, a situation of domination. A basic condition for the rule of law, and for preventing domination, is that every use of coercive force is governed by the law, as has been discussed in Sect. 2 above. The absence of a legal basis for the daily reporting obligation is not just a matter of ‘rule-implementing discretion’Footnote 77 or, in other words, ‘bureaucratic discretion’,Footnote 78 that is widespread and unavoidable in any legal system. Instead, it reflects a situation of ‘strong discretion’, where controlling rules are simply absent altogether, which is one of the two forms of discretion that cannot be reconciled with the rule of law, according to Lovett.

If this would be fixed, and a legal basis would be created for the daily reporting obligation, this would not, however, necessarily mean that domination would henceforth be absent. As has been discussed in Sect. 2 above, merely authorizing the use of force is not enough to prevent domination; it should also be assessed whether sufficient accountability mechanisms are available to prevent accountability discretion. Such accountability mechanisms should at least to some extent be self-initiated or self-controlled. The less possibilities there are for migrants to exit, the more important this element of ‘voice’ is. Consequently, for establishing the degree of domination to which migrants living in family locations are subjected, the remainder of this section will analyse:

  • options for migrant families without legal residence to exit the power of the state to which they are subjected in family locations (i.e. their level of dependency);

  • whether there are legal mechanisms to contest the measures (i.e. whether there are legal remedies available); and

  • the grounds that can be invoked to contest the measures (i.e. whether there are legal grounds stemming from autonomous legal sources, that are not primarily developed by the sovereign power that constrain the discretion of the authorities).

3.3 Exit Options

Migrant families without legal residence have three routes to leave the coercive power to which they are subjected in family locations: (1) leave the country altogether; (2) regularize their status and, for that reason, become eligible for other kind of state benefits; or (3) reject or leave the family locations and fend for themselves.

Benton has convincingly argued that the exit costs for leaving a country of residence depend on both the viability of a life elsewhere and the relative costs of leaving, which, on their part, depend on factors such as the economic and security situation in the country, existence of social ties, employment opportunities, skills, existence of debts to travel agencies or family members etc.Footnote 79 For this reason, it is safe to assume that at least for part of the families living in family locations, the (objective and/or subjective) costs of leaving the Netherlands are high.

With regard to the option of regularization, there are possibilities, both on individual grounds, such as asylum, family life or medical reasons, as on the basis of a general amnesty. However, difficulties of proving continued residence; the existence of a ‘genuine’ relationship; new circumstances with regard to their asylum account; or the existence of a medical emergency; can hamper regularization options. Additionally, the existence of a criminal record or the absence of any identity documents can stand in the way. Hence, also for this exit route, it is safe to assume that it is not available for all migrants living in the state’s family locations.

Since migrants without legal residence are not eligible for any kind of state-funded shelter or other kind of basic needs, the third exit route is not really a viable option either. As the Hoge Raad has stressed in its judgment, state-funded shelter is necessary for these families in order to prevent a humanitarian emergency. For migrants who do not have a strong social network in the Netherlands, living in these family locations is the only way to ensure basic needs for their children.

Due to these different constraints, for many migrants living in family locations, exit from the power of the state in the locations is only possible at high cost. In order to prevent situations of domination, it is, therefore, important that migrants living in family locations are able to hold the authorities accountable for their use of discretionary power.

3.4 Possibilities to Contest

The fact that the daily reporting obligation has no legal basis, would normally entail that no administrative legal protection is available, as there is no formal administrative ‘decision’. However, with regard to migrants, an exception exists. Article 72(3) of the Aliens Act 2000 provides that an act of the administrative authority in respect of a person in his capacity of alien should be equated with a formal administrative decision for the purposes of legal protection.

Districts courts have ruled differently as regards the question whether the daily reporting obligation for migrants in family locations qualifies as such an act and should, therefore, be equated with an administrative decision for the purposes of legal protection. The District Court of Amsterdam ruled that the parliamentary history of Article 72(3) of the Aliens Act 2000 shows that an act should be based on the Aliens Act in order to be equated with an administrative decision. Since the daily reporting obligation is not based on the Aliens Act 2000, it could not be equated with an administrative decision according to the District Court of Amsterdam.Footnote 80 The District Court of the Hague held as well that the daily reporting obligation cannot be equated with an administrative decision on the basis of Article 72(3) of the Aliens Act 2000.Footnote 81 A year later, however, that Court arrived at the opposite conclusion, and ruled that the application of the daily reporting obligation is an act concerning a person in his capacity as an alien, regardless of the absence of a basis in the Aliens Act, and should, therefore, be equated with an administrative decision.Footnote 82 The Council of State, ultimately, ruled that the daily reporting obligation can be equated with an administrative decision on the basis of Article 72(3), since the purpose of this rule is to entrust all legal protection of migrants to administrative judges.Footnote 83

This means that even though this was not entirely clear from the start, there is a legal option to contest the daily reporting obligation, or the refusal to exempt a person from this obligation. Similar to regular administrative decisions, in order to contest acts that are equated with an administrative decision, a formal objection should be lodged to the secretary of state. If this formal objection is declared unfounded by the secretary of state, it is possible to lodge an appeal against this decision with a District Court and a higher appeal with the Council of State.Footnote 84

3.5 Grounds of Contestation

The possibility of contesting an act of the authorities is only effective if there are grounds on which the act can be contested and the authorities can be held accountable for their actions. In line with the fundamental ‘duality of law’, as discussed in Sect. 2, it is important that these grounds stem from other legal sources, not primarily developed by the sovereign power. The Dutch constitution does not contain a right to freedom of movement or to choose a place of residence. This section will, therefore, analyse to what extent other rules i.e. human rights law, European Union law and/or general principles of law, constrain the rule-makers’ discretion.

Both the European Convention of Human Rights (ECHR) and the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR) contain the right to freedom of movement and the freedom to choose a residence.Footnote 85 The scope of these provisions is, however, limited to persons ‘lawfully within the territory of a state’. The European Court on Human Rights (ECtHR) has ruled that the phrase ‘lawfully within the territory’ refers to the domestic law of the State concerned:

‘It is for the domestic law and organs to lay down the conditions which must be fulfilled for a person's presence in the territory to be considered “lawful”Footnote 86

In addition, the Court held that migrants can only be regarded as “lawfully” in the territory as long as they comply with the conditions to which their admission and stay are subjected. In Omwenyeke, an asylum seeker complained that the obligation imposed on him to reside within an assigned district was in violation of his right to freedom of movement. The Court, however, merely noted that his provisional authorization to stay in Germany was conditional on his stay in the assigned district. Since he had left that district without permission, he was not ‘lawfully within the territory’, and Article 2 of Protocol 4 did not apply. This means that the Court did not scrutinize the residence restriction as such, but used it to stress the limited personal scope of the right to freedom of movement.

The families living in the Dutch family locations do not have authorization to take up residence in the Netherlands; nor do the majority have provisional authorization to stay on the territory. For this reason, the right to freedom of movement as laid down in the ECHR and ICCPR is inapplicable and, accordingly, does not constrain the authorities’ discretion.

The same is true with regard to other human rights. In Omwenyeke, the asylum seeker also complained that the residence restriction violated his right to respect for his private life but this complaint was declared manifestly ill-founded by the Court, without any further deliberation.Footnote 87 In addition, a residence restriction or a daily reporting obligation is unlikely to reach the threshold of inhuman and degrading treatment, which is forbidden under Article 3 ECHR and 7 ICCPR. In Hunde v. the Netherlands, a rejected asylum seeker complained about his poor living conditions in the light of Article 3 ECHR. The Court, in holding the complaint manifestly ill-founded, noted inter alia that the applicant had ‘the possibility to seek admission to a centre where his liberty would be restricted’.Footnote 88 Apparently, accommodation under the condition of liberty restriction is a way to prevent inhuman or degrading treatment, and does not constitute such treatment itself.

In EU law, the relevant instrument is the EU Returns Directive,Footnote 89 since the migrants living in family locations are, generally, subjected to an obligation to return to their country of origin. The Returns Directive allows Member States to impose obligations to ‘regular reporting to the authorities’ and ‘to stay at a certain place’ during the period for voluntary return, that Member States have to grant to illegally staying migrants when they issue a return decision.Footnote 90 The purpose of imposing such an obligation is to avoid the risk of absconding. This obligation may also be imposed during the time that the removal of the migrant concerned is postponed.Footnote 91 No futher conditions or procedural safeguards apply with regard to the issuance of these obligations.Footnote 92 The Return Directive, therefore, does not constrain the ability of Dutch authorities to impose a daily reporting obligation on the families living in family locations. Moreover, EU law allows member states to use such residence obligations and reporting obligations as a pathway to detention. The Returns Directive allows for detention if there is a ‘risk of absconding’.Footnote 93 The Returns Directive defines ‘risk of absconding’ as ‘the existence of reasons in an individual case which are based on objective criteria defined by law to believe that a third-country national who is the subject of return procedures may abscond’.Footnote 94 This means that it is up to Member States to lay down objective criteria in their national legislation for establishing whether a risk of absconding exists. In a case about the meaning of the term ‘absconding’ in the Dublin Regulation, the Court of Justice held that, ‘in order to ensure the effective functioning of the Dublin system and the achievement of its objectives,’ the authorities do not have to prove that the migrant concerned deliberately evades the reach of those authorities, as this would cause the authorities considerable difficulties.Footnote 95 Accordingly, non-compliance with a reporting obligation can be used by Member States as a criteria for establishing a ‘risk of absconding’, which is a ground for detention. This means that EU law not only allows member states to impose reporting obligations on unlawfully residing migrants, but also allows member states to use a significant degree of coercion in order to secure compliance.

The EU Charter on Fundamental Rights does not constrain member states any further in this regard, since freedom of movement only applies to EU citizens and ‘may be granted’ to nationals of third countries ‘legally resident in the territory of a Member State’.Footnote 96

Since international human rights law and EU law are inapplicable or do not constrain the authorities, the only grounds for contestation are general legal principles. Indeed, in the scarce Dutch case law about the daily reporting obligation, migrants merely rely on general principles of administrative law, such as proportionality and justice. Since these principles do not originate from specific norms, tailored to the issue of restrictions on freedom of movement, judges only cursorily examine such arguments.

In a case from 2012, residents of the family location in Katwijk claimed that the reporting obligation should be changed from a daily one to a weekly one. The district court of the Hague merely held:

‘in itself it is understandable that the duty to report is experienced as difficult, but [since the reasons for imposing this duty appear to be reasonable and justified], this is insufficient for qualifying the duty as unlawful’. Footnote 97

In a 2018 case, residents of the family location in Goes also claimed that the daily duty to report was too burdensome, and that a weekly reporting obligation would be more appropriate for their situation, since they are dependent on the shelter in the family location and had, therefore, no intentions to abscond. The district court of Middelburg did not deal with this claim. The court merely referred to the discussion of the claim against the restrictions of the applicants freedom to the territory of the municipality of Goes, which does have a basis in Dutch law. The court just added to this that it is possible to request an exemption from the daily reporting obligation, for example to visit their lawyer.Footnote 98

There are no other (published) cases about the daily reporting obligation.

4 Conclusion

[T]he populations we are trying to describe, those who have become effectively stateless, are still under the control of state power. In this way, they are without legal protection but in no way relegated to a “bare life”: this is life steeped in power. And this reminds us, crucially, that power is not the same as law’Footnote 99

For migrants living in family locations in the Netherlands, the provision of basic needs is made conditional on their subjection to coercion: a daily reporting obligation. By imposing this obligation, the authorities are able to change what these migrants might otherwise prefer to do and have a significant impact on migrants’ ability to establish their daily structure, and, arguably, on their autonomy and dignity. This kind of social power is coercive as it is based on conditional threats: non-compliance with the daily reporting obligation has severe consequences for migrants (loss of money that is needed for meeting basic needs and a ground for detention). This Dutch practise fits in a European trend towards more coercive and restrictive inclusionary practises for irregular migrants.

This paper has provided a rule of law framework with which to analyse such practises. Authors like Lovett, Benton and Palombella have convincingly argued how the rule of law, in their conceptualization, is necessary to realize the neorepublican concept of freedom as non-domination. Non-domination, or the absence of mastery by others, is a primary good in neorepublican theory, that should be available to everyone. Drawing on their writings, this paper has conceptualized domination as the situation in which a person is subjected to coercive rules from which s/he can only exit at high costs and that have no legal basis and/or cannot be contested in court on the basis of laws stemming from legal sources that are somehow independent from the sovereign power. The second part of the paper applied this concept of domination to the daily reporting obligation imposed on migrants living in Dutch family locations. It demonstrated the relevance and consequences of this concept by identifying two fundamental rule of law problems.

First, this paper revealed that the daily reporting obligation has no legal basis in Dutch law. This means that the power of the authorities is not constrained specifically by Dutch law i.e. by laying down exceptions, time limits etc. The authorities have full discretion in subjecting migrants to reporting obligations; they can establish the frequency, the time slot, and can exempt migrants from the obligation at will. Since migrants are highly dependent on shelter in these family locations, as exit options only exceptionally exist, this absence of a legal basis, a case of ‘strong discretion’, creates for most of these migrants a situation of sheer domination.

Even if, however, an adequate legal basis would be created for the daily reporting obligation, this would not prevent situations of domination. This paper has shown that for preventing domination, mere legality is not enough. In line with Lazar’s and Palombella’s argumentation, it should also be avoided that the rules themselves turn into a tool of domination, a mere instrument to legitimize (concentrations of) power. This paper has argued, drawing mainly on Benton and Palombella, that in order to prevent domination, it is also necessary that rule-makers can be held accountable for their use of coercion. Especially if exit options are scarce or non-existent, this means, as I have argued, that people should be able to contest the adoption and application of coercive rules before a judge, based on legal grounds that stem from sources sufficiently independent from the sovereign power.

The second problem identified in this paper is that relevant standards of human rights law and of EU law are either inapplicable, or do not constrain the authorities in any meaningful way. This means that the only grounds for contestation that migrants living in family locations can invoke are general principles of EU law or Dutch administrative law, such as the proportionality principle. The limited Dutch case law available shows that judges only briefly and superficially deal with such claims.

However, in the absence of applicable constitutional or human rights norms, domination can only be prevented if some other law is available that does not stem from gubernaculum, from the legitimate sovereign law, but from jurisdictio, a law otherwise developed. From a rule of law perspective, judges should protect the opposition of these two sides of the law, in order to prevent the law from becoming a sheer instrument of the preferences of the sovereign power. Instead of waving away arguments based on the principle of proportionality, this would, for example, mean that judges use this principle as a real counterbalance to the gubernaculum side of the law, by asking questions and critically examining the justification, on an individual basis, for the use of coercive power in the family locations. Even though this would not necessarily mean that migrants cannot be subjected anymore to reporting obligations, it would ensure more procedural justice and could imply some constraints on the sovereign power, e.g. as regards time limits, frequency and exceptions to the daily reporting obligation.

This Dutch example shows how the protection of freedom as non-domination, conceptualized from a rule of law perspective, sets more demanding criteria for the (courts of) law than the protection of human rights. At the same time, it does not require non-interference or elaborate positive obligations from the state. This framework does not ensure irregular migrants’ freedom as self-mastery (for which access to legal residence and/or economic independence would, arguably, be required) but it does ensure their fundamental freedom in terms of absence of mastery by others. While this paper has applied this framework to spatial restrictions imposed on irregular migrants, it is relevant for the evaluation of other coercive practises for irregular migrants as well, such as the forced collection of biometric dataFootnote 100 or seizure of digital devicesFootnote 101. For irregular migrants, who do not have the right to reside in the territory, but who are entirely under the control of state power, non-domination as conceptualized in this paper provides, in my view, a necessary framework of review for such coercive practises, that ensures a kind of protection that is currently lacking.