Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-m9kch Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-06T08:19:54.627Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

HUME’S PRINCIPLE, BAD COMPANY, AND THE AXIOM OF CHOICE

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 April 2022

SAM ROBERTS*
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF KONSTANZ KONSTANZ 78457, GERMANY
STEWART SHAPIRO
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY THE OHIO STATE UNIVERSITY COLUMBUS, OH 43210 E-mail: shapiro.4@osu.edu

Abstract

One prominent criticism of the abstractionist program is the so-called Bad Company objection. The complaint is that abstraction principles cannot in general be a legitimate way to introduce mathematical theories, since some of them are inconsistent. The most notorious example, of course, is Frege’s Basic Law V. A common response to the objection suggests that an abstraction principle can be used to legitimately introduce a mathematical theory precisely when it is stable: when it can be made true on all sufficiently large domains. In this paper, we raise a worry for this response to the Bad Company objection. We argue, perhaps surprisingly, that it requires very strong assumptions about the range of the second-order quantifiers; assumptions that the abstractionist should reject.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Boolos, G. (1984). To be is to be a value of a variable (or to be some values of some variables). Journal of Philosophy, 81, 5472; reprinted in [5].Google Scholar
Boolos, G. (1985). Nominalist platonism. Philosophical Review, 94, 327344; reprinted in [5], pp. 73–87.Google Scholar
Boolos, G. (1987). The consistency of Frege’s foundations of arithmetic. In Thompson, J. J., editor. On Being and Saying: Essays for Richard Cartwright. Cambridge: MIT Press, pp. 320; reprinted in [5], pp. 54–72.Google Scholar
Boolos, G. (1997). Is Hume’s principle analytic?. In Heck, R. Jr, editor. Language, Thought, and Logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 245261; reprinted in [5], 301–314.Google Scholar
Boolos, G. (1998). Logic, Logic, and Logic. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Burgess, J. P. (1984). Review of Crispin Wright’s Frege’s conception of numbers as objects. The Philosophical Review, 93, 638640.Google Scholar
Dummett, M. (1991). Frege: Philosophy of Mathematics . Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Dummett, M. (1998). Neo-Fregeans: In bad company?. In Schirn, M., editor. The Philosophy of Mathematics Today. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 369387.Google Scholar
Ebert, P. and Shapiro, S. (2009). The good, the bad, and the ugly. Synthese, 170, 415441.Google Scholar
Feferman, S. (2006). Predicativity. In Shapiro, S., editor. The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 590624.Google Scholar
Fine, K. (2002). The Limits of Abstraction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Florio, S. and Linnebo, Ø. (2020). Critical plural logic. Philosophia Mathematica, 28, 172203.Google Scholar
Frege, G. (1884). Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik. Breslau: Koebner; translated by Austin, J. (1960). The Foundations of Arithmetic (second edition). New York: Harper.Google Scholar
Frege, G. (1893). Grundgesetze der Arithmetik 1. Olms: Hildescheim; translated by Ebert, P. A. and Rossberg, M. (2013). Basic Laws of Arithmetic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fritz, P. and Goodman, J. (2017). Counting incompossibles. Mind, 126, 10631108.Google Scholar
Hale, B. (1987). Abstract Objects. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hale, B. (2000). Abstraction and set theory. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 41, 379398.Google Scholar
Hale, B. (2010). The bearable lightness of being. Axiomathes, 20, 399422.Google Scholar
Hale, B. (2013). Properties and the interpretation of second-order logic. Philosophia Mathematica (3), 21, 133156.Google Scholar
Hale, B. (2013). Necessary Beings: An Essay on Ontology, Modality, and the Relations Between Them. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hale, B. and Wright, C. (2001). The Reason’s Proper Study. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Heck, R. (1992). On the consistency of second-order contextual definitions. Nous, 26, 491494.Google Scholar
Landman, F. (1989). Groups I. Linguistics and Philosophy, 12, 559605; Groups II. Linguistics and Philosophy, 12, 723–744.Google Scholar
Lévy, A. (1969). The definability of cardinal numbers. In Bulloff, J. J., Holyoke, T. C., and Hahn, S. W., editors. Foundations of Mathematics: Symposium Papers Commemorating the Sixtieth Birthday of Kurt Gödel. Berlin, Spring, pp. 1538.Google Scholar
Linnebo, Ø. (2004). Predicative fragments of Frege arithmetic. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 10, 153174.Google Scholar
Linnebo, Ø. (2009). Introduction. Special issue devoted to the bad company issue. Synthese, 170, 321329.Google Scholar
Linnebo, Ø. (2010). Pluralities and sets. Journal of Philosophy, 107, 144164.Google Scholar
Maddy, P. (1983). Proper classes. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 48, 113139.Google Scholar
Maddy, P. (2007). Second Philosophy: A Naturalistic Method. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Moore, G. H. (1982). Zermelo’s Axiom of Choice: Its Origins, Development, and Influence. New York: Springer.Google Scholar
Poincaré, H. (1906). Les mathématiques et la logique. Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale, 14, 294317.Google Scholar
Priest, G. (2006). In Contradiction: A Study of the Transconsistent (second revised edition). Oxford, Oxford University Press; (first edition). Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhofs, 1987.Google Scholar
Rayo, A. and Yablo, S. (2001). Nominalism through de-nominalization. Noûs, 35, 7492.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Resnik, M. (1988). Second-order logic still wild. Journal of Philosophy, 85, 7587.Google Scholar
Roberts, S. Reflection principles: A survey, forthcoming.Google Scholar
Roberts, S. Pluralities as nothing over and above. Journal of Philosophy, forthcoming.Google Scholar
Shapiro, S. (1991). Foundations Without Foundationalism: A Case for Second-order Logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Shapiro, S. (2000). Frege meets Dedekind: A neo-logicist treatment of real analysis. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 41, 335364.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapiro, S. (2003). Prolegomenon to any future neo-logicist set theory: Abstraction and indefinite extensibility. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 54, 5991.Google Scholar
Shapiro, S. (2018). Properties and predicates, objects and names: Impredicativity and the axiom of choice. In Fred-Rivera, I. and Leech, J., editors. Being Necessary: Themes of Ontology and Modality from the Work of Bob Hale. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 92110.Google Scholar
Tennant, N. (1987). Anti-Realism and Logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Uzquiano, G. (2009). Bad company generalized. Synthese, 170, 331347.Google Scholar
Walsh, S. (2012). Comparing Peano arithmetic, Basic Law V, and Hume’s principle. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 163, 16791709.Google Scholar
Weir, A. (1998). Naïve set theory is innocent. Mind, 107, 763798.Google Scholar
Weir, A. (2003). Neo-Fregeanism: An embarrassment of riches. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 44, 1348.Google Scholar
Weyl, H. (1918). Das Kontinuum. Leipzig: Verlag von Veit; translated by Pollard, S. and Bole, T. (1994) as The Continuum. Dover.Google Scholar
Whitehead, A. N. and Russell, B. (1910). Principia Mathematica, Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. (2013). Everything. Philosophical Perspectives, 17, 415465.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. (2013). Modal Logic as Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wright, C. (1983). Frege’s Conception of Numbers as Objects. Aberdeen: Aberdeen University Press.Google Scholar
Wright, C. (1997). On the philosophical significance of Frege’s theorem. In Heck, Jr., R., editor. Language, Thought, and Logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 201244; reprinted in Hale and Wright (2001), pp. 272–306.Google Scholar
Wright, C. (2004). Warrant for nothing (and foundations for free). Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume, 78, 167212.Google Scholar