Skip to main content
Log in

Finding the force: How children discern possibility and necessity modals

  • Published:
Natural Language Semantics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper investigates when and how children figure out the force of modals: that possibility modals (e.g., can/might) express possibility, and necessity modals (e.g., must/have to) express necessity. Modals raise a classic subset problem: given that necessity entails possibility, what prevents learners from hypothesizing possibility meanings for necessity modals? Three solutions to such subset problems can be found in the literature: the first is for learners to rely on downward-entailing (DE) environments (Gualmini and Schwarz in J. Semant. 26(2):185–215, 2009); the second is a bias for strong (here, necessity) meanings; the third is for learners to rely on pragmatic cues stemming from the conversational context (Dieuleveut et al. in Proceedings of the 2019 Amsterdam colloqnium, pp. 111–122, 2019a; Rasin and Aravind in Nat. Lang. Semant. 29:339–375, 2020). This paper assesses the viability of each of these solutions by examining the modals used in speech to and by 2-year-old children, through a combination of corpus studies and experiments testing the guessability of modal force based on their context of use. Our results suggest that, given the way modals are used in speech to children, the first solution is not viable and the second is unnecessary. Instead, we argue that the conversational context in which modals occur is highly informative as to their force and sufficient, in principle, to sidestep the subset problem. Our child results further suggest an early mastery of possibility—but not necessity—modals and show no evidence for a necessity bias.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1a
Fig. 1b
Fig. 2
Fig. 3a
Fig. 3b
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7
Fig. 8
Fig. 9
Fig. 10

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In this paper, we put aside two other possibilities. First, children could learn force on the basis of explicit negative feedback: they would be corrected by adults when they produce necessity modals to describe mere possibilities. We leave a systematic investigation of whether children receive such feedback, but, anecdotally, we haven’t encountered any. In their study on every, Rasin and Aravind (2020) report only one case of explicit negative feedback out of 72 every uttered by children. Second, children could exploit the principle of contrast (Clark 1987) (e.g., knowing a possibility modal could lead children to hypothesize a necessity meaning for the next modal they encounter). However, as we discuss in Sect. 2.1, learners cannot expect two modals to necessarily express different forces, since several modals express the same force. If children heard necessity claims explicitly contrasted with possibility claims (e.g., “you can, but you don’t have to”), they could infer that the former expresses possibility, and the latter necessity, based on logical compatibility. While we did not systematically examine the transcripts for such cases, we did extract all cases where two modal claims were related by the logical connectives or, but, and and. We found only 85 such cases (out of 18,853 utterances). Among these, only three were possibly useful to figure out the force of possibility modals (e.g., “it might be in your box or it might be lost”), but we found no informative cases for necessity modals. This may be an underestimation, since we did not look for the occurrence of modals across different utterances. However, this very low frequency makes it unlikely that children can learn from such contrasts.

  2. Many variants of this idea can be found in the literature. The Subset Principle (Baker 1979; Berwick 1985; Dell 1981; Manzini and Wexler 1987; Pinker 1979, a.o.) was originally proposed for the acquisition of syntactic phenomena. Later on, the Semantic Subset Principle (SSP) was introduced by Crain and Thornton (1998) to account for semantic set/subset problems at the sentential level (see also Crain et al. 1994; Crain 2012).

  3. We were unaware of Rasin and Aravind’s methodology when we started this project with Dieuleveut et al. (2019a) and thus approached the problem for modals differently. We leave an application of Rasin and Aravind’s methodology to modals for future research, though we suspect that it might not always be easy to tell whether a possibility is already part of the common ground when a necessity statement is made, as all kinds of possibilities may be open at any given point in a conversation, even if they may not be salient.

  4. The difference between weak and strong necessity is illustrated in the following example: ‘Employees must wash their hands. Everyone else should’ (von Fintel and Iatridou 2008). Weak necessity modals are still treated as necessity modals, but quantify over a smaller domain than their strong counterparts.

  5. Logical entailment relations hold within flavor only: for example, epistemic necessity (e.g., ‘given what we know, he must be upstairs’) does not entail deontic possibility (e.g., ‘given the rules, he can be upstairs’). Horn scales are thus defined within a flavor. Because of flavor variability, this means that the same lexeme can appear in different scales. We leave aside debates about ability modals, often argued to have no necessity counterpart (Horn 1972; Hackl 1998) (e.g., ‘Jo can speak German; in fact, he has to’ leads to oddity, or forces a switch in flavor interpretation). It is also argued that ability modals do have duals, compulsion modals, but they are just extremely infrequent (e.g., ‘I have to sneeze’) (Mandelkern et al. 2015).

  6. Other analyses take variable modals to neither be underlying possibility nor necessity. Kratzer (2012) analyzes them as upper-end degree modals, roughly equivalent in meaning to ‘it is somewhat probable (/desirable) that p’.

  7. See, for example, Cinque’s (1999) hierarchy.

  8. Such considerations might explain why necessity but not possibility modals tend to be PPIs.

  9. This asymmetry has been attributed to conceptual and grammatical factors, but it might instead reflect a frequency asymmetry in the input. For how children learn that modals can be used to express various flavors, see van Dooren et al. (2017, 2022).

  10. We do not differentiate among subtypes of root flavors (ability, teleological, deontic, …).

  11. Results from another HSP study where participants had to fill in the blank (instead of making a forced choice) are reported in Dieuleveut et al. (2019b).

  12. An example of the experiment can be accessed at https://frm.pcibex.net/r/HDtxJP/.

  13. Accuracy for controls was very high (94.6%). There was no difference between groups in accuracy.

  14. We sometimes had to step back to random-intercepts-only models when the model failed to converge with the full random-effects specification.

  15. We used the same procedure (based on model comparisons) for all subsequent experiments reported in this paper, but don’t systematically report the reduced model.

  16. Answers were coded as 1 if the response was accurate, and 0 otherwise. Effect sizes (β), standard errors (SE), z-values, and p-values for the logistic models are reported in online Appendix C for Experiment 1 and all following analysis.

  17. Contexts involving interrogative sentences appeared almost exclusively in root-AFF-1 and root-AFF-2, as epistemic and negated modals are rare in interrogatives. Out of 80 contexts for root-AFF, there were 21 interrogative sentences (19 involving possibility modals; 2 involving necessity modals).

  18. This higher accuracy in possibility contexts might also reflect a general tendency to answer with possibility modals by default, maybe because of their relative frequency. To test for the effect of frequency, we compared accuracy for can and able-to (used in root-aff-2 and root-neg), which are both root possibility modals but strongly differ in frequency (3 able vs. 100 can in the Manchester corpus). The general accuracy on able was not significantly lower than on can (overall: able: 80.8% vs. can: 89.8% vs. have to: 71.7%).

  19. Few other corpus studies address the distribution of possibility and necessity modals with respect to negation, and fewer look at child-directed speech, but they also suggest that negated necessity modals are not frequent. De Haan (2011) reports that negation is very rare with must: 2.5% in the Brown corpus (written English) and 1.4% in the Switchboard corpus (spoken English). Thornton and Tesan (2013) report the frequencies of some negative auxiliary verbs in the input to children in the Providence corpus, but don’t specify their frequency relative to the positive forms. Jeretič (2018) reports that negation on necessity modals is infrequent in the input to French and Spanish children (French: 15.5%; Spanish: 6.2%).

  20. Horn focuses on a different but related problem, namely the fact that cross-linguistically, the ‘O’ corner of the Aristotelian square of opposition (corresponding to negated universals, e.g., non-necessity meanings) never seem to be lexicalized, whereas the other three corners (possibility, necessity, and impossibility) can be. Horn argues that this follows from the fact that there is no functional pressure to lexicalize non-necessity meanings: speakers already have a way to express non-necessity, using scalar implicatures.

  21. We thank an anonymous reviewer for pointing this issue out.

  22. Examples of the experiments can be accessed at https://farm.pcibex.net/r/sohaoF/ (Exp. 2) and https://farm.pcibex.net/r/ZbVcQT/ (Exp. 3).

  23. Accuracy on attention checks and tense controls was very high (attention checks: 99.4%; tense controls: 95.8%), with no difference between groups. To compute accuracy on tense controls, we only included sentences that could not lead to an ambiguity (e.g., because of containing a temporal adverb) (10 out of 20 cases).

  24. The fact that participants perform better than chance on possibility contexts in the Jabberwocky experiment might reflect a general tendency to answer with possibility modals when given a forced choice task—perhaps because of their higher frequency, see fn. 24. It may also be driven by their higher accuracy in interrogative sentences, as discussed in Sect. 3.2.3 (mean accuracy for possibility in interrogatives: Exp1: 98.1%; Exp2: 96.2%; Exp3: 76.1%; in declaratives: Exp1: 75.1%; Exp2: 65.8%; Exp3: 59.5%).

  25. This is not true stricto sensu, as participants also lose the information about the subject (e.g., I/you/Caroline…).

  26. An example of the experiment can be accessed at https://farm.pcibex.net/r/lrxZaB/.

  27. We sometimes had to step back to random-intercepts-only models when the model failed to converge with the full random-effects specification. We also checked that there was no significant difference between groups (root-aff-1 vs. root-aff-2) (Answer=1)∼Group+(1|Subject)+(1|Item). Results of the model comparison were not significant (\(\chi^{2}(1)=0.22\), p = 0.64).

  28. Similar distributional patterns (possibility modals being used more frequently than necessity modals and occurring frequently with negation) are found in Spanish and French (Jeretič 2018) and Dutch (van Dooren et al. 2022).

  29. An example of the experiment can be accessed at https://farm.pcibex.net/r/mYOcOz/.

  30. Because some of the negated have to in child productions were particularly unclear (e.g., ‘I can’t have to read it.’), we also used not gotta and not need. Details are provided in online Appendix B.

  31. Out of 148 contexts, 36 of them had the modal appear in the preceding dialogue (24.3%) (uttered by the child: 11; by the mother or another adult: 20; by both: 5).

  32. As a proxy, we checked that the mean length of dialogues was the same for adults and children (mean number of words for children’s contexts: 39.6 words/dialogue; for adults’ contexts: 38.9).

  33. For the adult version, the proportion of errors on controls was very low (5.4%), with no difference between groups. For the child version, however, the initial proportion of errors on controls was quite high (21.6%): post-hoc analysis revealed that this came from five control contexts for which the accuracy was particularly low, and thus were not reliable controls. We decided to remove these five controls from our exclusion criteria, as they were particularly difficult and probably do not indicate that subjects were not doing the task correctly. After restricting to the 15 remaining controls, mean accuracy on controls was 90.0%, showing that participants were not answering randomly.

  34. As pointed out by an anonymous reviewer, our results may also be consistent with theories of acquisition that use a necessity bias that is sensitive to input frequencies, along the lines of Piantadosi et al.’s (2012b) Bayesian learner (see also Piantadosi et al. 2012a). We intend to address this in future work.

  35. We do not have enough data from each child to see whether children’s adult-like uses of necessity modals correlate with frequency in their input (i.e., whether children who hear more necessity modals use them more appropriately), but we intend to pursue this question in future work. We thank an anonymous reviewer for this great suggestion. See Dieuleveut (2021) for preliminary results and discussion.

  36. For a similar investigation of what aspects of the input predict children’s understanding of think and know, see Dudley (2017).

References

  • Acredolo, Curt, and Karen Horobin. 1987. Development of relational reasoning and avoidance of premature closure. Developmental Psychology 23(1): 13–21. https://doi.org/10.1037/0012-1649.23.1.13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. L. 1975. How to do things with words. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van der Auwera, Johan. 2001. On the typology of negative modals. In Perspectives on negation and polarity items, eds. Jack Hoeksema, Hotze Rullmann, Víctor Sánchez-Valencia, and Ton van der Wouden, 23–48. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. https://doi.org/10.1075/la.40.03auw.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Baker, C. L. 1979. Syntactic theory and the projection problem. Linguistic Inquiry 10(4): 533–581. https://www.jstor.org/stable/4178133.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barner, David, and Asaf Bachrach. 2010. Inference and exact numerical representation in early language development. Cognitive Psychology 60(1): 40–62. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cogpsych.2009.06.002.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barner, David, Neon Brooks, and Alan Bale. 2011. Accessing the unsaid: The role of scalar alternatives in children’s pragmatic inference. Cognition 118(1): 84–93. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2010.10.010.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barr, Dale J., Roger Levy, Christoph Scheepers, and Harry J. Tily. 2013. Random effects structure for confirmatory hypothesis testing: Keep it maximal. Journal of Memory and Language 68(3): 255–278. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jml.2012.11.001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bates, Douglas, Martin Mächler, Ben Bolker, and Steve Walker. 2014. Fitting linear mixed-effects models using lme4. arXiv preprint arXiv:1406.5823.

  • Berwick, Robert C. 1985. The acquisition of syntactic knowledge. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bindra, Dalbir, Kenneth A. Clarke, and Thomas R. Shultz. 1980. Understanding predictive relations of necessity and sufficiency in formally equivalent “causal” and “logical” problems. JEP: General 109(4): 422–443. https://doi.org/10.1037/0096-3445.109.4.422.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bochnak, M. Ryan. 2015. Underspecified modality in Washo. In Proceedings of the eighteenth and nineteenth workshop on structure and constituency in the languages of the Americas, eds. Natalie Weber and Sihwei Chen, 3–17. Vancouver: UBCWPL.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brockmann, Saskia, Sara McConnell, Valentine Hacquard, and Jeffrey Lidz. 2018. Children’s comprehension of pronouns and definites. In Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 22, eds. Uli Sauerland and Stephanie Solt, 259–276. Berlin: ZAS.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, Penelope, and Stephen C. Levinson. 1987. Politeness: Some universals in language usage. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Byrnes, James P., and Michelle A. Duff. 1989. Young children’s comprehension of modal expressions. Cognitive Development 4(4): 369–387.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cariani, Fabrizio, and Paolo Santorio. 2017. Will done better: Selection semantics, future credence, and indeterminacy. Mind 127(505): 129–165. https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/fzw004.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia, Gennaro, Stephen Crain, Maria Teresa Guasti, Andrea Gualmini, and Luisa Meroni. 2001. The acquisition of disjunction: Evidence for a grammatical view of scalar implicatures. In Proceedings of the 25th Boston University conference on language development, eds. A. H.-J. Do, L. Domínguez, and A. Johansen, 157–168. Somerville: Cascadilla Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cinque, Guglielmo. 1999. Adverbs and functional heads: A cross-linguistic perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, Eve V. 1987. The principle of contrast: A constraint on language acquisition. In Mechanisms of language acquisition, ed. B. MacWhinney, 1–33. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coates, Jennifer. 1988. The acquisition of the meanings of modality in children aged eight and twelve. Journal of Child Language 15(2): 425–434. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0305000900012435.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cournane, Ailís. 2015. Modal development: Input-divergent L1 acquisition in the direction of diachronic reanalysis. PhD dissertation, University of Toronto.

  • Cournane, Ailís. 2021. Revisiting the epistemic gap: Evidence for a grammatical source. Language Acquisition 28(3): 215–240. https://doi.org/10.1080/10489223.2020.1860054.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crain, S. 2012. The emergence of meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Crain, Stephen, and Rosalind Thornton. 1998. Investigations in universal grammar. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crain, Stephen, Weijia Ni, and Laura Conway. 1994. Learning, parsing and modularity. In Perspectives on sentence processing, eds. Charles Clifton Jr., Lyn Frazier, Keith Rayner, and Charles Clifton, 443–467. Hove, UK: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deal, Amy Rose. 2011. Modals without scales. Language 87(3): 559–585.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Haan, F. 1997. The interaction of modality and negation: A typological study. Milton Park: Taylor & Francis.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Haan, Ferdinand. 2011. Disambiguating modals: Constructions and must. Manuscript, Oracle.

  • Dell, F. 1981. On the learnability of optional phonological rules. Linguistic Inquiry 12(1): 31–37. https://www.jstor.org/stable/4178203.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dieuleveut, Anouk. 2021. Finding modal force. PhD dissertation, University of Maryland.

  • Dieuleveut, Anouk, Annemarie van Dooren, Ailís Cournane, and Valentine Hacquard. 2019a. Learning modal force: Evidence from children’s production and input. In Proceedings of the 2019 Amsterdam Colloquium, 111–122.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dieuleveut, Anouk, Annemarie van Dooren, Ailís Cournane, and Valentine Hacquard. 2019b. Acquiring the force of modals: Sig you guess what sig means? In Proceedings of the 43rd annual to the Boston University Conference on Language Development (BUCLD43), eds. Megan M. Brown and Brady Dailey, 189–202.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dieuleveut, Anouk, Ailís Cournane, and Valentine Hacquard. 2021. Finding the force: A novel word learning experiment with modals. Experiments in Linguistic Meaning 1: 136–146. https://doi.org/10.3765/elm.1.4883.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Dooren, Annemarie, Anouk Dieuleveut, Ailís Cournane, and Valentine Hacquard. 2017. Learning what ‘must’ and ‘can’ must and can mean. In Proceedings of the 21st Amsterdam colloquium, eds. Alexandre Cremers, Thom van Gessel, and Floris Roelofsen, 225–234.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Dooren, Annemarie, Anouk Dieuleveut, Ailís Cournane, and Valentine Hacquard. 2022. Figuring out root and epistemic uses of modals: The role of the input. Journal of Semantics.

  • Drubig, Hans Bernard. 2001. On the syntactic form of epistemic modality. Manuscript, University of Tübingen.

  • Dudley, Rachel E. 2017. The role of input in discovering presuppositions triggers: Figuring out what everybody already knew. PhD dissertation, University of Maryland.

  • von Fintel, Kai, and Sabine Iatridou. 2008. How to say ought in foreign: The composition of weak necessity modals. In Time and modality, eds. Jacqueline Guéron and Jacqueline Lecarme, 115–141. Dordrecht: Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4020-8354-9_6.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gillette, Jane, Henry Gleitman, Lila Gleitman, and Anne Lederer. 1999. Human simulations of vocabulary learning. Cognition 73(2): 135–176. https://doi.org/10.1016/s0010-0277(99)00036-0.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. 1975. Logic and conversation. In Speech acts, ed. J. P. Kimball. Vol. 3 of Syntax and Semantics, 41–58. Leiden: Brill. https://doi.org/10.1163/9789004368811_003.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gualmini, Andrea, and Vincenzo Moscati. 2009. The early steps of modal and negation interactions: Evidence from child Italian. In Romance languages and linguistic theory, eds. Enoch O. Aboh, Elisabeth van der Linden, Josep Quer, and Petra Sleeman, 131–144. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. https://doi.org/10.1075/rllt.1.07gua.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gualmini, Andrea, and Bernhard Schwarz. 2009. Solving learnability problems in the acquisition of semantics. Journal of Semantics 26(2): 185–215. https://doi.org/10.1093/jos/ffp002.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hackl, Martin. 1998. On the semantics of “ability attributions”. Manuscript, MIT.

  • Hacquard, Valentine. 2011. Modality. In Semantics: An international handbook of natural language meaning, eds. C. Maienborn, K. von Heusinger, and P. Portner, 1484–1515. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirst, William, and Joyce Weil. 1982. Acquisition of epistemic and deontic meaning of modals. Journal of Child Language 9(3): 659–666. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0305000900004967.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmann, T. R. 1966. Past tense replacement and the English modal auxiliary system. Harvard Computation Laboratory report NSF 17.

  • Horn, Laurence R. 1972. On the semantic properties of logical operators. PhD dissertation, UCLA.

  • Iatridou, Sabine, and Hedde Zeijlstra. 2013. Negation, polarity, and deontic modals. Linguistic Inquiry 44(4): 529–568. https://doi.org/10.1162/ling_a_00138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jeretič, Paloma. 2018. Evidence for children’s dispreference for weakness: A corpus study. Manuscript, New York University.

  • Karmiloff-Smith, Annette. 1979. Micro-and macrodevelopmental changes in language acquisition and other representational systems. Cognitive Science 3(2): 91–117. https://doi.org/10.1207/s15516709cog0302_1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koring, Loes, Luisa Meroni, and Vincenzo Moscati. 2018. Strong and weak readings in the domain of worlds: A negative polar modal and children’s scope assignment. Journal of Psycholinguistic Research 47(6): 1193–1217. https://hdl.handle.net/1721.1/131876.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, Angelika. 1981. Partition and revision: The semantics of counterfactuals. Journal of Philosophical Logic 10(2): 201–216. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00248849.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, Angelika. 1991. Modality. In Semantics: An international handbook of contemporary research, eds. C. Maienborn, K. von Heusinger, and P. Portner, 639–650. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, Angelika. 2012. Modals and conditionals: New and revised perspectives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kuczaj, Stan A., and Michael P. Maratsos. 1975. What children can say before they will. Merrill-Palmer Quarterly 21(2): 89–111. http://www.jstor.org/stable/23083972.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landau, Barbara, and Lila Gleitman. 1985. Language and experience: Evidence from the blind child. Vol. 8 of Cognitive science series. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacWhinney, Brian. 2000. The CHILDES project: The database, Vol. 2. Hove, UK: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mandelkern, MatthewAaron, Ginger Schultheis, and David Boylan. 2015. I believe I can φ. In Proceedings of the 20th Amsterdam Colloquium, eds. Thomas Brochhagen, Floris Roelofsen, and Nadine Theiler, 256–265.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manzini, M. Rita, and Kenneth Wexler. 1987. Parameters, binding theory, and learnability. Linguistic Inquiry 18(3): 413–444. https://www.jstor.org/stable/4178549.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthewson, Lisa. 2013. Gitksan modals. International Journal of American Linguistics 79(3): 349–394. https://doi.org/10.1086/670751.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moscati, Vincenzo, and Stephen Crain. 2014. When negation and epistemic modality combine: The role of information strength in child language. Language Learning and Development 10(4): 345–380. https://doi.org/10.1080/15475441.2014.880640.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moscati, Vincenzo, and Andrea Gualmini. 2007. More facts that isomorphism cannot explain. In Proceedings of Semantics and Linguistic Theory 17, 202–209.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musolino, Julien. 2006. On the semantics of the Subset Principle. Language Learning and Development 2(3): 195–218. https://doi.org/10.1207/s15473341lld0203_3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Musolino, Julien, Kelsey Laity d’Agostino, and Steve Piantadosi. 2019. Why we should abandon the semantic subset principle. Language Learning and Development 15(1): 32–46. https://doi.org/10.1080/15475441.2018.1499517.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noveck, Ira A. 2001. When children are more logical than adults: Experimental investigations of scalar implicature. Cognition 78(2): 165–188. https://doi.org/10.1016/s0010-0277(00)00114-1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noveck, Ira A., Simon Ho, and Maria Sera. 1996. Children’s understanding of epistemic modals. Journal of Child Language 23(3): 621–643. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0305000900008977.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orita, Naho, Rebecca McKeown, Naomi H. Feldman, Jeffrey Lidz, and Jordan Boyd-Graber. 2013. Discovering pronoun categories using discourse information. In Proceedings of the annual meeting of the Cognitive Science Society. 6 pp. http://lintool.github.io/NSF-projects/CCF-1018625/papers/Pronouns.pdf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ozturk, Ozge, and Anna Papafragou. 2015. The acquisition of epistemic modality: From semantic meaning to pragmatic interpretation. Language Learning and Development 11(3): 191–214. https://doi.org/10.1080/15475441.2014.905169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Papafragou, Anna. 1998. The acquisition of modality: Implications for theories of semantic representation. Mind & Language 13(3): 370–399. https://doi.org/10.1111/1468-0017.00082.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peterson, Tyler. 2010. Epistemic modality and evidentiality in Gitksan at the semantics-pragmatics interface. PhD dissertation, University of British Columbia.

  • Piantadosi, Steven T. 2011. Learning and the language of thought. PhD dissertation, MIT.

  • Piantadosi, Steven T., Joshua B. Tenenbaum, and Noah D. Goodman. 2012a. Modeling the acquisition of quantifier semantics: A case study in function word learnability. Manuscript, University of Rochester

  • Piantadosi, Steven T., Joshua B. Tenenbaum, and Noah D. Goodman. 2012b. Bootstrapping in a language of thought: A formal model of numerical concept learning. Cognition 123(2): 199–217. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2011.11.005.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piéraut-Le Bonniec, Gilberte. 1980. The development of modal reasoning genesis of necessity and possibility notions. Cambridge: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, Steven. 1979. Formal models of language learning. Cognition 7(3): 217–283. https://doi.org/10.1016/0010-0277(79)90001-5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rakoczy, Hannes, Felix Warneken, and Michael Tomasello. 2007. “This way!”, “No! That way!”—3-year-olds know that two people can have mutually incompatible desires. Cognitive Development 22(1): 47–68. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cogdev.2006.08.002.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rasin, Ezer, and Athulya Aravind. 2020. The nature of the semantic stimulus: The acquisition of every as a case study. Natural Language Semantics 29: 339–375. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-020-09168-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • R Core Team. 2013. R: A language and environment for statistical computing. https://www.r-project.org/.

    Google Scholar 

  • Repacholi, Betty M., and Alison Gopnik. 1997. Early reasoning about desires: Evidence from 14- and 18-month-olds. Developmental Psychology 33(1): 12–21. https://doi.org/10.1037//0012-1649.33.1.12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, Elizabeth J., Martin G. Rowley, Sarah R. Beck, Dan J. Carroll, and Ian A. Apperly. 2006. Children’s sensitivity to their own relative ignorance: Handling of possibilities under epistemic and physical uncertainty. Child Development 77(6): 1642–1655. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-8624.2006.00964.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruffman, T., J. Aitken, A. Wilson, A. Puri, and M. Taumoepeau. 2018. A re-examination of the broccoli task: Implications for children’s understanding of subjective desire. Cognitive Development 46: 79–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rullmann, Hotze, Lisa Matthewson, and Henry Davis. 2008. Modals as distributive indefinites. Natural Language Semantics 16(4): 317–357. https://www.jstor.org/stable/23748121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaeffer, Jeannette, and Lisa Matthewson. 2005. Grammar and pragmatics in the acquisition of article systems. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 23(1): 53–101. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-004-5540-1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, John R. 1969. Speech acts: An essay in the philosophy of language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Skordos, Dimitrios, and Anna Papafragou. 2016. Children’s derivation of scalar implicatures: Alternatives and relevance. Cognition 153: 6–18. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2016.04.006.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Snedeker, Jesse. 2000. Cross-situational observation and the semantic bootstrapping hypothesis. In Proceedings of the thirtieth annual child language research forum, ed. Eve V. Clark. Stanford: Center for the Study of Language and Information. 7 pp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snedeker, Jesse, Lila Gleitman, and Michael Brent. 1999. The successes and failures of word-to-world mapping. In Proceedings of the twenty-third Boston University Conference on Language Development, eds. A. Greenhill, M. Hughs, H. Littlefield, and H. Walsh. Somerville: Cascadilla Press. 12 pp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. 1978. Assertion. Syntax and Semantics 9: 315–332.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stromswold, Karin J. 1990. Learnability and the acquisition of auxiliaries. PhD dissertation, MIT.

  • Theakston, Anna L., Elena V. Lieven, Julian M. Pine, and Caroline F. Rowland. 2001. The role of performance limitations in the acquisition of verb-argument structure: An alternative account. Journal of Child Language 28(1): 127–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thornton, Rosalind, and Graciela Tesan. 2013. Sentential negation in early child English. Journal of Linguistics 49(2): 367–411. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0022226712000382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, Henry M., and Jaqueline D. Woolley. 1990. From simple desires to ordinary beliefs: The early development of everyday psychology. Cognition 35(3): 245–275. https://doi.org/10.1016/0010-0277(90)90024-e.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White, Aaron S., Philip Resnik, Valentine Hacquard, and Jeffrey Lidz. 2016. The contextual modulation of semantic information. Manuscript, LingBuzz. https://lingbuzz.net/lingbuzz/003188/current.pdf?_s=IsOs-TEnLbcihiMd.

  • Xu, Fei, and Joshua B. Tenenbaum. 2007. Word learning as Bayesian inference. Psychological Review 114(2): 245–272. https://doi.org/10.1037/0033-295X.114.2.245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yanovich, Igor. 2016. Old English motan, variable-force modality, and the presupposition of inevitable actualization. Language 92(3): 489–521.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We thank Alexander Williams, Jeff Lidz, Tyler Knowlton, Yu’an Yang, Anissa Zaitsu, Dan Goodhue, Rémi Varloot, the Modality Group, the Language Acquisition Lab at the University of Maryland, Florian Schwarz, and two anonymous reviewers for helpful comments and suggestions, as well as our research assistants Monica Pizzo, Joon Lee, David Whitcomb, Madisen Fong, and Avni Gulrajani.

Funding

This project is supported in part by NSF grant #BCS-1551628.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Anouk Dieuleveut.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Supplementary Information

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Dieuleveut, A., van Dooren, A., Cournane, A. et al. Finding the force: How children discern possibility and necessity modals. Nat Lang Semantics 30, 269–310 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-022-09196-4

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-022-09196-4

Keywords

Navigation