Skip to content
Publicly Available Published by De Gruyter October 7, 2020

On the Microfoundation of Linear Oligopoly Demand

  • Iwan Bos EMAIL logo and Dries Vermeulen

Abstract

We critically assess the representative consumer with quadratic aggregate utility function which forms the foundation of a well-known class of linear oligopoly demand structures. It is argued that this approach is problematic and redundant. Regarding the latter, we show how the same demand system can be derived directly from a population of heterogeneous buyers for any number of products. Welfare analyses based on aggregate demand is shown to be sensitive to the underlying microfoundation.

JEL Codes: B4; L1

1 Introduction

A well-known way of describing the buyers’ side of an oligopoly market is through a linear horizontally differentiated demand model. For the case of duopoly, the (direct) demand structure generally takes the following form:

x 1 ( p 1 , p 2 ) = a 1 b 1 p 1 + c p 2 ,

x 2 ( p 1 , p 2 ) = a 2 b 2 p 2 + c p 1 ,

where price and quantity are positive and respectively given by p i and x i , for i = 1, 2.[1] It is, moreover, commonly assumed that a i , b i , c > 0 and b i  > c, for i = 1, 2, so that a firm’s demand depends negatively on its own price, positively on the rival’s price and own effects dominate cross effects. This demand system can be roughly interpreted as follows. If, say, firm 1 raises its price slightly, then ceteris paribus some of its customers walk away and either go home or visit firm 2 instead. Likewise, lowering price attracts additional buyers, some of whom switch from the competing firm.

The traditional foundation for this demand specification does not come from a group of heterogeneous buyers, however, but from a representative consumer who on behalf of an unspecified buyer population maximizes a quadratic aggregate welfare function. The most popular variations of this type are due to Bowley (1924) and Shubik and Levitan (1980).[2]

In the field of macroeconomics, such a representative agent approach has been heavily criticized by many. One reason for this is that transforming individual preferences into representative aggregate preferences often proves problematic. It is, for instance, quite possible that the representative agent prefers A to B, whereas each and every represented buyer prefers B to A.[3] For this and other reasons, many macroeconomists are reluctant to take this approach and some even went as far as to effectively compose a requiem for the representative consumer.[4] This is in stark contrast to the fields of microeconomics and industrial organization, where the use of such a fictitious agent is widely accepted. What makes this particularly surprising is that a rationale for this approach is commonly missing.[5]

In this paper, we pursue two main goals. The first is to provide a critical assessment of the representative consumer as a foundation for the above linear demand structure. Specifically, we argue that it is both inaccurate and inadequate. It is inaccurate as the representative agent’s aggregate utility function has no (clear) connection with the objectives of those represented. Indeed, the existing literature typically remains silent on the characteristics and traits of those represented.[6] It is inadequate because a justification for both the utility specification and the solution approach is missing. Taken together, this leads us to conclude that the popular linear oligopoly demand structure lacks a proper foundation.

We then proceed with our second goal, which is to argue that quadratic representative consumer models are effectively redundant. This is done by showing that the same demand structure can be easily derived directly from a population of heterogeneous consumers making discrete choices. Specifically, we use a variation of the spatial spokes models as described in Chen and Riordan (2007) and Amir et al. (2016). We first present this alternative foundation for duopoly and then extend the framework to allow for any number of firms. The latter is of particular interest because Jaffe and Weyl (2010) establish that the linear oligopoly demand structure is inconsistent with discrete consumer choice when the number of products exceeds two. The critical difference with our approach is that we assume each firm to have a brand loyal, captive customer base.[7] That property appears sufficient for a discrete choice microfoundation of the linear demand differentiation model independent of the number of products involved.

A main advantage of this approach is that it is explicitly based on simple buyer behavior at the micro-level and therefore has a natural interpretation. In addition, however, it also has potentially important welfare implications. To illustrate this, we show that a welfare analysis based on the aggregate linear demand system may lead to wrong conclusions if one ignores the corresponding microeconomic foundation. Specifically, consumer welfare may decrease in the cross-price effect within our setting, while at the same time making the representative consumer better off. Hence, our population of heterogeneous buyers is not properly represented by this fictitious quadratic utility maximizer.

A couple of recent papers have raised some red flags regarding the use of a representative agent with a quadratic utility function. Kopel, Ressi, and Lambertini (2017), for instance, find that seemingly similar quadratic aggregate utility functions may give rise to fundamentally different demand systems. In turn, this might lead to radically different policy implications. In a similar vein, Theilen (2012) illustrates how the consequences of changes in product differentiation can be very sensitive to the precise linear demand specification. Amir, Erickson, and Jin (2017) contains a thorough study of several characteristics of the quadratic utility specification. Among other things, this paper shows that strict concavity of the utility function is a necessary condition for the corresponding demand system to be well-defined. As to the alternative microfoundation, Martin (2002, p. 53) points out how the linear demand system can be derived from a vertical product differentiation model. Finally, our work is also related to Anderson, De Palma, and Thisse (1989, 1992) who show how other representative consumer models, such as ones with a constant elasticity of substitution (CES) utility function, can be given a discrete choice foundation.

The remainder of this paper is organized as follows. The next section discusses the quadratic representative consumer utility function and highlights several problematic features of this specification. Section 3 presents the alternative microfoundation for linear oligopoly demand. Section 4 offers some welfare implications. Section 5 concludes.

2 Quadratic Representative Consumer Models

In this section, we express some concerns about the above mentioned class of quadratic representative consumer models. Specifically, we raise several issues regarding the shape of the objective function, the derivation of the corresponding demand functions and the relation between the products involved.

2.1 Issue 1: The Objective

Both the Bowley (1924) and the Shubik and Levitan (1980) demand specifications are derived from a representative consumer gross utility function that takes the following general form:

U ( x 1 , x 2 ) = α ( x 1 + x 2 ) β ( x 1 + x 2 ) 2 γ ( x 2 x 1 ) 2 ,

with α, β, γ > 0.[8] Notice that the way in which we present this objective function, it effectively consists of three distinct parts. Starting with the third, γ ( x 2 x 1 ) 2 , this part captures the complementarity between products x 1 and x 2. Consistent with classic consumer theory, utility is ceteris paribus higher with a more balanced consumption plan. In fact, the representative agent is induced to buy both products in equal amounts (x 1 = x 2) so that the third-term disutility is minimized and de facto disappears.

The first two parts, α ( x 1 + x 2 ) β ( x 1 + x 2 ) 2 , capture utility coming from total rather than relative consumption and express the extent to which the goods are considered substitutes. These components indicate that the consumer derives utility from consuming more products, but only up to a certain amount. That is, utility increases at low levels of total consumption through the first term, but at higher levels of total consumption the second term starts to dominate the first. This implies that there is a point at which the consumer is satiated. Notice that this is true also when the representative agent does not face a budget constraint and holds even when the goods would be offered, in the broadest sense, for free. Contrary to the third term favoring balance in consumption, this therefore is at odds with traditional consumer theory. Indeed, the fact that the objective function has a unique maximum makes that the common assumption of nonsatiation is violated.[9]

2.2 Issue 2: The Solution

To solve the representative consumer problem, one naturally needs to take account of the cost of consumption. In the following, we point out that the linear oligopoly demand structure will only result from the representative agent’s maximization problem under fairly specific, and arguably strong, assumptions.

Towards that end, let F be a set of vectors ( x , m ) n × and consider the utility function V : F . For (x, m) ∈ F, therefore, utility V(x, m) is obtained from consuming an amount of x n goods as well as from the unspent money m.[10] Moreover, let the vector of prices be given by p n . If the available income is I, then the representative consumer faces the following general maximization problem:

max x F V ( x , m ) s . t . : m = I p x , m 0 ,

where px is total expenditure.

It can be easily verified, however, that the linear oligopoly demand system is the solution to:

max x F U ( x ) + m s . t . : m = I p x .

Thus, in light of the general maximization problem, V(x, m) = U(x) + m and the constraint m ≥ 0 is either ignored or income is (implicitly) assumed large enough. Observe that this specification effectively treats expenditures as a disutility, which is linearly subtracted from the gross utility function. At first sight this may seem natural and innocuous, but it does imply two strong assumptions:

  1. The representative consumer’s utility function is quasi-linear in money;

  2. The representative consumer can borrow unlimited amounts of money for free.

The first condition means the absence of a wealth effect as utility is linearly increasing in money. Irrespective of whether utility is high or low, the marginal gain of an extra dollar is the same.[11] The second states that the budget restriction has no bite and is effectively non-existent. Given the quadratic nature of the objective function, this holds trivially when the representative consumer has a sufficiently large income.[12] Note, however, that this approach makes it irrelevant how much budget is available. Indeed, even when the representative agent loses all his income (I = 0) or would have severe debts (I < 0), demand for both products stays the same.

2.3 Issue 3: The Products

Following the textbook approach and thus assuming A1 and A2, the representative consumer picks x 1 and x 2 to maximize:

V ( x 1 , x 2 ) = α ( x 1 + x 2 ) β ( x 1 + x 2 ) 2 γ ( x 2 x 1 ) 2 + I p 1 x 1 p 2 x 2 .

Goods are substitutes in utility when for every η 1 > 0 there is an η 2 > 0 such that:

U ( x 1 η 1 , x 2 + η 2 ) = U ( x 1 , x 2 ) .

That is, every decrease in utility resulting from a reduction in the consumption of good 1 can be compensated by an increase in the consumption of good 2.[13] If we consider x 2 an implicit function X 2 ( x 1 ) along a level curve of V, then X 2 < 0 . Implicit differentiation yields:

α ( 1 + X 2 ) 2 β ( x 1 + X 2 ) ( 1 + X 2 ) 2 γ ( x 1 X 2 ) ( 1 X 2 ) = 0.

Rearranging gives:

X 2 ( x 1 ) = 2 γ ( x 1 x 2 ) + 2 β ( x 1 + x 2 ) α 2 γ ( x 1 x 2 ) 2 β ( x 1 + x 2 ) + α

Thus, X 2 < 0 requires

2 γ ( x 1 x 2 ) + 2 β ( x 1 + x 2 ) α < 0 ( β + γ ) x 1 + ( β γ ) x 2 < α 2

and

2 γ ( x 1 x 2 ) 2 β ( x 1 + x 2 ) + α > 0 ( β + γ ) x 2 + ( β γ ) x 1 < α 2

or the reverse.

Note that the above inequalities do not hold for all consumption bundles (x 1, x 2). For instance, x 1 = 0, x 2 = 1 and β γ < α 2 < β + γ violates the inequalities. In this model, therefore, utility can remain constant when the representative agent receives more or less of both goods.[14] One therefore may need a rather peculiar quadratic aggregate utility function to obtain a relatively straightforward demand system. This is arguably problematic since the representative consumer’s utility function is ultimately intended to serve as a microfoundation for linear oligopoly demand.

3 A Microeconomic Foundation for Linear Oligopoly Demand

In the preceding section, we have highlighted some problematic features of quadratic representative consumer models. We now proceed by presenting an alternative microeconomic foundation for the linear oligopoly demand system. Below, we study the two-good case first before showing the derivation for any number of products.

3.1 Duopoly

Consider the linear duopoly demand system as described above:

x 1 ( p 1 , p 2 ) = a 1 b 1 p 1 + c p 2 ,

x 2 ( p 1 , p 2 ) = a 2 b 2 p 2 + c p 1 .

In the following, we will show how this demand structure can be derived directly from a population of heterogeneous consumers.

Consider a price-setting duopoly where both firms are located on the boundary of an interval [0, 2]. In particular, and without loss of generality, firm 1 and firm 2 are respectively situated at 0 and 2. There are three types of consumers, each with uniform population density λ i on [0, 2], i = 1, 2, 3. The total number of type i buyers is thus given by 2 λ i . Type 1 customers are assumed to obtain positive gross utility when buying from firm 1, s > 0, and no utility when buying from firm 2. By contrast, Type 2 customers attach no value to the products of firm 1 and derive positive gross utility from buying at firm 2, v > 0. Finally, Type 3 customers value both equally and have a willingness to pay of 4 for each.[15] Consumers either buy one unit of the product or do not buy and are characterized by their location. In the spirit of spatial IO settings, there are costs associated with distance between buyer and seller and these are assumed to be linearly increasing.

Let us now specify the utility function of a Type 1 consumer located at z [ 0,2 ] . This customer has basically three options: (1) buy from firm 1 (value s − z − p 1), (2) buy from firm 2 (value z − 2 − p 2) or (3) buy nothing (value 0). Notice that the third choice dominates the second, because z − 2 − p 2 ≤ 0 for positive prices. Thus, the utility function of a Type 1 buyer located at z [ 0,2 ] effectively is

u 1 ( p 1 , p 2 , z ) = max { s z p 1 , 0 } .

The Type 1 customer who is indifferent between option (1) and option (3) is located at z = s − p 1.

The utility function of a Type 2 customer located at z [ 0,2 ] can be determined in a similar fashion and is given by

u 2 ( p 1 , p 2 , z ) = max { v 2 + z p 2 , 0 } .

The Type 2 customer who is indifferent between buying and not buying is thus located at z = p 2 − v + 2. Finally, the utility function of a Type 3 customer at z [ 0,2 ] is

u 3 ( p 1 , p 2 , z ) = max { 4 z p 1 , 2 + z p 2 , 0 } .

Under the assumption that prices are sufficiently low, the indifferent Type 3 buyer is located at z = 1 + 1 2 ( p 2 p 1 ) .[16]

On the basis of these utility specifications, we can now derive the corresponding demand functions. For a given combination of prices (p 1, p 2) in the relevant range, demand for firm 1 is given by the sum of consuming Type 1 buyers and the part of Type 3 buyers preferring the product of firm 1.[17]

x 1 ( p 1 , p 2 ) = λ 1 ( s p 1 ) + λ 3 ( 1 + 1 2 ( p 2 p 1 ) ) = s λ 1 + λ 3 ( λ 1 + 1 2 λ 3 ) p 1 + 1 2 λ 3 p 2 .

Demand for the products of firm 2 can be derived in a similar way.

x 2 ( p 1 , p 2 ) = v λ 2 + λ 3 ( λ 2 + 1 2 λ 3 ) p 2 + 1 2 λ 3 p 1 .

The above approach therefore allows one to derive any linear duopoly demand system of the form:

x 1 ( p 1 , p 2 ) = a 1 b 1 p 1 + c p 2 ,

x 2 ( p 1 , p 2 ) = a 2 b 2 p 2 + c p 1 ,

where λ 1 = b 1 c , λ 2 = b 2 c , λ 3 = 2 c , s = a 1 2 c b 1 c and v = a 2 2 c b 2 c .

3.2 Oligopoly

The above duopoly demand structure has been generalized to any number of firms by Häckner (2000). If the set of firms is N, then demand for each firm k N takes the following form:

x k ( p k , p k ) = a k b k p k + c j k p j ,

with a k , b k , c > 0. We will now use a variation on the ‘spokes-model’ introduced by Chen and Riordan (2007) to show how this demand system can be derived with the approach laid out in the previous subsection.[18]

Consider a price-setting oligopoly where each firm is ‘located’ at an end node of a star-shaped network. The edge from the center to firm i is denoted by E i . Let the distance to the center (i.e., the length of E i ) be equal to 1 so that the distance between each pair of firms is 2.

For each firm i N , there is a Type i consumer with uniform population density λ i on E i . The total number of type i buyers is thus given by λ i . Type i customers are assumed captive in the sense that they obtain positive gross utility v i  > 0 when buying from firm i and no utility when buying from any other firm j N , j ≠ i.

Next, for each pair of firms (i, j), type ij customers value the goods from both firm i and firm j equally and have a willingness to pay of 4 for each. Type ij customers are distributed with uniform population density λ i j along the path E i E j from firm i to firm j. Consumers either buy one unit of the product or do not buy and are characterized by their location. As before, there are costs associated with distance between buyer and seller and these are assumed to be linearly increasing.

Let us now specify the utility function of a Type i consumer located at z E i , where z = 0 indicates the location of firm i at the endpoint of E i and z = 1 is the location of the center. Such a customer has basically three options: (1) buy from firm i (value v i  − z − p i ), (2) buy from another firm j, j ≠ i, (value z − 2 − p j ) or (3) buy nothing (value 0). Notice that the third choice dominates the second since z − 2 − p j  ≤ 0 whenever p j is positive. Thus, the utility function of a Type i buyer located at z E i is effectively given by:

u i ( p i , p i , z ) = max { v i z p i , 0 } .

The Type i customer who is indifferent between option (1) and option (3) is located at z = v i  − p i .

The utility function of a Type ij customer located at z E i E j can be determined in a similar fashion and is given by

u i j ( p i , p j , p i j , z ) = max { 4 z p i , 2 + z p j , 0 } .

Under the assumption that prices are sufficiently low, the indifferent Type ij buyer is located at z = 1 + 1 2 ( p j p i ) .[19]

On the basis of these utility specifications, we can now derive the corresponding demand functions. For a given combination of prices p = (p 1,…, p n ) in the relevant range, demand for firm i is given by the sum of consuming Type i buyers and the part of Type ij buyers preferring the product of firm i.

x k ( p k , p k ) = λ k ( v k p k ) + j k λ k j ( 1 + 1 2 ( p j p k ) ) = v k λ k + j k λ k j ( λ k + 1 2 j k λ k j ) p k + 1 2 j k λ k j p j .

The above approach therefore allows one to derive any linear oligopoly demand structure of the form

x k ( p k , p k ) = a k b k p k + c j k p j , k N ,

where λ k  = b k  − c, λ k j = 2 c n 1 , and v k = a k 2 c b k c .

This result contrasts with Jaffe and Weyl (2010) which shows that this type of linear demand structure cannot be derived from a discrete choice setting when the number of goods exceeds 2.[20] In Jaffe and Weyl (2010), the distribution of customers over (realizations of) valuations is given by a smooth probability density function. As a result, the probability of observing a customer who does not value a particular product is zero. The above model does not fit within this framework due to the presence of captive consumers.[21] We thus conclude that linear oligopoly demand can be consistent with a discrete choice foundation for any number of products when each firm has a loyal customer base.

4 Welfare

Since the traditional representative agent approach and our alternative lead to the same demand system, it may be tempting to think that the implications are relatively innocuous. However, and as already pointed out in the introduction, welfare analyses are known to be sensitive to the precise specification of the representative consumer’s utility function. We now add to this by showing that results of a welfare analysis based on the aggregate linear demand system depend non-trivially on the underlying microeconomic foundation. Specifically, we illustrate how a stronger cross-price effect can be harmful for customers within our setting, while at the same time be seen as beneficial by the representative consumer.

In the following, we consider the simplest possible case of a symmetric duopoly. For some given prices p 1 and p 2, the representative consumer’s surplus is:

V = α ( x 1 + x 2 ) β ( x 1 + x 2 ) 2 γ ( x 2 x 1 ) 2 p 1 x 1 p 2 x 2 = α ( 2 a ( b c ) p 1 ( b c ) p 2 ) β ( 2 a ( b c ) p 1 ( b c ) p 2 ) 2 γ ( ( b + c ) ( p 1 p 2 ) ) 2 p 1 x 1 p 2 x 2 = 2 a 2 b c a p 1 a p 2 1 4 ( b c ) ( 2 a b c p 1 p 2 ) 2 1 4 ( b + c ) ( p 1 p 2 ) 2 a p 1 + b p 1 2 c p 1 p 2 a p 2 + b p 2 2 c p 1 p 2 = a 2 b c a p 1 a p 2 c p 1 p 2 + b 2 p 1 2 + b 2 p 2 2 .

Let us now derive consumer surplus under the same conditions within our alternative setting. Using symmetry, it holds that λ 1 = λ 2 = b c , λ 3 = 2 c , and s = v = a 2 c b c . The consumer surplus is then given by:

W = 1 2 λ 1 ( s p 1 ) 2 + 1 2 λ 2 ( v p 2 ) 2 + λ 3 [ 6 p 1 p 2 + 1 2 + 1 8 ( p 2 p 1 ) 2 + 1 2 + 1 8 ( p 2 p 1 ) 2 ] = b c 2 ( a 2 c b c p 1 ) 2 + b c 2 ( a 2 c b c p 2 ) 2 + 2 c [ 7 p 1 p 2 + 1 4 ( p 2 p 1 ) 2 ] = ( a 2 c ) 2 b c + 14 c a p 1 a p 2 c p 1 p 2 + b 2 p 1 2 + b 2 p 2 2 .

Comparing V and W, we see that the consumer surplus generally differs in absolute terms. Note, however, that the price effects are precisely the same in both cases so that ordinal welfare implications of price changes would lead to similar conclusions.

Yet, the same does not hold for changes in demand system parameters that may result from innovations, for instance. To see this, note that

V c = a 2 ( b c ) 2 p 1 p 2 ,

whereas

W c = ( a 2 c ) ( a + 2 c 4 b ) ( b c ) 2 + 14 p 1 p 2 .

It can be easily verified that the signs may not be the same.[22] In particular, an increase in the cross-price effect can be beneficial for the representative consumer (i.e.,  V c > 0 ), while being harmful for buyers within our framework (i.e.,  W c < 0 ). Conducting a welfare analysis at the aggregate demand level can therefore lead to wrong conclusions when one does not take account of the corresponding microeconomic foundation.

5 Concluding Remarks

The use of representative agents in economic theory dates back at least as far as the late 1800s when Marshall’s manuscript Principles of Economics saw the light of day.[23] Marshall introduced the notion of a ‘representative firm’, but also considered employing this approach in other areas of economics.[24] In fact, he is claimed to have said:[25]

“I think the notion of ‘representative firm’ is capable of extension to labour; and I have had some idea of introducing that into my discussion of standard rates of wages. But I don’t feel sure I shall: and I almost think I can say what I want to more simply in another way…

In this paper, we have shown this hunch might hold true for a well-known class of quadratic representative consumer models. Indeed, one can quite simply derive the corresponding linear oligopoly demand structure directly from a population of heterogeneous buyers. This renders the use of a fictitious agent in this case effectively redundant. Moreover, the resulting microeconomic foundation can be easily extended to other demand specifications.

It is, however, not only for the sake of simplicity that one should discard this representative buyer model. In line with other recent work discussed above, we have pointed out some problematic traits of this approach. In particular, we have argued that it is inaccurate as the representative agent’s aggregate utility function has no clear connection with the represented buyers’ objectives and that it is inadequate as it requires an unsatisfactory solution approach to obtain the linear oligopoly demand system.

Together, this should raise strong doubts about welfare analyses based on this type of representative consumer models. Indeed, we have illustrated how welfare implications of changes in the aggregate demand system depend non-trivially on its microeconomic foundation. This naturally warrants critical assessment of other settings with a similar approach. We leave this issue for future research.


Corresponding author: Iwan Bos, Department of Organisation, Strategy and Entrepreneurship, Maastricht University, P.O. Box 616, 6200 MD, Maastricht, The Netherlands, E-mail:

  1. We appreciate the comments and suggestions of Mark Armstrong, Stephen Martin, Ronald Peeters, Jannika Schad, seminar participants at Maastricht University, participants at the Oligo workshop 2019 in Nottingham, UK, and anonymous referees. All opinions and errors are ours alone.

References

Amir, R., J. Y. Jin, G. Pech, and M. Tröge. 2016. “Prices and Deadweight Loss in Multiproduct Monopoly.” Journal of Public Economic Theory 18 (3): 346–62, https://doi.org/10.1111/jpet.12173.Search in Google Scholar

Amir, R., P. Erickson, and J. Y. Jin. 2017. “On the Microeconomic Foundations of Linear Demand for Differentiated Products.” Journal of Economic Theory 169: 641–65, https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jet.2017.03.005.Search in Google Scholar

Anderson, S. P., A. De Palma, and T. Jacques-François. 1989. “Demand for Differentiated Products, Discrete Choice Models and the Characteristics Approach.” Review of Economic Studies 56 (1): 21–35, https://doi.org/10.2307/2297747.Search in Google Scholar

Anderson, S. P., A. De Palma, and T. Jacques-François. 1992. Discrete Choice Theory of Product Differentiation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.10.7551/mitpress/2450.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Armstrong, M., and J. Vickers. 1993. “Price Discrimination, Competition and Regulation.” Journal of Industrial Economics 41 (4): 335–59, https://doi.org/10.2307/2950596.Search in Google Scholar

Armstrong, M., and J. Vickers. 2015. “Which Demand Systems can be Generated by Discrete Choice?.” Journal of Economic Theory 158: 293–307, https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jet.2015.04.010.Search in Google Scholar

Bowley, A. L. 1924. The Mathematical Groundwork of Economics. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Chen, Y., and M. H. Riordan. 2007. “Price and Variety in the Spokes Model.” Economic Journal 117 (522): 897–921, https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0297.2007.02063.x.Search in Google Scholar

Choné, P., and L. Linnemer. 2020. “Linear demand systems for differentiated goods: Overview and user’s guide.” International Journal of Industrial Organization 73.10.1016/j.ijindorg.2020.102663Search in Google Scholar

Dixit, A. K. 1979. “A Model of Duopoly Suggesting a Theory of Entry Barriers.” Bell Journal of Economics 10 (1): 20–32, https://doi.org/10.2307/3003317.Search in Google Scholar

Dixit, A. K., and J. E. Stiglitz. 1977. “Monopolistic Competition and Optimum Product Diversity.” American Economic Review 67 (3): 297–308.Search in Google Scholar

Dow, J., and S. R. da Costa Werlang. 1988. “The Consistency of Welfare Judgements with a Representative Consumer.” Journal of Economic Theory 44 (2): 269–80, https://doi.org/10.1016/0022-0531(88)90004-x.Search in Google Scholar

Edgeworth, F. Y. 1881. Mathematical Physics: An Essay on the Application of Mathematics to the Moral Sciences. London: C. Kegan Paul & Co.Search in Google Scholar

Edgeworth, F. Y. 1925. The Pure Theory of Monopoly. Papers Relating to Political Economy, Vol. 1: 111–42.Search in Google Scholar

Hackner, J. 2000. “A Note on Price and Quantity Competition in Differentiated Oligopolies.” Journal of Economic Theory 93 (2): 233–9, https://doi.org/10.1006/jeth.2000.2654.Search in Google Scholar

Hartley, J. E. 1996. “Retrospectives: The Origins of the Representative Agent.” Journal of Economic Perspectives 10 (2): 169–77, https://doi.org/10.1257/jep.10.2.169.Search in Google Scholar

Jaffe, S., and G. E. Weyl. 2010. “Linear Demand Systems Are Inconsistent with Discrete Choice.” B.E. Journal of Theoretical Economics 10 (1): 293–307, https://doi.org/10.2202/1935-1704.1729.Search in Google Scholar

Jehle, G. A., and P. J. Reny. 2001. Advanced Microeconomic Theory, 2nd ed. Boston, MA: University of Chicago, Addison-Wesley Longman, inc.Search in Google Scholar

Jerison, M. 1984. “Social Welfare and the Unrepresentative Representative Consumer.” Discussion Paper, SUNY Albany.Search in Google Scholar

Kirman, A. P. 1992. “Whom or What does the Representative Individual Represent?” Journal of Economic Perspectives 6 (2): 117–36, https://doi.org/10.1257/jep.6.2.117.Search in Google Scholar

Kopel, M., R. Anna, and L. Lambertini. 2017. “Capturing Direct and Cross Price Effects in a Differentiated Products Duopoly Model.” The Manchester School 85 (3): 282–94, https://doi.org/10.1111/manc.12146.Search in Google Scholar

LaFrance, J. T. 1985. “Linear Demand Functions in Theory and Practice.” Journal of Economic Theory 37 (1): 147–66, https://doi.org/10.1016/0022-0531(85)90034-1.Search in Google Scholar

Martin, S. 2002. Advanced Industrial Economics, 2nd ed. Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishing.Search in Google Scholar

Pigou, A. C. 1956. Memorials of Alfred Marshall. New York: Kelly Millman.Search in Google Scholar

Shubik, M., and R. Levitan. 1980. Market Structure and Behavior: Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.10.4159/harvard.9780674433403Search in Google Scholar

Singh, N., and X. Vives. 1984. “Price and Quantity Competition in a Differentiated Duopoly.” RAND Journal of Economics 15 (4): 546–54, https://doi.org/10.2307/2555525.Search in Google Scholar

Soeiro, R., and A. A. Pinto. 2019. “Social Power as a Solution to the Bertrand Paradox.” Discussion Paper.Search in Google Scholar

Spence, M. 1976. “Product Selection, Fixed Costs, and Monopolistic Competition.” Review of Economic Studies 43 (2): 217–35, https://doi.org/10.2307/2297319.Search in Google Scholar

Theilen, B. 2012. “Product Differentiation and Competitive Pressure.” Journal of Economics 107 (3): 257–66, https://doi.org/10.1007/s00712-011-0261-5.Search in Google Scholar

Received: 2019-07-07
Accepted: 2020-07-20
Published Online: 2020-10-07

© 2022 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston

Downloaded on 6.5.2024 from https://www.degruyter.com/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2019-0114/html
Scroll to top button