Skip to main content
Log in

The World and Its Nightmare (Levinas on Sense and Nonsense)

  • Theoretical / Philosophical Paper
  • Published:
Human Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This text deals with the interpretation of where the meaningfulness of existence and our being in the world in Emmanuel Levinas’s conception originates in its contrast to the similar conception developed by phenomenology of appearing - which is represented by M. Heidegger and H. Maldiney. I want to show on what premises Levinas argues that the epiphany of sense can only emerge in the case of a continuous overcoming of the nonsense of appearing and thus of Being as such. Therefore, I intend to go through the steps of Levinas’ reasoning, which he never developed systematically, and explain why he can view Being as nonsensical and what this notion of nonsense could possibly mean in Levinas’s philosophy. As a result, I would like present an implicit argumentation behind Levinas’s well-known claim that the birth of sense must be of ethical origin and cannot arise through the process of appearing or Being alone.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In this text I have tried to introduce a common terminology for all the theories mentioned. However, let us recall that Heidegger for example also linked his philosophy to the notion of transcendence (Heidegger, 1996b: 214).

  2. See for exaple Lannoy (1990), Kang (1997), Neppi (2000), Cools (2005), Lawton (2005), Long (2006), Ombrosi (2006), Sebbah (2016) where the theme of nonsense is directly related to the topics (il y a, death, nothingness, suffering) of these articles and yet absent.

  3. I think Levinas’s view of nonsense hasn’t changed in its essence. It evolved, clarified, concretized, and above all became truly coherent, in my view, as Levinas’sthinking matured, when he developed his philosophy of ethics more precisely (see Sealey, 2010: 100). I also recommend Bernasconi’s article (2005).

  4. I write the capital B here deliberately because of the connection with Heidegger’s terminology: so Being for us will be Being as such.

  5. It must be noted that the terms vulnerability, mortality, sensibility or, e.g., insomnia are used by Levinas (in contrast to our text) mostly, although not exclusively, in an ethical context; that is because they attain their true meaning in the process of transcendence, only within an ethical situation, when excess remains excess (or transcendence). Still, I believe it is important to keep in mind the wider, more general import of these concepts as the cornerstones of embodied existence, because what is constitutive of their meaning is their “ambiguity,” their role in the categories of sense and nonsense (see Levinas, 1998b: 190, footnote 30.)

  6. To be fair, I think Maldiney goes further than Heidegger’s philosophy in his conception of what is non-apparent because he is concerned with corporeality (see for example Maldiney, 1973: 136). However, Maldiney, like Heidegger, subscribes to the same and more general paradigm of thought, in which the Transcendent as the non-apparent is the hidden side of being, while its revealed side is the apparent (see Maldiney, 2012: 204). For this reason, I classify both authors under “phenomenology of appearance” and thus contrast them with Levinas.

  7. Futher interpretation can be found in Rolland (2000).

  8. Very illustrative are Levinas’s descriptions of madness stemming from our subordination to the processes of Essence as experiences of the impossibility to touch pure nothingness, death (Levinas, 1978: 61), in this sense experiences of never-ending dying which is denied a different dimension, the future (Levinas, 1987: 11), i.e., the suffering from the hell of the Same and the desperate totality of Being, which not even death can pierce. “Death, which was to be the fading away of life, confirms the being of life in its generality of pure being, and becomes part of it” (Levinas, 1996: 161).

  9. Compare with interesting development of Maldiney’s and Romano’s concept of personal uniqueness in Prášek (2021: 721-740).

  10. Bernstein (2004: 266) summarises well the problem of immorality of such behaviour, which leads to the evil of theodicy. As far as the problem of theodicy is concerned, an interesting article by Han (2020: 45-79) presents the opinion that in Levinas we may find clues for the interpretation of the ethical expectation of the so called “messianic future” and hope as well, contrasting to Heidegger’s analyses of future connected to mortality.

  11. Maldiney’s philosophy is an example of such a philosophy that extends the concept of otherness beyond other people (see Maldiney, 1973: 152), and it is therefore possible to use his thesis, for example, in ecophenomenology and to defend the need of an ethical approach to animals and nature too. This is a much more difficult task in Levinas’scase. On the other hand, as I said, if the otherness of things, animals, etc. comes from factual transcendence in Maldiney’s case, by contrast it is harder to justify philosophically the necessity of an ethical approach to them. A very inspiring synthesis of Levinas and Maldiney in an ecophenomenological perspective was made by Per Prášek in his forthcoming article Levinas vs. Maldiney: On a Face of Sensible Nature for the Journal of British Society for Phenomenology.

  12. Levinas deliberately uses these words, against and in spite of death, for description of transcendence as an opposition to Heidgger’s Sein zum Tode, being towards death.

  13. https://www.biblegateway.com/passage/?search=Song%20of%20Solomon%208%3A6&version=ESV.

  14. „We should ask ourselves whether the humanity of man is his having-to-be. And this leads inevitably to a discussion with Heidegger” (Levinas, 2000: 18). “[…]I am persuaded that around the death of my neighbour what I have been calling the humanity of man is manifested” (Levinas, 1999: 158).

  15. Levinas thematizes suffering as evil in the text Transcendence and Evil (Levinas, 1998b: 122-136).

  16. Regarding text Transcendence and Evil, one could object that Levinas literally wrote that evil is some sort of “transcendence” (Levinas, 1998b: 129). However, I believe that the intention of the article leads to a different assertion (as is the case in the text Emmanuel Levinas, “Useless Suffering,” Levinas 1998a: 91-102). That is why several pages later Levinas comes to the conclusion that it is exclusively the awakening of soul (awakening by evil and to Goodness) which responds to “a transcendency that is no longer absorbed by my knowledge” (Levinas, 1998b: 132).

  17. A partial answer as to why it is not possible to elucidate why transcendence is connected with the question of good and evil is supplied by Cohen (see 2004: 276f.). I think it’s a matter of an assumption that can’t be further justified (and which of course every theory has), which Levinas shares with the Jewish and Christian religions.

References

  • Bastiani, F. (2015). Trauma and crisis in Emmanuel Levinas and Henri Maldiney conference paper available at https://www.academia.edu/17558003/Trauma_and_Crisis_in_Emmanuel_Levinas_and_Henri_Maldiney.

  • Bernasconi, R. (2005). No exit: Levinas’aporetic account of transcendence. Research in Phenomenology, 35, 101–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein, R. J. (2004). Evil and the temptation of theodicy. In S. Critchley, & R. Bernasconi (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Levinas (3rd ed., pp. 252–267). Cambridge University Press.

  • Cohen, R. A. (2004). Ethics, exegesis and philosophy. interpretation after Lévinas. Cambridge University Press.

  • Cohen, R. A. (2006). Thinking least about death: Contra Heidegger. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 60(1/3), 21–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cools, A. (2005). Revisiting the Il y a: Maurice Blanchot and Emmanuel Levinas on the question of subjectivity. Paragraph, 28(3), 54–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Critchley, S. (2005). Il y a—holding Levinas’s hand to Blanchot’s fire. In C. Katz, L. Trout (Eds.), Emmanuel Levinas. Critical assessments of leading philosophers (1st ed., pp. 75-87). Routlege.

  • Han, H. (2020). Reading Levinas’ deconstruction of time trough the ethical subject. Interpretationes Acta Universitatis Carolinae Studia Philosophica Europeanea, 10(1), 45–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1949). Existence and being. Henry Regnery Company.

  • Heidegger, M. (1996a). Being and time. State University of New York Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (1996b). “Introduction to philosophy“. Einleitung in die Philosophie. Gesamtausgabe vol. 27. Klostermann.

  • Kang, Y. A. (1997). Levinas on suffering and solidarity. Tijdschrift voor Filosofie, 59(3), 482–504.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landgrebe, L. (1940). The world as a phenomenological problem. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, (1)(1), 38–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lannoy, J. L. (1990). “‘There is’ and phenomenology in the thought of the young Levinas“. «Il y a» et phénoménologie dans la pensée du jeune Lévinas. Revue Philosophique de Louvain, 88(79), 369–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lawton, P. (2005). Levinas’notion of the “there is“. In C. Katz, L. Trout (Eds.), Emmanuel Levinas. Critical assessments of leading philosophers (1st ed., pp. 249-259). Routlege.

  • Leibniz, W. G. (1989). In E. Leroy, & Loemker (Eds.), Philosophical papers and letters. Springer.

  • Levinas, E. (1978). Existence and existent Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Levinas, E. (1987). Collected philosophical papers of Emmanuel Levinas. Martinus Nijhoff Publishers.

  • Levinas, E. (1986). The trace of the other. In M. C. Taylor (Ed.), Deconstruction in context. Literature and philosophy (1st ed., pp. 345–359). The University of Chicago Press.

  • Levinas, E. (1990). Difficult freedom: essays on Judaism. The John Hopkins University Press.

  • Levinas, E. (1996). Propes names. Standford University Press.

  • Levinas, E. (1998a). Entre nous: on thinking-of-the-other. Columbia University Press.

  • Levinas, E. (1998b). Of God who comes to mind. Standford University Press.

  • Levinas, E. (1999). Alterity and transcendence. The Athlone Press.

  • Levinas, E. (2000). God, death, and time. Standford University Press.

  • Levinas, E. (2003). On escape. Standford University Press.

  • Levinas, E. (2011a). Otherwise than being, or, beyond essence. Duquesne University Press.

  • Levinas, E. (2011b). Totality and infinity. Essay on exteriority. Duquesne University Press.

  • Long, E. T. (2006). Suffering and transcendence. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 60(1/3), 139–148.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maldiney, H. (1973). “Gaze, speech, space”. Regard, parole, espace. l’Age d’Homme.

  • Maldiney, H. (2007). “Thinking of man and madness”. Penser l’homme et la folie. Grenoble.

  • Maldiney, H. (2012). “Art, the lightning of being”. L’art, l’éclair de l’être. Les Editions du Cerf.

  • Neppi, E. (2000). Being and evil in the thought of Emmanuel Levinas”. L’Être et le Mal dans la pensée d’Emmanuel Levinas. Esprit, 265(7), 69–87.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ombrosi, O. (2006). “Unnecessary suffering: the end of theodicy according to E. Levinas”. Souffrances inutiles: La fin de la théodicée d’après E. Levinas. Gregorianum, 87(2), 368–379.

    Google Scholar 

  • Overgaard, S. (2004). Husserl and Heidegger on being in the world. Kluwer Academic publishers.

  • Patočka, J. (1999). Body, community, language, world. Open Court.

  • Prášek, P. (2021). Personal uniqueness and events. Human Studies, 44, 721–740. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-021-09597-0. Advance online publication.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prášek, P. Levinas vs. Maldiney: On a face of sensible nature. Forthocoming for the Journal of British Society for Phenomenology.

  • Purcell, M. (1995). The mystery of death alterity and affectivity in Levinas. New Blackfriars, 76(899), 524–534.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rolland., J. (2000). Postscript: on the other man. In E. Levinas (Ed.), God, death, and time (pp. 225–239). Standford University Press.

  • Sealey, K. (2010). Levinas’s early account of transcendence. Levinas Studies, 5, 99–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sebbah, F. D. (2016). „There is and ethical vigilance.“ Il y a et vigilance éthique. Intellectica Revue de l’Association pour la Recherche Cognitive, 66, 57–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • The Holy Bible. (2016). English standard version. Available at www.biblegateway.com.

Download references

Funding

The “Face of Nature” in Contemporary French Phenomenology-Czech Science Foundation, GAP 21-22224 S, realized at the Czech Academy of Science, Institute of Philosophy.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniela Matysová.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Matysová, D. The World and Its Nightmare (Levinas on Sense and Nonsense). Hum Stud 46, 79–99 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-023-09662-w

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-023-09662-w

Keywords

Navigation