1 Introduction

Ket is the last still spoken of the indigenous Yeniseian languages of Krasnoyarsk Krai in central Siberia (Russia). The Ket verb is often described as polysynthetic (Vajda, 2017b), and exhibits many traits characteristic of what Fortescue (2013) terms an old polysynthetic language: the verbal system is the product of what Fortescue calls ‘successive historical layering, with fossilization’, wherein many chronologically distinct waves of new material have been grammaticalized on top of existing material, as older components of the verb have been switched around, fused together, or had their functions reanalyzed (Vajda, 2010, 2013). The end result is a system in which inflectional categories are often expressed discontinuously, redundantly, and with tremendous variability from one verb to another.

One example of this is the way that Ket indexes verbal arguments. In Ket, both subjects and direct objectsFootnote 1 are indexed on transitive verbs. However, the way that this is done varies significantly from one verb to another. For example, the verbs in (1) and (2) mark their subjects in the same way (k), but use different markers, occurring at different positions in the string, for the object (d and ba respectively).Footnote 2

Necessary background on Ket verbal morphology, including an explanation of the given segmentations, is provided in §3. For Ket’s usually discontinuous stems, this paper follows one of the practices suggested in the Leipzig Glossing Rules, glossing the first lexical morph in the string with the meaning of the entire lexeme and the remaining lexical morphs with stem.Footnote 3

  1. (1)
    figure a
  1. (2)
    figure b

This difference between the two verbs holds not only for 1st person singular objects, but for any object, cf. kusq-aj-da ‘you warm him up’, kusq-ij-da ‘you warm her up’, etc. vs. kej-a-ɣava ‘you throw him’, kej-i-ɣava ‘you throw her’, and so on.

Now consider another verb, shown in (3). This verb marks its object in the same way as (1) (d), but marks its subject twice (k and ku) redundantly.

  1. (3)
    figure c

Again, this double subject marking is maintained throughout the paradigm, cf. da=bu-gdit ‘she carries me’, dbo-gbit ‘I carry it’, and so on.

This type of variability between verbs is characteristic of the system as a whole. In Ket, different verbs mark their subjects and objects using different markers in different combinations. As previous Ketological literature has demonstrated, it is usually not possible to predict which markers a verb will use to mark its arguments (subjects for intransitive verbs, subjects and direct objects for transitive) based on any syntactic, semantic, or phonological properties of the verb (Vajda, 2015). In other words, despite the best efforts of some Ket scholars in the past to prove otherwise (Reshetnikov & Starostin, 1995; Butorin, 1995; Belimov, 1991), the complexities of Ket argument marking are purely morphological, in the sense of Aronoff (1994), with the verbal lexicon being divided into a fairly complex system of inflection classes.

Building on this established analysis from the Ketological literature, this paper adds the following observation: within Ket’s inflectional class system, the same material is very frequently reused with different functions across different classes. The same marker that indexes the subject in one verb can index the object in another, and vice-versa.Footnote 4 Consider the marker ba (1.sg), which marks the object in example (2). It can also mark the subject alone:

  1. (4)
    figure d

Cf. ‘they spend the day’.Footnote 5

Or it can be a co-exponentFootnote 6 of the subject with another marker:

  1. (5)
    figure e

Cf. k-aɣa-ɣu-tsaq ‘you make a quick trip to the forest and return’ [VZ 116–177].

In some verbs, the same material used to index subjects and objects can even serve completely unrelated functions. For example, o can mark 3m arguments in the past tense.Footnote 7

  1. (6)
    figure f

cf. end-iru-nsuk ‘she forgot’, en-ba-nsuk ‘I forgot’ [KN 489].

However, it can also mark just past tense, without having any argument-marking function. In the following example, the subject is marked by ba.Footnote 8

  1. (7)
    figure g

This phenomenon, where the same formal material is used systemically to encode different functions is called polyfunctionality (Stump, 2014, 2015).Footnote 9 This paper understands this term broadly, referring to any instance of a many-to-one mapping between function and form. This includes both the use of the same marker to encode different function across different lexemes (as is the case in 4-7 above), and the use the same marker to encode different functions across different forms of the same lexeme (in other words, syncretism). This follows the definition given in Stump (2014, p. 73): “In the domain of inflectional morphology, polyfunctionality is the use of the same morphology in the expression of distinct morphosyntactic property sets. Inflectional polyfunctionality is observable both within and across paradigms and even within individual word forms”.

Polyfunctionality represents a type of morphological complexity (Baerman et al., 2017), and more specifically a phenomenon known as complexity of exponence (Anderson, 2015), in which the relationship between grammatical information (e.g. tense, person) and the formal units which are used to encode it (e.g. affixes, stem changes, tones) is non-isomorphic (not one-to-one) or otherwise opaque.

Recent years have seen an increased interest in morphological complexity (see Arkadiev & Gardani, 2020 for a recent overview), including complexity of exponence. Much of this work has focused on the communicative challenges which morphological complexity would seem logically to create. Roughly, if the same information can be encoded in different ways in different contexts, how does the language user determine how that information is or should be encoded in any particular form? The type of apparent communicative challenge presented by a system like Ket is well formulated as the Inflected Word Recognition Problem (IWRP) in Bonami and Beniamine (2021):

  1. (8)

    Inflected Word Recognition Problem (Bonami & Beniamine, 2021, p. 82)

    What allows speakers to draw inferences from a word’s form to its content?

In another words, as applied specifically to Ket:

In a language like Ket, in which the same formal material is frequently associated with different functions in different wordforms, how might a listener encountering a novel form understand which of these possible functions was intended in the given form?

It is assumed that many sources of information could aid the listener in this task – syntactic context, discourse context, the semantics of a given verb – however, this paper investigates only one, a property of morphological systems know as implicative structure (Wurzel, 1984). This can be understood as interdependencies between elements within a morphological system.

Implicative structure has been a major theme in recent work on morphological complexity, with much of it focusing paradigmatic implicative structure, or interdependencies between whole words within an inflectional paradigm. Building on the established model of Ket’s unique argument-marking and tense-marking morphology, (Nefedov & Vajda, 2015; Vajda, 2014, 2015; Georg, 2007; Nefedov, 2015, inter alia), using data drawn from both published sourcesFootnote 10 and original fieldwork,Footnote 11 this paper departs from previous work on the role of implicative structure in morphology, focusing instead on syntagmatic implicative structure – interdependencies between subword pieces. It demonstrates that uncertainty concerning the function of a polyfunctional marker in a given verbform can be greatly reduced through implicative relations which hold between that marker and other markers in the same wordform. The Ket case makes broader typological predictions about the hypothesized limits of complexity of exponence and its relationship with implicative structure.

The structure of this paper is as follows. Section 2 lays out the background on morphological complexity. Section 3 provides necessary background on relevant aspects of the Ket verbal system. Sections 4 an provides an overview of polyfunctionality in the Ket argument-marking system. Section 5 lays out examples of implicative structure between markers. Section 6 discusses the relationship between the Ket system and some other types of highly complex exponence discussed in the literature, namely Gestalt Exponence (Blevins, 2016, inter alia), and Distributed Exponence (Carroll, 2022). Section 7 provides further discussion and concludes.

2 Complexity of exponence and implicative structure

Before discussing polyfunctionality in Ket argument marking (in §4), and how syntagmatic structure could help to resolve the challenges associated with it (§5), it is necessary to start with some background, which this section aims to provide. It is divided into three subsections.

Section 2.1 expands upon the central notion of complexity of exponence, the term used in this paper to refer to non-isomorphic form-meaning mappings. It clarifies what this means, and discusses what phenomena are understood to contribute to, as well as not contribute to, complexity of exponence for a particular language.

Section 2.2 discusses several inter-related issues. It discusses further the Inflected Word Recognition Problem as well as the related Paradigm Cell Filling Problem, used to illustrate the way in which implicative structure can be used to resolve the communicative challenges associated with complexform-meaningmappings. This section also introduces the information theoretic notions of entropy and conditional entropy, which provide a more precise way of talking about implicative structure and the role that it plays in a particular morphological system.

Finally, §2.3 suggests that the role of implicative structure in morphology is much broader than previous work has explored, namely that it has not explored the relationship between implicative structure and other types of complexity of exponence which do not directly bear on the PCFP, such as polyfunctionality. It has also not explored how languages with a large number of polyfunctional markers might use implicative structure differently. An exploration of the role played by syntagmatic implicative structure in resolving polyfunctionalform-meaningmappings in Ket is presented as a contribution to the framework.

2.1 Complexity of exponence

Nearly any discussion of inflectional morphology from a cross-linguistic perspective will note that it is a point of massive cross-linguistic variation. Some languages are conventionally understood to lack inflectional morphology entirely (Vietnamese, Yoruba), while others have massive inflectional paradigms (Archi). Some languages have essentially no inflection classes (Turkish), while others have hundreds (Chinantec verbs). Such observations have prompted a sizeable literature on how to conceptualize and measure the complexity of morphological systems. For overviews, see the introductory chapters of Baerman et al. (2015) and Arkadiev and Gardani (2020).

This paper focuses on one particular dimension of morphological complexity, which Anderson (2015) refers to as complexity of exponence. Essentially the same notion, with subtle differences, has also been referred to as non-canonicity of exponence (Baerman et al., 2017), non-linearity (Dahl, 2004, 2017), and opacity (Hengeveld, 2011; Trudgill, 2020). Complexity of exponence refers to those cases where there is a non-isomorphic relationship between units of meaning and units of form across the lexicon. In other words, there is not a one-to-one mapping between a unit of information (grammatical or lexical) and the formal material that is used to encode that information (i.e. affixes, stem changes, tones). Examples of non-isomorphic relationships (outlines in more detail in Table 1) include phenomena like allomorphy, cumulative exponence (i.e. fusion), Multiple Exponence (Harris, 2017), also known as Extended Exponence (Matthews, 1972) and, as has already been noted, polyfunctionality (Stump, 2015, 2014). The more a morphological system instantiates any of the above, the higher its complexity of exponence. Examples of complexity of exponence are given in Table 1.

Table 1 Examples of complexity of exponence

As noted in §1, this paper understands the term polyfunctionality broadly (in concurrence with Stump, 2014), encompassing any type of many-to-one mapping between meaning and form. Polyfunctionality of markers can arise through the reuse of material across different cells of the same paradigm (e.g. -en in German verbs marks the infinitive, 1pl.prs and 3pl.prs, a case of classical syncretismFootnote 12), across different inflection classes (e.g. -u in Russian marks accusative singular with class I nouns, but dative singular with class II nouns), and across different morphosyntactic categories (e.g. person/number suffixes in Nenets mark possessors on nouns and direct objects on verbs).

Complexity of exponence is not directly related to the number of distinct categories which a morphological system distinguishes (i.e. the number of cells in a paradigm), or to the amount of information that can be expressed in a single wordform (i.e. the degree of synthesis, cf. Bickel & Nichols, 2007). Some extremely complex systems involve very small paradigms and only a few formatives per wordform. For example, nominal inflection in Nuer (Baerman, 2012) involves only 3 distinct forms per lexeme and a small number of formatives per wordform (a stem, which may undergo alternations, plus a suffix), but the system exhibits a massive amount of allomorphy and unpredictable syncretism. Conversely, systems with very large paradigms and a very high degree of synthesis may be very simple if the relationship between formatives and the functions which they encode is very transparent and consistent across the lexicon. This would be the case with, for example, Turkic languages.Footnote 13

When there is a non-isomorphic relationship between form and function across different lexemes, then this creates inflection classes, groupings of lexemes which encode information in the same way, different from other groups of lexemes (as a phenomenon, this is sometimes called flexivity, Bickel & Nichols, 2007).

Inflection classes have been the primary focus of much of the literature on morphological complexity, because they makes things more difficult for the language user. For a speaker of a language with inflection classes, it is not enough to know what information they want to encode (i.e. what case or what tense to use); they must also know how to encode that information for a particular lexeme. For the listener, inflection classes make things more difficult when the formal material used to encode a particular feature in one class is used to encode different information in another class (i.e. when allomorphy creates polyfunctionality). A quite sizeable literature has developed around the communicative task posed to speakers (for good reason, as the problem is much bigger than it might seem at first glance). The next sections aims to introduce the reader to this literature.

2.2 The paradigm cell filling problem and conditional entropy

As noted in the last section, the presence of inflection classes in a language forces a speaker of that language to know, for every inflected lexeme, not only what information to encode, but also how to encode it.

The speaker must be able to do this without any guarantee of having heard the form that they want to use before. This is because linguistic input follows a Zipfian distribution, where a small number of forms are very common, while all other forms may be vanishingly rare. Studies have shown that even increasingly large corpora may never contain all inflected forms for morphologically complex languages (Baayen, 2002; Blevins et al., 2017; Sims & Parker, 2016) and have suggested that the need to predict unknown forms continues throughout the lifespan (Bonami & Beniamine, 2016; Sims & Parker, 2016).

Work beginning with Ackerman et al. (2009) terms the puzzle of how speakers are able to predict all forms of all lexemes based on at best some subset of them the Paradigm Cell Filling Problem, and as the solution it implicates the property of morphological systems known as implicative structure (Wurzel, 1984). A language exhibits implicative structure if known forms provide information which can be used to predict unknown forms.

Implicative structure is a property, at minimum, of inflectional paradigms. An inflectional paradigm refers to all inflected forms of the same lexeme taken collectively.Footnote 14 As an example of how these exhibit implicative structure, consider a highly simplified version of Russian nominal inflection in the singular (excluding stress), given in Table 2.

Table 2 Russian 1st, 2nd and 3rd Nominal Inflection Classes (singular forms, without stress)

Russian nouns provide an example of implicative structure at work. Case and number are encoded cumulatively using inflectional suffixes. However, the same value can be encoded with one of several different suffixes (different allomorphs) depending on the noun: dative singular with -e, -u or -i, instrumental singular with -oj, -om, or -ju, and so on.

The task of predicting which allomorph will go with which noun however is made much simpler by the fact that they co-vary to a great extent with one another. If a user of Russian knows e.g. that a given noun has an accusative singular in -u, they know that (almost always) the dative singular suffix will have -e and not -u, and the instrumental will have -oj and not -om, and so on.

The more forms that one knows, the easier this task becomes. For example, the suffix -i for the genitive singular is shared between declensions I and III, making it poorly predictive of the other forms. However, if the speaker knows any other form in addition to the genitive, then this is enough to predict all other forms.Footnote 15

The networks of implicative relations that are learned based on frequent lexemes can then be analogized to produce new forms, allowing the speaker to accurately predict all forms of even very rare lexemes. For example, suppose that a Russian-user has never encountered the form ‘a seasonal migration by reindeer caravan among Siberian peoples (dative singular)’. If they know that this is the dative singular from the syntactic context, then they can be reasonably certain that the genitive singular will be , without having ever encountered it before.Footnote 16

Although most previous work has focused on the communicative challenge associated with producing novel forms (with encoding), some recent work has shown a shift towards the task of comprehending novel forms (with decoding) (Bonami & Beniamine, 2021), and with its relationship with complexity of exponence (Carroll, 2022). This is the so-called Inflected Word Recognition Problem, cited in §1. This paper represents an extension of this line of research.

The next section discuses in more detail the implications of information theoretic approaches to morphology for complexity of exponence specifically.

2.3 Implicative structure, decoding, and polyfunctionality

Information theoretic approaches to morphology, like those outlined above, have underscored how implicative structure can be used in a language to resolve complex form-function mappings.

At the same time, the full ramifications of this model for different kinds of morphological complexity has not been sufficiently explored. As work in this area largely originates from attempts to solve the Paradigm Cell Filling Problem, it has largely focused on certain types of complexity of exponence which are directly relevant to the PCFP, while not exploring the implications of its findings for other types of complexity.Footnote 17 Some kinds of complexity of exponence, like affix, stem, or tonal allomorphy are directly related to the PCFP. If the same information can be encoded in many different ways across different lexemes, this creates a challenge for the speaker in solving the PCFP. These phenomena, as such, have been a major point of study.

Other kinds of complexity of exponence, like polyfunctionality, do not directly relate to the PCFP. If the same formal material can encode different functions, this is not a major problem in solving the PCFP, since the speaker presumably knows which meaning they intended.Footnote 18 It is a problem however for the listener, who must determine which meaning was intended, which, for a language with very high exponence complexity, may be a non-trivial task. As such, most previous literature has focused primarily on communicative challenges in encoding information (which exponent is needed for this lexeme?), not in decoding information (which of the things this exponent can mean does it mean in this form?).

Owing to its origins, previous work has also focused almost exclusively on implicative structure within paradigms, and has not focused on how other types of implicative structure might be important for resolving complexform-meaningmappings in languages with diverse morphological structures.

The remainder of this paper sets out to begin filling these gaps. It makes two proposals. The first is that high predictability (low conditional entropy) is a necessary property of morphological systems when mapping from form to meaning, not only from meaning to form. In other words, uncertainty must be low for both the speaker and the listener, and in some languages implicative structure plays a crucial role in achieving this.

The second is that the importance of implicative structure in decoding is a point of cross-linguistic variation. This builds on work by Sims and Parker (2016), who demonstrate that the amount of ‘work’ done by implicative structure in predicting unknown forms (formally, the difference between entropy and conditional entropy) varies across languages. However, the present paper also goes further, proposing that the role of implicative structure across different languages varies not only quantitatively, in the amount of work done by implicative structure, but also qualitatively, in the kind of implicative structure that systems exhibit. More specifically, it is argued that for some languages, as illustrated with Ket, implicative structure is found not only within networks of related words, but also between individual morphs in wordforms. This type of structure is hypothesized to be an adaptation characteristic of languages with very high complexity of exponence, especially those which are strongly head-marking, equivalent to the notion of an old polysynthetic language, proposed by Fortescue (2013).

To illustrate an example of both points, consider again the Russian example of a rare form ‘a seasonal migration by reindeer caravan among Siberia peoples’ (dative singular). The suffix -u in this word could hypothetically encode either the dative (II declension) or the accusative (I declension). However, encountering another form, like the nominative singular argiʂ would disambiguate the function of -u in the first case (since if it encoded the accusative, the nominative should be encoded with -a). Footnote 19

In actual practice though, the need to rely on implicative structure for this purpose in a language like Russian is likely to be quite low; Russian is strongly dependent marking and has robust case/number/gender agreement on nominal modifiers, and hence the syntactic context of a given form provides ample opportunity for disambiguating its function. A quick websearch is enough to confirm this, as in the actual title for an article about an event dedicated to the memory of the Nenets writer Leonid Laptsuy, given in example (9).Footnote 20

  1. (9)
    figure h

Here is clearly the complement of the predicative adjective podobna ‘similar (to)’, which invariably takes a complement in the dative, and not the accusative.Footnote 21 Implicative structure could help disambiguate the form, but the need to rely on it for this function is low.

This is not the case for all languages though. By contrast, consider the sentence ‘they migrated seasonally, made the argish’ in the northern dialect of Ket.Footnote 22 This is a perfectly grammatical sentence by itself, with no syntactic information available outside the verbform.

Like many Ket verbs, the way that the subject is marked for this verb is fairly complex (a full discussion of the Ket verbal system is given in the next section). It exhibits Multiple Exponence, marking the subject (and the past tense) twice. Three of the markers associated with marking subjects, d, bu, and o, are all, on their own, partially ambiguous with regard to their function.

However, the function of each of these markers can be disambiguated by the presence of other markers in the verbform. The combination of the prefix d (person) and the suffix in (pl.number) indicates that the subject of the verb is either 1.pl or 3.pl but leaves it ambiguous as to which. The marker bu redundantly encodes a 3rd person subject, ambiguous as to whether it is masculine, feminine, or plural. However, bu is a special form that indicates it is a co-exponent with a subject marker d-. The presence of bu therefore disambiguates the person encoded by d. The presence of in in turn makes it clear that bu encodes a 3pl subject, and not 3m or 3f. Finally, o always encodes past tense, but in some verbs additionally encodes a 3rd person masculine singular argument (which can be either the subject or object). The fact that the subject-marking function is absent here is not discernible by considering the marker itself in isolation, but can be discerned by looking at other markers. Among other things (discussed in §5), its number value here is incompatible with in.

To make things clearer, we can represent implicative structure between morphs using a dependency graph, shown in Fig. 1, with the arrows representing information that the markers at the beginning of the arrow provide about the function associated with the marker at the end of the arrow. Note that, although in this case morphs later in the string provide information about those earlier in the string, in Ket, these dependencies can go in any direction; morphs earlier in the string can also provide information about the function of morphs later in the string as well, as will be seen later on.

Fig. 1
figure 1

Syntagmatic implicative structure in the Ket verb

Putting all of this together, the structure of nearly every component in the verb is unambiguous, and the meaning of all components in the verb is less ambiguous,Footnote 23 as shown in Fig. 1.Footnote 24

  1. (10)
    figure m

As this example illustrates, in Ket verbs, we see a similar dynamic playing out at the syntagmatic level as has been described for the structure of paradigms in other languages. Even though many individual morphs are polyfunctional, any potential ambiguity is greatly reduced by implicative structure which holds between morphs.

Of course, implicative structure between morphs does not need to do all the work. Presence of a full NP (e.g. ‘people’) or an overt pronoun (e.g. ‘they’), or knowledge of related forms, or simply discourse context, could all accomplish some of the decoding work done by implicative structure in this example. Similarly, the fact that implicative structure exists in the syntagmatic structure is not direct evidence that it is used by Ket listeners.

Nevertheless, the fact that implicative structure allows for such a striking difference between the language’s very high complexity of exponence and actual ambiguity is highly suggestive of the idea that such structure is a communicative adaptation. This is especially the case for a head-marking language with prodrop,Footnote 25 like Ket, in which examples like the above, with just a verbform, may constitute a substantial portion of the input.

The remainder of this paper strives to develop of a more complete understanding of the role of implicative structure, as a formal organizational property of the system, in Ket argument marking. The next section lays out essential background information on the overall structure of the Ket verb.

3 Background on Ket verbal morphology

As noted in §1, the Ket verb is often described as polysynthetic (Vajda, 2017b), and exhibits many traits characteristic of an old polysynthetic language (Fortescue, 2013). Waves of chronologically distinct material have been grammaticalized on top of existing material, as older components of the verb have been metathesized, fused together, or reanalyzed (Vajda, 2010, 2017a), producing a seemingly random interdigitation of inflectional, derivational, and lexical material.

The resulting system is often described as templatic, meaning simply that the order of morphs in the verb reflects the grammaticalization history and is not derivable from semantic scope or abstract syntactic structure in any obvious way (see Mithun, 2011 for a defense of this assessment and parallel developments in NavajoFootnote 26). Specific templatic models have been used to describe the Ket verb since the 1990s (Reshetnikov & Starostin, 1995; Butorin, 1995; Werner, 1997; Vajda, 2001, 2003, 2004). Such models, similar to those used for the Na-Dene languages, divide the verb into a fixed number of morphological ‘slots’, or position classes (P), which different markers can be said to occupy. Table 3 gives a simplified version of the current predominant templatic model of the Ket verb, adapted from Nefedov and Vajda (2015).Footnote 27

Table 3 Templatic model of the Ket verb (simplified from Nefedov & Vajda, 2015, p. 36)

As the templatic model shows, the Ket verb goes against cross-linguistic tendencies in affix ordering. The stem, whose internal structure is not considered in this paper, consists of up to three discontinuous pieces (P7-P5-P0), which are interdigitated with markers that indicate the subject and object, tense, or some limited valence-changing operations.Footnote 28 The templatic model also gives some sense of the complexity of the argument-marking system. Argument markers are copious, all but one of the sets of argument markers can mark either the subject or the object, and many of the argument markers in the area P4-P1 represent a fusion or reanalysis of historically distinct markers, and alternatively or simultaneously encode completely orthogonal functions (tense, valence, or seemingly nothing at all).

Templatic models like the above should not be seen as explanatory mechanisms or as something cognitively real. Rather, as (Crippen, 2012, p. 43) puts it for Tlingit, a templatic model should be understood as “merely a descriptive tool that aids in understanding the positions and interrelationships of different morphological elements within the verb.” Elements assigned to the same position class are those which are in paradigmatic opposition (complementary distribution) and share the same morphotactic behavior (occur in the same position in the string), even if they have contradictory or orthogonal functions (cf. discussion in Vajda, 2001, pp. 371–372). In this sense, a position class is equivalent to Gurevich (2006, p. 8)’s notion of a distribution/form class.

To underscore this point, this paper deviates from previous Ketological work in that it avoids the metaphor of a position class as a ‘slot’, which markers ‘occupy’ or ‘fill’. Instead, it takes the position classes as labels for sets of markers. For example, rather than saying that “ba occupies P6”, it will refer to the “P6 set of markers” (={ba, ku, a, i...}), which are in complementary distribution and share the same morphotactic behavior. This removes an unnecessary level of abstraction.Footnote 29

Something that is not immediately apparent from the templatic class model is the tremendous variability across Ket verbs. Of the three possible stem-components, only the one represented in Vajda’s model by P0 is present in all verbs. In the tense system, one of two different tense markers represented by P4 (s∼∅ and ao, where npstpst) may or may not be present. Finally, the argument-marking system is the most variable and complex, and the remainder of this section turns to describing it in more detail.

3.1 Argument markers

The main sources of morphological complexity in the Ket verb is the way that the system marks verbal arguments. Ket indexes up to two arguments verb-internally, usually a subject and a direct object (although some trivalent verbs require agreement with the indirect object over the direct object).

Verbs make use of essentially three distinct sets of markers. This paper refers to these sets using the names of the corresponding postion classes in Vajda’s templatic model. These are the P8 set, the P6 set, and the P4/P3/P1 set respectively. In older literature (e.g. Krejnovich, 1968), the equivalent labels are the di/du, ba/a and di/a sets (based on the 1s and 3m forms respectively).Footnote 30

These sets of markers are distinct both in their segmental content (with some overlap across sets) and in their ordering relative to other morphs, when such morphs are present. This section will examine each of the sets in turn. A summary of all argument markers is given in Table 4.Footnote 31

Table 4 Summary of Ket argument markers (based on Nefedov and Vajda (2015, pg. 38))

The P8 set of markers, shown in Table 4, occur at the leftmost edge of the verb. It only indexes the person and (for the 3rd person) the gender of the argument, whereas the other sets mark person/gender and number cumulatively. Many verbs use the suffix -in (P-1 in Vajda’s model), in conjunction with the P8 set to indicate a plural subject.

In examples throughout, indices below a morph represent the position class to which it belongs.Footnote 32

  1. (11)
    figure n
  1. (12)
    figure o

The P8 markers show distinct long (12) and short (13) variants. The long variants, with a vowel, appear only with certain basic verbs and only in the non-past.Footnote 33 The short forms show less phonological boundedness with the verb than do other verbal affixes, and in certain phonological environments may be pronounced separately, or appended to the preceding word (13), or elided altogether except in very careful speech. The phonological details necessarily fall outside the scope of this paper, but in relevant instances I represent the short P8 markers as clitics (=). I return to this issue in Sect. 5.6.

  1. (13)
    figure p
  1. (14)
    figure q

The P6 set of markers appears to the right of the P8 set and any P7 lexical morphs, if the latter are present, and to the left of all other components of the verb.Footnote 34

  1. (15)
    figure r
  1. (16)
    figure s

The P4/P3/P1 set of markers, is the oldest, and shows many complexities which the other sets do not. For one thing, the 3rd person animate markers cumulatively mark tense (pst/npst) alongside person, which is not true of any other argument markers.

The basis for splitting this set into three distinct position classes, an innovation introduced in Vajda (2001, 2003, 2004), is twofold. First, the third person animate markers occur to the left of the past tense markers {l, n}, while the 1st/2nd person markers occur to their right.

  1. (17)
    figure t
  1. (18)
    figure u
  1. (19)
    figure v

This variable morphotactic behavior is not exhibited by the special ‘jointly-indexed’ 3rd person forms, a and , which occur in the same position as 1/2 markers.Footnote 35

  1. (20)
    figure y

Second, the three subsets differ from one another in their relationship to other markers. Each of the subsets shows identical morphotactic behavior with, and is in complementary distribution with, at least one marker that is not in complementary distribution with the members of the larger set.

It may be helpful to visualize this using some actual modified set notation. In Fig. 2, markers which are in complementary distribution are shown as belonging to the same set.

Fig. 2
figure 2

Set Representation of the P4/P3/P1 Position Classes: solid lines share the same morphotactic behavior, dashed lines also share phonological material

The P4 argument markers {ajo, ijdit/iru,}, for example, are in complementary distribution with the P1 and P3 sets of argument markers, and hence are elements in the same superset. However, they are also in complementary distribution with, and occur in the same position in the string as, the tense markers {ao, s∼∅} (npstpst). At the same time, the tense markers {ao, s∼∅} are not in complementary distribution with the P3 or P1 argument markers.

As an illustration, consider the forms in (21)–(23). The tense marker ao (here a for npst) freely co-occurs with b and daŋ (v and due to lenition, see fn. 31), but cannot co-occur with ij.

  1. (21)
    figure aa
  1. (22)
    figure ab
  1. (23)
    figure ac

This same relationship holds between the P1 argument markers and the resultative marker a and between the argument marker b and the empty morph b (see §4.2).

Those sets which are encircled by dashed lines represent markers which show not only the same morphotactic behavior (they show up in the same position in the string, and it is not possible to have more than one of them in a single form), but also share the same phonological material in at least some instances. The tense marker ao and the cumulative argument/tense marker ajo are usually (but not always) distinct in the non-past (a vs aj), but are formally (i.e. phonologically and morphotactically) identical in the past (as o, seen already in ‘they migrated’ in §2.3).Footnote 36 The two a’s and two b’s, on the other hand, show complete formal identity in all cases.

All three pairs are the result of historical reanalysis, wherein the form and distribution of a marker has been altered through it being equated with another, historically unrelated, marker (Vajda, 2010). As such, their similarity clearly goes beyond accidental homophony. This leaves the difficult analytical question of whether these pairs are instantiations of the same marker, or not. Even if this were merely a case of accidental syncretism within the paradigm,Footnote 37 these pairs would still fit the definition of polyfunctionality used in this paper as “reuse of the same formal material with different functions”, and their formal identity clearly present a challenge for a listener, attempting to determine what each marker in a given verbform does. As such, given the narrow analytical focus of this paper, as investigating the information available to a listener in accomplishing exactly this task, this paper treats these pairs as instances of the the same polyfunctional marker in those cases where they are homophonous, while acknowledging that different analytical choices might be appropriate under different analytical goals.

These markers have an important role to play in the story, and are revisited in §4 and §5.

Finally, returning to Fig. 1, there is one marginal exception to the given generalizations, that being that b (3n) and a (3.joint) can co-occur in class IV intransitive verbs, which is seemingly a by-product of the interaction of two separate families of constructions which these markers participate in (more on this in §3.2).

3.2 Argument-marking classes

Arguments are indexed using different combinations of these markers. The choice of which sets of markers are used to mark which arguments defines a given verb as a member of a particular inflection class. Classes are split according to transitivity, but among verbs of the same transitivity, class membership is largely arbitrary, and is usually not predictable from any semantic, syntactic, or phonological property of the given verb, although certain semantic clusterings can be observed within the classes, and certain constructions require a particular argument-marking pattern (Vajda, 2015).

This paper will refer to verbs which exhibit the same argument-marking pattern as belonging to the same argument-marking class, and will follow the system developed in Vajda (2015), Nefedov and Vajda (2015), Nefedov (2015), and Kotorova and Nefedov (2015), which classifies verbs into nine classes.

A summary of the intransitive argument-marking classes is given in Table 5. Note that classes v3 and v4 multiply expone the subject.

Table 5 Summary of Ket intransitive argument-marking classes

Intransitive class 1 (v1) verbs mark their subjects with the P8 (di/du) marker set, as in (24).

  1. (24)
    figure af

Verbs of this class typically show an animacy split, where they mark neuter-class 3rd person subjects not with a member of the P8 set, but instead with the 3n marker from the P4/P3/P1 (di/a), b (here lenited to v, see footnote 31).

  1. (25)
    figure ag

This is not always the case though, and some neuter subjects, particularly those that are perceived as playing a more active role in the event, are instead marked like feminine nouns.

  1. (26)
    figure ah

Intransitive class II verbs (v2) mark their subjects with the P6 (ba/a) set.

  1. (27)
    figure ai

Intransitive class III (v3) verbs mark their subjects with both the P8 (di/du) set and the P6 (ba/a) set.

  1. (28)
    figure aj
  1. (29)
    figure ak

As mentioned briefly in §2.3, the 3rd person members of the P6 set have a special ‘jointly-indexed’ form (this author’s term) bu, which is shared across classes. This marker is used only in the 3rd person by verbs which use Multiple Exponence of the subject (i.e. the P6 markers alongside another marker set, which for the P6 set is always the P8 markers).

  1. (30)
    figure al

Intransitive class 4 (v4) verbs mark their subjects with both the P8 (di/du) set and the P4/P3/P1 (di/a) set.

  1. (31)
    figure am
  1. (32)
    figure an

As with v3 verbs, there are special ‘jointly-indexed’ forms for the 3rd person P4/P3/P1 markers. Unlike v3, these distinguish number (a for s, for pl) and show different morphotactic behavior, occurring immediately before the right-most part of the stem.

  1. (33)
    figure ao

Like v1 verbs, this class also marks neuter subjects differently, using b from the P4/P3/P1 set in place of a marker from the P8 set.

  1. (34)
    figure ap

There are some verbs which show a mixed v1/v4 class, following the v1 pattern with singular subjects, but the v4 pattern with plural subjects.

  1. (35)
    figure aq

Finally, intransitive class 5 verbs mark their subject using the P4/P3/P1 (di/a) set.

  1. (36)
    figure ar
  1. (37)
    figure as

The model adopted here distinguishes four transitive argument-marking classes, a summary of which is given in Table 6. Note that each verb marks only one object, but for those that use the P4/P3/P1 markers for the object, which of the three subsets is used depends on person and animacy (as was the case before with v5 verbs which P4/P3/P1 markers for subjects).

Table 6 Summary of Ket transitive argument-marking classes

Note that, while the transitive classes are labelled by analogy with the intransitive classes which share the same subject-marking pattern (except for transitive class 2 and intransitive class 2, where the object of the former is marked like the subject of the latter), this convention is simply an artefact of how the analysis developed over time. The transitive classes are different inflection classes from the intransitive classes, and could just as appropriately be labelled classes 6–9, or something equivalent.

Transitive class 1 (vt1) verbs mark their subjects with the P8 (di/du) set and their objects with the P4/P3/P1 (di/a) set.

  1. (38)
    figure at

Transitive class II (vt2) verbs mark their subjects using the P8 (di/du) set and their objects using the P6 (ba/a) set.

  1. (39)
    figure au

Transitive class III (vt3) verbs mark their subjects using both the P8 (di/du) set and the P6 (ba/a) set, and mark their objects using the P4/P3/P1 (di/a) set. Like v3 verbs, the P6 set has a special ‘jointly-indexed’ form bu for 3rd person arguments.

  1. (40)
    figure av

Transitive class IV (vt4) verbs mark their subjects using both the P8 (di/du) and the P4/P3/P1 set. Like v4 verbs, the P4/P3/P1 set has special jointly-indexed forms for 3rd person arguments, a and , occurring immediately before the right-most part of the stem. This class is very small and is limited to a few lexemes (Vajda, 2015).

  1. (41)
    figure aw

Having laid out this necessary background on the Ket verb, the next section turns directly to the issue of polyfunctionality in the Ket verb.

4 Polyfunctionality in the Ket verb

The last section laid out the relevant components of the predominant model of Ket verbal morphology established in the Ketological literature, with some slight conceptual and terminological changes.Footnote 38 Assuming this model as a foundation, this section is now able to demonstrate how Ket argument markers instantiate polyfunctionality, expanding upon issues that have been alluded to or touched upon in §3. This is followed in §5 by a discussion of how syntagmatic implicative structure could aid in resolving complex form-function mappings.

All cases of polyfunctionality in Ket in this paper relate to the argument-marking system. They can be divided into two groupings: cases where the same marker is reused with different functions within the argument-marking system, and cases where formal material is shared between the argument-marking system and some other subsystem of the language, such that the same marker may or may not encode an argument, depending on the form.

The former is discussed in detail in section §4.1. As for the latter, one instance of this has already been discussed in §3 (pp. 27–29), that being the relationship between the P4 tense marker ao (pstnpst), which encodes only tense, and the P4 argument marker ajo, which encodes both 3.sg.m arguments and tense cumulatively. The two markers are both morphotactically and phonologically identical in the past tense, and are treated for the purposes of this paper as representing a single polyfunctional marker in such cases.

The other instance concerns the relationship between the argument-marking system and the empty morph b, which has historically broken off from parts of the stem. This was mentioned briefly in section §3, and is discussed in full in §4.2.

4.1 Polyfunctionality within the argument-marking system

The broad observation that some markers can mark either the subject or the object was made already by Krejnovich (1968, pp. 22–23). As such, the present paper, like much of Ket linguistics, can be seen as an attempt to build on his observations using new theoretical tools.

Table 7 lays out whether a particular position class is associated with the subject or the object by inflection class. Recall that position classes here are understood as markers which have the same morphotactic behavior and are in complementary distribution. The P8 set always marks the subject, as do the special 3rd person ‘jointly-indexed’ forms of the P6 and P1 sets, but all other argument markers (P6, P4, P3, P1, except the 3rd person ‘jointly-indexed’ forms) can mark either the subject or the object.

Table 7 Argument marker sets by function (A/S/O) across classes

Lest one think that some of the markers are simply tracking different types of arguments,Footnote 39 we can break down the notion ‘subject’ further into transitive (A) and intransitive subjects (S), which gives us the distribution in Table 7.

As Table 10 shows, the P8, P6 and P1 markers are all readily associated with both transitive and intransitive subjects, depending on the class. What is the case is that all four transitive verb classes use the P8 marker set, alone or in addition to another argument marker. Hence, the P6 and P1 markers are never the sole exponents of a transitive subject (with some possible exceptions, see §5.4). Nevertheless, in transitive verbs they can freely mark either transitive subjects (alongside P8), or objects, in a way that is clearly not reducible to tracking a single argument.

Consider the following two verbs with the P6 marker ba, where ba in the first verb marks a transitive subject (along with the P8 marker d), while ba in the second marks an object.

  1. (42)
    figure ax
  1. (43)
    figure ay

For another example, the following two verbs with the P1 marker di, where in the first verb di marks a transitive subject along with the P8 marker d, and in the second di marks an object.

  1. (44)
    figure az
  1. (45)
    figure ba

The only markers associated with intransitive subjects but not transitive subjects are the P4 and P3 markers. Prefiguring the discussion in section §5, this gap has nothing to do with the type of arguments tracked by the P4 and P3 markers, but is instead because these two markers always encode the 3rd person. Since, in order to mark transitive subjects, they must be a co-exponent with a P8 marker, the special 3rd person co-referential form of the P4/P3/P1 markers, a1, is used instead.

4.2 Argument marking and empty morph b

Work as early as Krejnovich (1968, p. 38) has noted that b (phonetically often v or p), usually the 3rd person neuter member of the P4/P3/P1 argument marker set, appears in many verbs which lack any neuter argument. In such cases, it occurs throughout the paradigm and lacks any obvious grammatical function. However, it is phonologically identical with the neuter argument marker, which occurs in exactly the same morphotactic position – after any P4 marker and before the P2 past tense markers l and n.

For example, consider the partial paradigm of the verb ‘cover’, given in Table 8. Here the actual object is marked with the P6 marker set.Footnote 40

Table 8 Partial paradigm for

Compare this to a verb like ‘warm up’, given in Table 9, where b is a true agreement marker, in paradigmatic opposition to other P4/P3/P1 markers indicating the object. This case is far from anomalous: Kotorova and Nefedov (2015) list 921 verbs which have b throughout their paradigms.

Table 9 Partial paradigm for us7-q5-a4-da0 warm.up
Table 10 Possible functions for each set of potential argument markers

Based on comparison with Kott, Vajda (2017a, 2013) demonstrates that non-argument-marking cases of b derive historically from unrelated sources via metathesis from other parts of the stem, which were then reanalyzed.

Non-argument-marking b might be analyzed as an empty morph, a unit of form without any corresponding function or meaning (Hockett, 1947). Krejnovich (1968, p. 38) explicitly opts for this analysis, calling it an ‘empty morpheme’ (pustaja morfema). More recent literature has typically opted for more neutral, but also more idiosyncratic, terminology. Vajda (2013) and following work refers to non-agreement b, while Nefedov and Vajda (2015) talk about thematic b.

This paper adopts the empty morph analysis of Krejnovich (1968), and glosses b in relevant instances as such (em).

4.3 Summary of polyfunctionality in Ket and discussion

A useful concept in summarizing the Ket system is that of a potential argument marker, a marker that indicates arguments in at least some verbs. Taken together, all of the possible functions for Ket potential argument markers can be summarized as in Table 12.

5 Implicative relations in syntagmatic structure in Ket

This section lays out examples of implicative structure internal to Ket verbforms, between potential argument markers. Although these markers are highly polyfunctional across the language as a whole, the listener can often substantially narrow down the range of possible functions for a given potential argument marker based on which other potential argument markers are present in the same wordform, and which person/number/class features those markers encode.

It should be stressed that the purpose of this section is not to claim that Ket listeners do pick up on these patterns and use them in online processing, which is of course an empirical psycholinguistic question.Footnote 41 The point is simply to point out that these patterns exist, are available in the input, and allow for a massive formal difference between the range of possible functions for a given marker in the language as a whole, and the range of possible functions which that marker can have in context.

5.1 Single argument marker

The absence of other potential argument markers implies that the marker that is present indicates an intransitive subject.

  1. (46)
    figure bb
  1. (47)
    figure bc
  1. (48)
    figure bd

5.2 More reliable markers disambiguate less reliable ones

Ket potential arguments markers can be organized along a scale, from least to most polyfunctional, depending on how greatly their functions can vary across different lexemes. Recall that bu6 and a1 are the special ‘jointly-indexed’ 3rd person forms of the P6 and P4/P3/P1 sets respectively.

  1. (49)

    P8 set, bu6, a1 >>P6 set, P1 set, P4 set (not o4) >> o4, b3

A frequent phenomenon is that the presence of markers further to the left along this scale has implications which help to disambiguate the intended function of the markers further to the right along the scale. This is especially true with regard to the P8 set of markers. (54) is the first of several generalizations about the P8 set of markers, which has important implications for other markers in the verb:

  1. (50)

    P8 markers only ever mark subjects, never objects or something outside of the argument system.

This generalization means that if a P8 marker occurs in a given verbform alongside markers of other sets, those other markers can only be exponents of the subject if they are co-exponents with P8. This in turn is only possible if the given marker has compatible features with the P8 marker.

For example, consider a form like kirultus ‘you raised her’.

  1. (51)
    figure be

In this case, iru4, as a P4/P3/P1 marker, is more polyfunctional than the P8 marker k8. Depending on the verb, it might indicate either the subject or the object. However, the P8 marker must mark the subject. Since the two markers have incompatible features, meaning they cannot be co-exponents of the same subject, the P4 marker must mark the object in this form.

As before, we can represent implicative relations between morphs using a dependency graph, as shown in Fig. 3.

Fig. 3
figure 3

P8 marker and another marker have different features (ex. (51))

Conversely, if a form has a P8 marker and another marker which has the same features, then either the two must be co-exponents of the subject (i.e. there must be subject Multiple Exponence), or the form must be reflexive. In Ket, these two scenarios are morphologically identical. Compare a true reflexive verb in (51), with a verb with double subject marking in (52).Footnote 42

  1. (52)
    figure bg
  1. (53)
    figure bh

When there are three markers present, if one of them has the same features as the P8 marker, then that marker is a co-exponent of the subject, while the other non-P8 marker is the object, as shown in example (54) and Fig. 4.

  1. (54)
    figure bi
Fig. 4
figure 4

Same features as P8 marker is subject, other is object (ex. (54))

Recall that in the 3rd person the P6 and P4/P3/P1 marker sets have special forms (bu6 and a1 respectively) when they are jointly indexed with a P8 marker, as shown in (55) (bu6) and (56) (a1).

  1. (55)
    figure bk
  1. (56)
    figure bl

These forms have important implication themselves. For one, they disambiguate the 1st person and 3rd person masculine forms of the P8 set (both d or t), which are otherwise syncretic, as shown in Fig. 5.

Fig. 5
figure 5

3rd person jointly-indexed form disambiguates P8 marker (ex. (56))

They also disambiguate some forms where the subject and object are of the same class and number, as shown in Ex. (57) and Fig. 6.

  1. (57)
    figure bn
Fig. 6
figure 6

3rd person jointly-indexed forms disambiguate cases where multiple markers have same features (ex. (57))

We can further summarize the relevant generalizations as in Table 11.

Table 11 P8/P6/P1 Generalizations

Things become more complicated once one considers forms with the potential argument markers o and b, since these can either mark arguments or can serve other functions. However, many of the implicative relations already discussed can also help to narrow down the range of possible functions for these markers in any given form as well.

For example, in a verb with a P8 marker and b, the latter can either indicate a neuter object (58) or be an empty morph (59).Footnote 43

  1. (58)
    figure bp
  1. (59)
    figure bq

However, b3 cannot indicate a neuter subject. For that, it would need to be co-exponent with the P8 marker. Even if they were to have compatible features, a co-exponent of a netuer subject in the P4/P3/P1 set would be marked not with b, but with the special jointly-indexed form a1. This narrows down at least one potential function, as show in Fig. 7.

Fig. 7
figure 7

b cannot be subject if P8 marker is present (ex. (58))

The same generalizations hold also for o, which also cannot indicate a subject in a form with P8 for the same reason.

5.3 Restrictions on multiple exponence

Recall from §3.2 that, of Ket’s 9 major argument-marking classes, four of them involve Multiple Exponence: v3, v4, vt3, and vt4. The last of these, vt4, is very small, consisting of only two or three lexemes (Vajda, 2015, p. 637), although one of them (to sell, cf. example (41)) belongs to the basic vocabulary.

The patterns seen in these classes allow for the following generalization about Multiple Exponence in Ket, given in (60).

  1. (60)

    Multiple Exponence of arguments always involves a P8 marker, or a P3 marker in paradigmatic opposition with P8 markers.

The qualification “or a P3 marker in paradigmatic opposition with P8 markers” might be somewhat opaque. Recall that some class v1 and v4 verbs use b ([b, v, p]) in place of a P8 marker to indicate at least some neuter subjects. We can see this with, for example, the class 1 verb (which does not use Multiple Exponence of the subject) below:

  1. (61)
    figure bs
  1. (62)
    figure bt

It is only in verbs like this, and seemingly only by virtue of it being in paradigmatic opposition to P8, that b can be a co-exponent of the subject with another marker.Footnote 44 Even then, that other marker must have compatible features, be from the P4/P3/P1 set, and be in its jointly-indexed form, which means it can only be a1.Footnote 45

  1. (63)
    figure bu
  1. (64)
    figure bv

Upon encountering one of these verbs, the presence of a1 implies that the subject must be marked by b3 (here v), since the only other possibility would be a P8 marker, which is absent, thereby ruling out other possible functions for b3. This is shown in Fig. 8.

Fig. 8
figure 8

b (v, p) with a1 and without P8 must mark subject (ex. (64))

The fact that Multiple Exponence always directly or indirectly involves a P8 maker also means that it is not possible to have multiple object marking.Footnote 46 This in turn means that if the subject and object can be determined, all other potential argument-markers in the form must serve a non-argument-marking function.

For example, consider the form ‘you covered him’, in example (65), which has four potential argument markers, k8, a6, o4, v3.

  1. (65)
    figure bx

The first marker, k8 must represent the subject. None of the other potential argument markers have compatible features, which rules them out as co-exponents of the subject. See Fig. 9 for illustration.

Fig. 9
figure 9

Marker with different features from P8 marker cannot mark the subject; a6 must mark an argument, multiple object marking not possible, therefore o and v cannot mark arguments here (ex. (65))

This leaves all three of a6, o4 and v3 as potential object markers. Of the three, only a6 must always represent an argument. Since it cannot mark the subject here, it must mark the object. Since Multiple Exponence of the object is impossible, a6 being the object implies that the other two markers must not be argument markers. In this way again, the less polyfunctional marker (a) helps to disambiguate the function of the more polyfunctional markers (o and v). Again, see Fig. 9 for illustration.

5.4 Restrictions on transitive subject marking

Recall again that all of the argument-marking classes for transitive verbs involve a P8 marker as one of the exponents of the subject. This generally means that if the verb does not have a P8 marker, it is intransitive, which in turn leads to the following generalization in (66).

  1. (66)

    If the verb has no P8 marker, it also has no object.

There do seem to be some marginal exceptions to this. Specifically, some class v2 verbs which have b, seemingly as an empty morph, appear to be able to take 3rd person neuter objects.

  1. (67)
    figure bz

However, objects of other persons do not seem to be possible. The meaning of ‘I heard you’, for example can only be expressed using a paraphrase with a 3rd person neuter object, ‘I heard your words’.

  1. (68)
    figure ca

It is likely that such verbs have b as an empty morph, and lack true object agreement,Footnote 47 and yet the formal identity with the neuter object marker licenses a neuter object, although it could also be that b is a real object marker in such cases, and these verbs can only take neuter objects for some other reason.

In either case, it is not possible for any other marker to indicate an object in the absence of a P8 marker. For example, in ‘I heard’, neither ba6 nor o4 can indicate the object, as shown in Fig. 10.

Fig. 10
figure 10

Absent a P8 marker, verb usually cannot have an object; P6 markers must mark subject, others cannot mark subjects and usually cannot mark objects (cf. ex. (68))

Now the question arises of which of the three potential argument markers marks the subject. In cases like this, the least polyfunctional marker is ba6. It must indicate an argument, unlike o4 and b3. Since it is not possible for it to mark the object here, its presence excludes the possible subject function of the other two markers. This is also illustrated in Fig. 10.

These implicative relations hold for any verbform that lacks a P8 maker but has a P6 marker, a P1 marker other than a1, or a P4 marker other than o4. That marker will indicate the subject, while all other potential argument markers must serve a non-argument-marking function (save for the aforementioned sort of neuter quasi-object marking). This is summarized in Table 12.

Table 12 Summary of generalizations from Fig. 10

It also means that the following combinations of markers in the same verbform should be impossible, since it would require that the verb have two subjects: P6 + P1, P6 + P4 other than o4, and P4 other than o4 + P1 other than a1.

Of course, the question remains as to why (nearly?) all transitive verbs in Ket use the P8 marker set, alone or in addition to another marker set. In attempting to answer this, it should be kept in mind that the P8 set of markers is the most recent component of the verb to grammaticalize. The P1 and P6 sets are much older; they were present in Ket’s now dormant relative Kott,Footnote 48 and are reconstructed to Proto-Yeniseian. Based on Vajda’s reconstruction (Vajda, 2010, 2017a), all 1/2 subjects in Proto-Yeniseian (S or A) were marked with the P1 set, while the P6 set only ever marked objects (though not all objects were marked with it).Footnote 49 However, both sets of markers in the modern language, he argues, are heterogeneous in origin, resulting from fusion of previously distinct markers and metathesis with reanalysis of material from other components of the verb, including one another, leading to their polyfunctionality in the modern language. This means that, at minimum historically, the requirement that transitive verbs include the P8 markers has nothing to do with the inability of either the P6 or P1 sets to index transitive subjects – at least the P1 set has always been able to do that. Rather, as argued further on in §5, resolving which markers, if any, indicate transitive subjects is one of several disambiguating functions which the P8 markers serve, reflecting a way in which the language has increased its syntagmatic implicative structure in order to deal with the more complex form-meaning mappings of its older markers.

5.5 Co-occurence restrictions within the P4/P3/P1 set

As discussed in §3.1, ajo4 as an argument/tense marker and ao4 as a tense marker show identical morphotactic behavior, and identical phonological behavior in the past. However, they are not distributionally identical. Tense-marking ao4 is in complementary distribution with the P4 markers: the argument-marking ajo4 as well as ij4 and its allomorphs and 3pl and its allomorphs. In (69) and (70), ao is elided when another P4 marker is present.

  1. (69)
    figure cc
  1. (70)
    figure cd

However, ao freely co-occurs with other members of the P4/P3/P1 argument set, such as b (v, p, 3.n.obj or EM) and daŋ (, 1pl). This is shown in (71) and (72).

  1. (71)
    figure ce
  1. (72)
    figure cf

Argument/tense marking ajo4 does not have this property. It is in complementary distribution with all other members of the P4/P3/P1 set. This means that whenever another P4/P3/P1 marker is present, this implies that o4 can only be a tense marker. This is illustrated in Fig. 11.

Fig. 11
figure 11

Presence of other P4/P3/P1 markers disambiguates o

The other member of the P4/P3/P1 set which can serve a non-argument marking function, b, seems to show a different distributional restriction. Namely, b as an empty morph never occurs in the same paradigm as b as an object marker,Footnote 50 maybe for historical reasons or maybe because the former would be likely to be reanalyzed as the latter. A search of Kotorova and Nefedov (2015) confirms this: of the 921 verbs that are listed with b as an empty morph, only 8 of them are listed as belonging to classes vt1 or vt3, which are the classes that use P4/P3/P1 for object marking, and all of them appear to be mislabelled vt2 or v1 verbs.

This does nothing for disambiguating the function of b itself, but it does mean that any time b, as either an argument or an empty morph, occurs alongside o, the latter cannot be an object. This is illustrated in Fig. 12. Note that b3 in Fig. 12 has an allomorph m, which also marks past tense, due to historical coalesence between b3 and a following plural marker n.

  1. (73)
    figure ch
Fig. 12
figure 12

With b present, o cannot mark object

5.6 Elision of the P8 markers

Before moving on, there is one potential challenge to the system laid out above, which should be addressed. As noted in §3.1, the P8 markers have long and short forms. The short forms, which are used by the vast majority of verbs, show clitic behavior before consonants, and often encliticize to the end of the proceeding word rather than appearing with the rest of the verb. All but the 3rd person feminine marker are single consonants. If the P8 marker is not encliticized to the end of the preceding word, it is often elided entirely, except in careful speech, especially if the proceeding word also ends with a stop ( ‘I work’, or ).Footnote 51 The 3.f P8 short form marker da never elides ( or ‘she works’, *), and the short P8 markers are always retained remain with the rest of the verb when they precede a vowel ( 1.sbj-come-stem, ‘he comes’, *bu=d , *bu ).

If P8 markers are so important to the comprehension of unknown verbal forms, what can be said about cases in which the P8 marker is elided? Any amount of elision of the P8 markers greatly increases the amount of uncertainty about the function of a novel form. Large speech corpora, which unfortunately are almost impossible to collect for Ket at this stage, would be necessary to determine what percentage of novel verbs encountered by speakers occur in contexts in which the P8 marker is completely elided, but if they represent a substantial portion of the input, then this might be a serious challenge to the idea that the P8 markers are a functional adaptation meant to increase syntagmatic implicative structure.

At the same time, there is some diachronic evidence which supports a functional adaption story for the P8 markers. It seems to be the case that the elision of the P8 markers is a recent development. Texts collected by Anuchin at the turn of the 20th century show cases of long-form P8 markers, with full vowels, in cases where the short form would be used and likely elided in modern Ket (cf. modern Ket (t=)kajnam ‘I took it’).Footnote 52

  1. (74)
    figure cj

If the elision of the P8 marker is a recent development, and if the P8 markers are responsible for much of the syntagmatic implicative structure of the verb, and if there is indeed a connection between syntagmatic implicative structure and the maintenance of high complexity of exponence in Ket, then we would expect the elision of the P8 markers to be associated with a corresponding drop in complexity of exponence. And indeed there is some evidence for this in modern Ket. The author’s teacher seems to show certain signs of paradigm leveling, wherein the 3rd person form of the older, non-P8, exponent in some verbs with Multiple Exponence is extended to other, though not all, cells of the paradigm. Note (g)bugbus for the 2nd person singular, instead of the expected u=k ku-g-b-us, you=2.sbj 2.sg.sbj-carry-3.n.obj-stem.

  1. (75)
    figure ck
  1. (76)
    figure cl
  1. (77)
    figure cm

In all of these forms, there is a consonant immediately following where the P8 marker would be expected. In (76), the P8 marker is saved by being encliticized to the end of the preceding, vowel-final, word. In (75) and (77), the preceding word ends with a consonant, preventing encliticization, and the P8 marker is elided. These data show that the 3rd person jointly-indexed member of the P6 marker set has been extended to the 2nd person singular, although not the 1st person singular.Footnote 53 Note that it is specifically bu which is the least polyfunctional member of the P6 set, always representing the subject, and hence the subject can be easily recovered even when the P8 marker is lost (as in (77)).Footnote 54 This seems consistent with a system which is “readjusting”, finding ways to compensate for the loss in some instances of the P8 markers, and hence the decoding cues which they provide. More research is needed on this topic.

6 Ket and the typology of exponence

Before concluding, it is worth briefly exploring how the type of complex exponence found in Ket relates to other types of highly complex exponence discussed in the literature, and specifically the notions of Gestalt Exponence (Blevins, 2016) and Distributed Exponence (Carroll, 2022).

Gestalt Exponence is not precisely defined in the literature, but is conventionally applied to those cases in which individual formatives cannot be associated with a particular meaning in a given form, but rather encode meaning only through their combination. Consider the partial paradigm for Estonian lukk ‘lock’, given as an example of Gestalt Exponence in Blevins (2016, pp. 16–18), shown in Table 13.

Table 13 Estonian noun ‘lock’, taken from (Blevins, 2016, pp. 16–18)

Estonian encodes case through a combination of stem alternations (strong kk stem vs. weak k stem) and inflectional suffixes. Neither the strong stem nor the suffix u can be associated with the meaning ‘partitive singular’, as the strong stem is shared with the nominative, and the suffix is shared with the genitive. Only in conjunction do the strong stem and suffix u encode the meaning ‘partitive singular’.

Ket superficially bears some resemblance to such exponence patterns in that individual elements are reused across the morphology in different combinations for different functions. The crucial difference appears to be that Ket reuses pieces for different functions only across lexemes, not within the inflectional paradigms of single lexemes. In other words, within the paradigm of a given lexeme (say dbatsaq ‘I make a quick trip to the forest and return’), a given marker (say ba) always encodes the same function (here 1.sg.sbj). Deviations from consistent form∼meaning mappings arise only when one compares across lexemes (say, ba in ‘you cover me’, which encodes 1.sg.obj). This gives Ket an essentially morphemic quality which differs from those systems described as Gestalt Exponence, such as Estonian, Georgian (Blevins, 2016; Gurevich, 2006), and Yam languages (Carroll, 2022; Carroll et al., 2016). For each individual lexeme, the meaning of the whole is essentially the sum of the meaning of the parts.

At the same time, this is partly a question of analytical choice. The Estonian system could also be analyzed in similar terms to the Ket system in this paper. The strong stem and the suffix u could both be analyzed as polyfunctional morphs; the strong stem could be taken to encode either nominative or partitive singular, and the u suffix to encode either genitive or partitive singular. The form then would exhibit Multiple Exponence, and the two morphs would exhibit syntagmatic implicative structure, disambiguating one another, as shown in (78) and Fig. 13.

  1. (78)
    figure cn
Fig. 13
figure 13

Estonian Gestalt Exponence as polyfunctionality with syntagmatic implicative structure

The reverse does not appear to be true; it is not possible to analyze the Ket system in terms of recombinant Gestalts, which lack compositional structure. Ket verbs are not always able to be fully disambiguated based on syntagmatic structure alone (for example, verbs with empty morph b3 are often ambiguous in their transitivity based on syntagmatics alone). Hence, the same combination of markers need not represent the same paradigm cell in all cases, unlike systems like Estonian. Hence, a Gestalt analysis for Ket not only fails to capture the unique properties of the system, but makes the wrong predictions about interpretability based on different combinations of formants.

Some recent work by Matthew Carroll has suggested an approach which allows for a unified treatment of both types of systems (Carroll, 2022). In defining his notion of Distributed Exponence, Carroll presents an approach which somewhat abstracts away from this difference between Ket and languages with prototypical Gestalt exponence. He defines Distributed ExponenceFootnote 55 as the following (Carroll, 2022, 2):

Distributed exponence is the co-occurrence of multiple formatives within a single word such that more than one formative is required to provide a fully specified reading of a feature or category (Caballero & Harris, 2012; Carroll et al., 2016; Harris, 2017).

The Ket argument marking system clearly exhibits this property, as outlined throughout this paper, and so does the Estonian data cited above. Carroll relies on his notion of Informativeness, as a more theoretically neutral alternative to exponence, defined informally in the following way:

What information does a language learner or hearer have about the (grammatical) meaning of a word given this formative? (Carroll, 2022, p. 6)

Under this approach, e.g. Estonian u and Ket ba serve the same function: they reduce the range of possible paradigm cells which the form could represent, and have in common the fact that they must be considered in conjunction with other markers in order to provide unambiguous information. Carroll’s approach and the polyfunctionality analysis taken here for Ket seem to represent essentially notational variants of one another, although future research will show whether some crucial difference exists between the two approaches.

7 Discussion and conclusion

This paper has shown that Ket exhibits remarkably high complexity of exponence, owing to the abundance of polyfunctional argument markers. At the same time, such markers are organized into networks of implicative relations with one another, such that actual ambiguity about the function of any given marker is substantially lower than if the marker were considered in isolation.

At the core of these networks is the P8 set of markers, which frequently act as the starting point for chains of implications about other markers. Given that the P8 markers were the last component of the verb to grammaticalize, and are the first markers in the string (and therefore the first to be processed), this dynamic bears some resemblance to the notion of Reinforcement Multiple Exponence (Harris, 2017, pp. 61–64, 163–165; cf. also Caballero & Kapatsinski, 2015). This is where a second, often more frequent or transparent, exponent is added, due to the older exponent of the relevant feature becoming opaque or difficult to parse.Footnote 56 The difference is that rather than just reinforce one feature or set of features, the P8 markers often allow for whole cascades of implications, often as much through their differences with other markers as through their similarities, or through their absence as much as through their presence. Rather than simplify the remarkable complexity of exponence towards the right edge of the verb, Ket has instead added additional implicative structure, which allows for otherwise unfeasibly complex form-function mappings to be maintained.

The Ket data underscore the point made by Sims and Parker (2016) that the role and importance of implicative structure varies across languages with different morphological structures. Ket suggests 1) that implicative structure can play a role in resolving complex form-function mappings not in encoding, but also in decoding and 2) that implicative relations need not only hold between paradigmatically related words or families of constructions, but can hold also between markers.

In languages like Russian or English, both of these points might be true in some trivial sense as well. However, since complexity of exponence is comparatively very low, the number of morphs per word is small, and the syntactic structure provides ample cues for resolving what complexity does exist, the amount of work done by syntagmatic implicative structure for the listener is likely negligible. It is only Ket’s combination of an abundance of polyfunctional markers, a large number of morphs per word, and exclusive head-marking of core syntactic arguments, that allows for syntagmatic implicative structure to do so much work.

Of course, high complexity of exponence, a high degree of synthesis, and predominant head-marking are all properties characteristic of old polysynthetic languages (Fortescue, 2013): those languages whose structures are the result of long periods of successive grammaticalizations and reanalysis. Hence, the particular set of historical contingencies observable in Ket might have played out in a similar way in other languages which have followed a similar historical trajectory. Only further research would say.

In terms of broader implications for an understanding of polyfunctionality and complexity of exponence more generally, Ket as a case study suggests a sort of Low Conditional Entropy Conjecture for the listener. As a hypothesis, there is no a priori limit on how many functions a single marker may have across a language. It may have as many functions as history would have it, provided that the intended function can be determined in any particular instance, although how that result is achieved will vary from language to language.