Skip to main content
Log in

Modus Ponens and the Logic of Decision

  • Published:
Journal of Philosophical Logic Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article presents and discusses a prima facie counterexample to modus ponens. To appropriately theorize the case, I argue for conceptualizing the notions of logical consequence and logical commitment in “normative” terms, so that logical commitment does not attach to the premises of a spurious dominance argument—and, more generally, does not attach to unreasonable decision states, or to syntactically specified classes thereof. I also suggest that there is a logical motivation for the restriction to “well-formed” decision states that is characteristic of Savage-style logics of decision.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  1. Alonso-Ovalle, L. (2006). Disjunction in alternative semantics. http://semanticsarchive.net/Archive/%7BTV%7DkY2ZlM/alonso-ovalle2006.pdf. Ph.D, Dissertation, University of Massachusetts Amherst.

  2. Ayer, A.J. (1964). Fatalism. In The concept of a person and other essays (pp. 235–268). Macmillan & Co.

  3. Biezma, María K.R. (2012). Responding to alternative and polar questions. Linguistics and Philosophy, 35, 361–406. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-012-9123-z.

  4. Bledin, J. (2014). Logic informed. Mind, 123, 277–316. https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/fzu073.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Bledin, J. (2020). Fatalism and the logic of unconditionals. Noûs, 54, 126–161. https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Briggs, R.A., & Pettigrew, R. (2020). An accuracy-dominance argument for conditionalization. Noûs, 54(1), 162–181. https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Broome, J. (1999). Normative requirements. Ratio, 12, 398–419. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9329.00101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Buller, DJ. (1995). On the ‘standard’ argument for fatalism. Philosophical Papers, 24, 111–125. https://doi.org/10.1080/05568649509506524.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Cantwell, J (2006). The logic of dominance reasoning. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 35, 41–63. http://www.jstor.org/stable/30226858.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Cariani, F., Kaufmann, M., & Kaufmann, S. (2013). Deliberative modality under epistemic uncertainty. Linguistics and Philosophy, 36, 225–259. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-013-9134-4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Charlow, N. (2013b). What we know and what to do. Synthese, 190, 2291–2323. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-011-9974-9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Charlow, N. (2013c). Conditional preferences and practical conditionals. Linguistics and Philosophy, 36, 463–511. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-013-9143-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Charlow, N. (2015). Prospects for an expressivist theory of meaning. Philosophers’ Imprint, 15, 1–43.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Charlow, N. (2016). Decision theory: Yes! Truth conditions: No!. In N. Charlow M. Chrisman (Eds.) Deontic Modality (pp. 47–81). Oxford University Press.

  15. Charlow, N. (2018). Decision-theoretic relativity in deontic modality. Linguistics and Philosophy, 41, 251–287. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-017-9211-1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Christensen, D. (2004). Putting logic in its place: formal constraints on rational belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  17. Ciardelli, I. (2018). Questions as information types. Synthese, 195, 321–365. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1221-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Ciardelli, I., & Roelofsen, F. (2011). Inquisitive logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 40, 55–94. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-010-9142-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Dreier, J. (2009). Practical conditionals. In D Sobel S Wall (Eds.) Reasons for action 116–133. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  20. Dummett, M. (1964). Bringing about the past. Philosophical Review, 73, 338–359. https://doi.org/10.2307/2183661.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Egan, A (2007). Some counterexamples to causal decision theory. The Philosophical Review, 116, 93–114. http://www.jstor.org/stable/20446939.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Gibbard, A. (1990). Wise choices apt feelings. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Gibbard, A., & Harper, WL. (1981). Counterfactuals and two kinds of expected utility. In W. Harper, R. Stalnaker, & G. Pearce (Eds.) Conditionals, belief, decision, chance and time (pp. 153–190). Netherlands: Springer.

  24. Gillies, AS. (2009). On truth-conditions for If (but not quite only If). The Philosophical Review, 118, 325–349. https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-2009-002.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Gillies, AS. (2010). Iffiness. Semantics and Pragmatics, 3, 1–42. https://doi.org/10.3765/sp.3.4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Groenendijk, J., & Roelofsen, F. (2009). Inquisitive semantics and pragmatics. http://www.illc.uva.nl/inquisitive-semantics, Ms., ILLC.

  27. Groenendijk, J., & Stokhof, M. (1984). Studies on the semantics of questions and the pragmatics of answers. http://dare.uva.nl/record/123669. Ph.D, Dissertation, University of Amsterdam.

  28. Hájek, A. (2009). Dutch book arguments. In P. Anand, P. Pattanaik, & Puppe C. (Eds.) Oxford handbook of rational and social choice (pp. 173–195). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  29. Hamblin, C. (1958). Questions. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 36, 159–168. https://doi.org/10.1080/00048405885200211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Hedden, B. (2013). Incoherence without exploitability. Noûs, 47, 482–495.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Hospers, J. (1967). An introduction to philosophical analysis. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Jeffrey, R. (1983). The logic of decision, 2nd edn. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 8–9.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Joyce, J. (1998). A nonpragmatic vindication of probabilism. Philosophy of Science, 65, 575–603. https://doi.org/10.1086/392661.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  34. Joyce, J. (1999). The foundations of causal decision theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 115ff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  35. Kolodny, N. (2005). Why be rational. Mind, 114, 509–563. https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/fzi509.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. Kolodny, N., & MacFarlane, J. (2010). Ifs and oughts. Journal of Philosophy, 107, 115–143. https://doi.org/10.5840/jphil2010107310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. Kratzer, A. (1981). The notional category of modality. In H. Eikmeyer H. Rieser (Eds.) Words, worlds, and contexts (pp. 38–74). Berlin: De Gruyter.

  38. Kratzer, A. (1991). Conditionals. In A. von Stechow D. Wunderlich (Eds.) Semantics: an international handbook of contemporary research (pp. 651–656). Berlin: De Gruyter.

  39. Kratzer, A. (2012). Modals and conditionals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Lewis, D. (1981). Causal decision theory. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 59, 5–30. https://doi.org/10.1080/00048408112340011.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  41. Lewis, D (1999). Why conditionalize?. In Papers in metaphysics and epistemology. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511625343.024 (pp. 403–407). Cambridge University Press.

  42. Moss, S. (2015). On the semantics and pragmatics of epistemic vocabulary. Semantics and Pragmatics, 8, 1–81. https://doi.org/10.3765/sp.8.5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  43. Moss, S. (2018). Probabilistic knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  44. Pettigrew, R. (2019). On the expected utility objection to the dutch book argument for probabilism. Noûs. https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12286.

  45. Roberts, C (1996). Information structure in discourse: towards an integrated formal theory of pragmatics. In OSU Working papers in linguistics, Vol 49: Papers in Semantics. Ohio State University. http://semanticsarchive.net/Archive/WYzOTRkO/.

  46. Rothschild, D. (2012). Expressing credences. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society CXII Part, 1, 99–114. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9264.2012.00327.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  47. Savage, LJ. (1972). The foundations of statistics. Dover.

  48. Schulz, M. (2018). Modus ponens under the restrictor view. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 47, 1001–1028. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-018-9459-0.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  49. Stalnaker, R. (1975). Indicative conditionals. Philosophia, 5, 269–286. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02379021.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  50. Stojnić, U. (2017). One’s modus ponens: modality, coherence and logic. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 95, 167–214. https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  51. Veltman, F. (1996). Defaults in update semantics. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 25, 221–261. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00248150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  52. Willer, M. (2012). A remark on iffy oughts. Journal of Philosophy, 109, 449–461. https://doi.org/10.5840/jphil2012109719.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  53. Yalcin, S. (2011). Nonfactualism about epistemic modality. In A. Egan B. Weatherson (Eds.) Epistemic modality (pp. 295–332). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  54. Yalcin, S. (2012). Bayesian expressivism. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society CXII Part, 2, 123–160. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9264.2012.00329.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  55. Yalcin, S. (2012). A counterexample to modus tollens. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 41, 1001–1024. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-012-9228-4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada (435-2015-0423) Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada (435-2020-0329)

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nate Charlow.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Charlow, N. Modus Ponens and the Logic of Decision. J Philos Logic 52, 859–888 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-022-09690-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-022-09690-4

Keywords

Navigation