Skip to content
BY 4.0 license Open Access Published by De Gruyter Open Access August 17, 2023

Whither Rough Ground? On the “Ordinary” of Ordinary Aesthetics

  • Edward Guetti EMAIL logo
From the journal Open Philosophy

Abstract

This article is a criticism of the narrative self-understanding offered by advocates of Ordinary Aesthetics. Even though the frustration with the philosophy of art (in contrast with philosophical aesthetics) is, in many ways, an overdetermined result, the sense of the ordinary as available through the withdrawal of this art-centred concern is misguided. This article argues that the reported death of art and the seemingly consistent suggestion that “anything goes” do not relieve contemporary philosophy from its being situated precisely in the wake of these practices of sense-making. I claim that Ordinary Aesthetics is dealing in an illusory conceit to the extent that defences of Ordinary Aesthetics are indebted to a demand that aesthetics may be a living field of philosophical inquiry today only if the fate of artworks is deleted from that narrative. Arguing this point requires an account of the idea of the death of art, associated with Hegel but perhaps more recently with Danto, and I sketch how Danto’s account does not cohere with the account provided in Ordinary Aesthetics. But because the claim of Ordinary Aesthetics amounts to a claim about the capacities of human sense-making independent of historical trajectories and a sense of the ordinary as that which is just available to a timeless abstraction of the human sensorium, my criticism of Ordinary Aesthetics requires a deeper defence of the relation of the faltering of narratives of art with the philosophical effort to make sense of ordinary experiences. Doing so requires that I provide alternatives: what I regard as two related though quite different philosophical approaches, namely, Cavell’s Ordinary Language Philosophy (which is startlingly absent from defences of Ordinary Aesthetics) and the program of a philosophical aesthetics elaborated in Adorno.

After the leaves have fallen, we return

To a plain sense of things. It is as if

We had come to the end of the imagination,

Inanimate in an inert savoir.

[…]

The greenhouse never so badly needed paint.

The chimney is fifty years old and slants to one side.

A fantastic effort has failed, a repetition

In a repetitiousness of men and flies.

Yet the absence of imagination had

Itself to be imagined. The great pond,

The plain sense of it, without reflections, leaves,

Mud, water like dirty glass, expressing silence

Of a sort, a silence of a rat come out to see,

The great pond and its waste of lilies, all this

Had to be imagined as an inevitable knowledge,

Required, as necessity requires.

—Wallace Stevens, “The Plain Sense of Things”

History, perhaps even especially recent history or, grandly, the idea of historicity itself, may be, as Stephen Daedalus remarks in James Joyce’s Ulysses, a nightmare from which we are trying to awake. Joyce’s alter-ego, perhaps even unbeknownst to such a recherché writer, is reiterating some thoughts on historical reiteration found in the famous opening of Marx’s Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte tract, namely that “the tradition of all dead generations weighs like a nightmare on the brains of the living.” Though many may be inclined to leap at the opportunity to abandon the present as an ongoing outcome of a “tradition of all dead generations” and begin anew, this fantasy is checked by ordinary reality. The fantastic effort fails in everyday life, but it might be thought to be untested in terms of our imaginative or artistic capacities. In this article, I frame recent scholarship gathered under the title of “Ordinary Aesthetics” as precisely an attempt to slough off the dead weight of philosophical history, allegedly because it had become too occupied and entrapped by its obsession with art works. The promised innocence of rebirth envisioned in the fantasy corresponds to the sense in recent literature that this kind of return to (paradoxical) new origins can be actualized in a specifically aesthetic form of attention to everyday, ordinary, experiences (e.g. of recovering maligned beauty in nature from its theory-driven deniers, of appreciating the variety of sensuous qualities of boredom or wage labour). I argue that, even though the frustration with the philosophy of art (in contrast with philosophical aesthetics) is in many ways an overdetermined result, the sense of the ordinary as available through the withdrawal of this art-centred concern is misguided. Rather than thinking that the ordinary can be recovered by leaping back across the fate of the work of art, this article argues that the reported death of art and the concomitant suggestion that “anything goes” do not relieve contemporary philosophy from its being situated precisely in the wake of these practices of sense-making. I claim that Ordinary Aesthetics is dealing in an illusory conceit to the extent that defences of Ordinary Aesthetics are indebted to a conception that aesthetics may be a living field of philosophical inquiry today only if the fate of artworks is deleted from that narrative.

As a burgeoning field of aesthetic inquiry, Ordinary Aesthetics, sometimes known as “Everyday Aesthetics” or the “Aesthetics of Everyday Life,” appears to be an overdetermined result. Momentarily leaving aside narratives of the end of the work of art, which anticipate some of the theses of Ordinary Aesthetics (“OA”), advocates for OA, such as Arnold Berleant, narrate its rise as a result that is responsive to trends that are internal to the trajectories of works of art (focusing on visual arts).[1] Others, such as Yuriko Saito, hold that aesthetics does not depend upon a set of “special objects” (meaning here works of art) and is made richer by embracing the diversity of what might be said to be naturally ordained to human experience.[2] Peter Quigley and others have argued that turning towards everyday experiences entails turning away from the abstruse dead-ends of “theory” and towards a revitalization of the concept of beauty, which, in turn, can offer salutary results and interesting pathways for the Environmental Humanities or Eco-Criticism.[3] Finally, from a slightly separate angle of approach, Graham Harman recently defended an aesthetics of Object-Oriented Ontology that seems to dovetail with OA advocacy. Harman understands this work to “salvage treasures from the wreck” of Kantian formalism, places aesthetics as “first philosophy,” and, thus, partakes of a governing narrative to jettison the self-imposed restrictions of epistemological-aesthetic traditions in order to appreciate the “non-relational autonomy or closure of objects from their contexts.”[4] These related expansions of the field of aesthetics in many ways claim a revanchist and therapeutic aim: taking back, as it were, the rough ground of the ordinary in aesthetics, recovering what is supposed to be an everyday plain sense of experienced things, appears to answer a complex need across philosophical and humanistic disciplines.

According to a pervasive narrative in this scholarship, one that I will refer to as the “governing narrative,” OA and its interdisciplinary family relations (such as Eco-Aesthetics) make good on several contemporary demands through a recovery of a sense of “aesthetics” that had been neglected or submerged beneath a complex interweaving of misguided epistemology and the exhausted attention given to the philosophy of art. This can be seen in the way that Berleant identifies Kantian aesthetics as having introduced a plethora of “obsolescent concepts” that have served to mire aesthetic theory “in the framework and concepts of the eighteenth century.”[5] One need not be fully immersed in the new phenomenological wave of Object-Oriented Ontology (“OOO”) to appreciate how, in relation to works of art, Harman’s account of OOO trades on a similar vision of the obsolescence of a traditional framework while at the same time alighting upon moments in Kant, Husserl, Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty, and others that preserve the thought, restored through OOO, of an inexhaustible excess, a surplus in the real object above its various relations of experiential exchange. Harman goes so far as to say that OOO corrects an error that German Idealism succumbed to in inheriting Kant: “Kant’s notions of finitude and the thing-in-itself should have been retained, while simply removing their restriction to cases involving human beings.”[6] Though lacking the tone of correction, Saito remarks on the irony that a newfound venture, created, as it were, anew, is merely a matter of being faithful to an older conception of aesthetics, the general science of perception, in Baumgarten’s thought.[7] Quigley, too, frames his zealous defences of beauty as a heroic kind of “rear-guard” action or “reactionary gesture” in wishing that it to be read as a “return of the repressed.”[8] Other defences of OA (e.g. Leddy 2012: 132–135) also include the attempt to restore “aura” within the experience of ordinary objects that Benjamin famously sketched as a remnant of a disintegrating sense of the sacred in the profanation of artworks, amplified in the era of mechanized reproducibility, a concept he exiled almost immediately to a lost time.[9]

Given the alliance of views risen up in defence of OA, it seems prima facie unappealing to wonder if the governing narrative motivating the several accounts of OA and its theoretical fellow travellers can and should be criticized. I am taking up this effort here, but not in the name of defending the some one of the old “formalizations” or “narrowings” ascribed to traditions of theory or artworks. I think it is neither likely nor desirable that we have our history à la carte. Asking after the sense of the “ordinary” in OA, here, is to ask specifically whether it promises or recommends an ability to merely “turn back the clock” of history by voiding the post-Kantian line or the evident exhaustion of trajectories of art practices and starting afresh. Exhaustion is not the same as error, and I take it as a central datum of this tradition that it betrays a potentially unsettling truth of a history of art practices and the historical conditioning of what is imagined to be the human sensorium. My point concerns the relation of aesthetic with this history of practices, a tradition of art whose sway has been repeatedly affirmed as defunct. Framed this way, the most salient interlocutors for OA are those who have diagnosed and responded to the death of art, the demise of a certain narrative of confinement, and to reflect upon the presence of what might be regarded as the dead weight of tradition, the ghost of art’s collapses, still present at the feast of OA. Thus, it appears necessary to consider trajectories that develop out of the death of art, and I will consider a few lines that evolve out of Hegel through Adorno and, quite differently, Danto. Instead of valorising an untimely leap into the fantasy of an uncorrupted moment pairing aesthetic innocence with ordinary objects, in a matter of speaking, the ordinary is that which suffers this corruption. Aesthetics is not established in flight from this history but, rather, in inheriting it. I take myself to be bolstered in asserting this position by Stanley Cavell’s engagement with aesthetic problems and the condition of works of art through the lens of Wittgensteinian Ordinary Language Philosophy. The relevance of an Ordinary Language pursuit of an idea of the “ordinary” is also, surprisingly, neglected by the OA and OOO accounts mentioned earlier, and one of the tasks of this article is to situate a kind of confrontation between the ordinary in OA and after Cavell.[10]

Naïvely put, I am asking whether it is possible, let alone desirable, to accept the governing narrative of OA, shepherding a return to an idea of aesthetics purified of the excrescences that have become attached to it (i.e. the narrow landscape of works of art, “theory,” and the need for erudite critics to serve as cultural gatekeepers). Pursued along this path, the governing narrative presumes a model for thinking of aesthetics as a neutral and ahistorical conception of the human sensorium to which experiences are given in a mode called “ordinary,” and that these should be regarded as opening onto a sense of the “ordinary” as that which serves an operation of recovery from the heady decades of confining aesthetics to increasingly diminishing corners of experience. A slightly baffling way of putting the question I am raising here is to ask when the ordinary is available for a specifically aesthetic form of reflection or sensuous exposure. This is liable to be confusing because its sounds like it is asking whether it is always possible for anyone to reflect on her sensory experiences. We may feel restrained to respond: always, or, whenever in the presence of objects and given to such reflection, which can be heard as tantamount to saying “in everyday situations.”

The question is more interestingly heard as asking for the conditions when it is possible to identify such reflection as aesthetic, and I am supposing that it might be possible for aesthetics to fail to describe such reflection. Consider the following case: a young movie critic reflects upon her account of a new film and judges that her account is “interesting” or “incisive.” Such descriptions of her reflections, however, if they are to mean anything, will come out in her audience’s reception of her account. Obviously, different normative factors will come into play if she, or anyone, describes her reflections as being about the taste of watermelon rinds, the sounds made by foxes, or about this object here and now.[11] These comparisons reveal some of the relevant and unavoidable conditions when any person reflecting on her experiences could mean that her reflections are aesthetic ones, a meaning which can be communicated to others and subject to the commitments that such a communication implies. The young critic’s reflective description of her account can be mistaken for several reasons, it is boring rather than interesting, it traffics in stereotypes rather than incisive wit. It would be an evasion of the point for her to console herself with a private assurance that “at least my reflections are interesting to me.”

With this case of the young critic, I am rehearsing some considerations modelled on the considerations that informed Kant’s own theorization of judgements of beauty (and the differences of commitment between saying that something is agreeable as opposed to beautiful). Notably, the claim that to remark of an experience that it is “beautiful” is subject to a commitment that would be incoherent to limit to a personal sense (“beautiful to me”) without requiring that it hold also of anyone in the same position. This is the heralded Kantian conception of the judgement of beauty as made on subjective ground and compelling universal agreement, speaking with a particular voice that is also representative of human community. The Kantian argument is controlled by the idea that “beauty” is not a determinate, objective, concept that can be directly sensed, and, hence, that the judgement of beauty is a reflective rather than determinative judgement. My point in unfurling this Kantian background is to question whether OA can or should accept this grammatical baggage about “beauty,” the contestable worldly presence of “aesthetic qualities,” or, indeed, being convinced of a subjective ability to speak on behalf of a community. More to my point in what immediately follows: is the sense of the aesthetic available ordinarily one that must be judged specifically through a mediation by works of art? What would such a necessary mediation indicate?

Philosophers often explicitly frame the development of OA by referring to the career of the art-centred paradigm of aesthetics after Kant.[12] This identification of a sensitive historical locus in Kantian aesthetics is entirely correct. In the 30 or so years separating Kant’s third critique and Hegel’s lectures on aesthetics, we move from a thought that celebrates the organized exteriority of nature in Kant to the Hegel’s celebration of its replacement at every point of interest by the Anthropos. Some (e.g. Robert Pippin) have claimed that Hegel announces the advent of artistic modernism,[13] but I would underline his lack of patience with natural beauty. In his prefatory remarks, Hegel underscores that his topic is the philosophy of (fine) art and that the purpose of this emphasis is to “at once exclude the beauty of nature.”[14] There are at least two important questions that follow from this: the first is to ask about Hegel’s own motivation to centre aesthetics on the fine arts; the second is to ask of OA what is being affirmed in the claim that aesthetics has been confined, unjustly or arbitrarily, to art, disconnected from nature and experiences of the ordinary? What is at stake in this depiction of false imprisonment?

Sketching a response to the first of these two questions, Hegel’s argument against natural beauty has at least two steps. In a thumbnail sketch, the first step is that any appreciation of natural beauty as such is done from a distinctly human perspective, a point that Kant would surely agree with, that what we are appreciating is not really the natural scene as an external reality but rather the natural externality is an obscure mirror of our own capacities for judgement. If some natural scene is beautiful, it is so because it shows us distinctly human capacities, which, for Hegel, are more satisfactorily exercised in the fine arts. We appreciate ourselves in appreciating nature, but this activity is not satisfied by natural externalities alone. For Hegel, we are driven to engage human attempts at expanding or testing sense-making practices, although, famously, we have been fatefully fixed, for a time, to a restless dissatisfaction with accomplished artistic modes of sense-making. Not discounting the history of this fixture, we are no longer fixed to art, generally, as a sense-making practice. The second step (one that features in some OA conceptions about the defamiliarization that seems to be internal to aesthetic appreciation as such)[15] is to recognize that, when we enter into the attitude of appreciation, we are also denaturalizing the scene and we intuit something that is no longer, say, the abode of woodland animals but rather a dimly reflected abstract concept. Here is Hegel’s way of putting that point: “In this connection ‘natural’ cannot be used in the strict sense of the word, for as the external configuration of spirit, it has no value in simply existing immediately as the life of animals, the natural landscape, etc.”[16]

Before advancing to the question concerning the specific determination of aesthetics as having been unjustly captive to the philosophy of art, it is essential to recall that, for Hegel, the Idea as presented in art was not the exclusive possession of art, but rather that art and philosophy (and religion) all shared a similar vocation of making adequate the collective self-understanding of some collective “we.” Positing the intersection of these different spheres of human practice, objective spirit, must be acknowledged as guiding the notorious thought from Hegel that the time for great art is already over, that it can no longer fulfil the vocation that drove it away from the appreciation of natural beauty. Instead of lingering with a false promise for reconciliation between matter and idea, the foregoing telos of artwork is replaced by reflection on the human. “In this self-transcendence art is nevertheless a withdrawal of man into himself, a descent into his own breast, whereby art strips away from itself all fixed restriction to a specific range of content and treatment, and makes Humanus, its new holy of holies.”[17]

Some OA theorists seize this proclamation of the end of art and, following Arthur Danto’s compelling interpretation,[18] view this as the prescience of the eventual liberation of aesthetics from the art conventions. In a phrase that Danto frames as the truth of the end of art, OA theorists might leap at the prospect that, now, “anything goes.”[19] Down this pathway, the end of art thesis easily becomes a premise for the advent of OA, especially in Berleant’s narrative of aesthetics as progressive actualization of engaged experience.[20] But there are multiple and conflicting arguments condensed in different ways of casting the consequences of “anything goes.” It should be granted that both the OA theorist and Danto agree that aesthetics ought not be confined to a narrow region of possible experiences. Both argue that there is no conceptual boundary filtering aesthetic experiences from those that had heretofore been nearly exclusively within the domain of exhibiting works of art. As illustrated earlier, the OA theorist takes this to mean that aesthetic evaluations and concepts are now liberated into the ordinary domain of any everyday experience. For Danto, however, it is artists who are now liberated from prior constraints of form, presentation, or appearance. Artists, according to Danto, are now “free to make art in whatever way they wished, for any purposes they wished, or for no purposes at all. That is the mark of contemporary art.”[21] Even though both the OA theorist and Danto share the premise that denies any special ontology wherein categories of aesthetic or artistic evaluation have their proper home, Danto’s claim is that this liberation is not of the everyday into a domain formerly occupied by artworks but, rather, an inverse influx of artists coming to inhabit everyday regions. He describes as art’s becoming “post-historical” in the sense that contemporary art has closed the grand narrative of art’s (Western) historical tradition that, for Danto, came to a head with modernism and had its final flourishing in the abstract expressionism of the 1960s. But championing post-historical art practices is not the same thing as valorising the aesthetics of ordinary experiences against the grain of history. For Danto, the post-historical condition of art is just that “there is no a priori constraint on how works of art must look – they can look like anything at all.”[22] Yet his claim still privileges a kind of historically educated mode of critical discernment that searches for the work of art. This critical pursuit has become even more removed from being ordinarily available precisely because “there does not even have to be an object to look at, and if there are objects in a gallery, they can look like anything at all.”[23] In other words, if anything is potentially indiscernible from a possible work of art, then, rather than making any ordinary experience the (restored) home of aesthetic considerations, Danto’s direction of thought seems to throw into question whether aesthetics has any place within the contemporary (i.e. in his terms “post-historical”) world.[24]

Considering this narrative of the end of art and its possible relation with OA seems to have returned us to the initial question of whether philosophical reflection on the ordinary can be described as “aesthetic.” This question is harder to answer if we understand the OA narrative as insisting that aesthetic reflection can be understood as a retrieval of categories of experience that had been stymied by the narrow occupation with the fine arts. The line of thought from Danto (contentiously extending a thought of Hegel’s) is that the post-historical condition makes the blurred difference between “ordinary” and “artistic” experiences in need of further philosophical interpretation. In the post-historical condition, a traditional sense of aesthetics has no place. Contrarily, if OA is indebted to the claim that contemporary aesthetic considerations must be cut loose from recent decades of art theory, then OA needs an account of what remains after subtracting arts from the aesthetic. In coming to a clarified understanding of the possibility of OA today, we must first clarify the relation between philosophical reflection on works of art (and, if Danto is right, their end) and ordinary reflection on human sense-making practices. For example, was the tradition of High European Modernism merely a cage for human practices of sense-making or is its fate tutelary or somehow indicative of a contemporary situation of human sense-making? Put another way, this is a limiting case of a broader question of the relation between the abstraction of the human sensorium (what might be called bodily sensory capacities in their exposure to an environment) and the historical practices of making sense, conceiving, experiences, including here the fact that these practices are linguistic and that languages are historical artefacts.

A family of prominent interpretations for understanding the significance of the fate of modern art through abstract expressionism runs through the work of Adorno, Cavell, or, even, the work of T. J. Clark and Michael Fried. One broad thesis that gathers these divergent interpretations of the history of artworks in the narrative governing OA is that such works are not capable of being understood apart from philosophical reflection on the conditions of human capacities of sense-making and vice-versa. I will recount here some of the thoughts featured in Adorno’s work in order to lay the challenge most directly before turning to a similar claim in Cavell. Adorno is committed to the view that works of high modernism reveal what has become of conditions of sense-making, the conditions of the very possibility of philosophical reflection. In the words of one of his current readers: “To say that these practices are the condition of possibility of philosophy should be taken as equivalent to saying that they provide the condition of possibility for our being or becoming self-conscious about who we are, what the world we inhabit is like, and how these two fit together.”[25] A history of modernist works of art reveals, in nuce, an internal and agonistic, exhausted, relation over portraying conditions of experiencing the world under the aspect of its disenchantment by modern rationality.

The succession of modernist modes suggests that antecedent modernist works had not successfully dispelled the multiple ersatz enchantments of representation (“picture thinking” in Hegel’s phrase), anthropomorphism, religious longing, utopian futures, and so on. This line of thinking explains without being committed to Clement Greenberg’s view of modernism, which emerges quite explicitly at times in Fried and Cavell, as successive interrogations of the necessities of an artistic medium. What else is the drive towards this successive self-emptying of the minimal commitments necessary for achieving, say, a painting, if not the suspicion that each iteration is still haunted by remnant enchantments? More to my point, is this not what is desired for a kind of liberation of artwork from its captivity to an illusory confinement?

The “end of art” thesis, viewed under the influence of Adorno, becomes a project of reiterated and multidimensional efforts to achieve a disenchanted world, in other words, a project for arriving at a natural world through reflection on the historical stations of artistic creation. In some ways, Adorno’s account can be made to fit within a map of OA’s governing narrative. For both Adorno and the governing narrative of OA, natural beauty stands apart from the historical trajectory of artistic becoming and, thus, serves as a fulcrum for redemptive critique of what has become all-too conventional within a bifurcation of an experience of artworks and ordinary life. For OA theorists, that which is natural, often equated with an idea of what is ordinary, can be discovered by abjuring the artifices and fads of the art world, which are supposed to have led to the dead end of history and “anything goes.” Conversely, for Adorno, natural beauty stands apart from what is ordinary, if this latter term refers to that which is readily available as daily experience, since natural beauty stands for what does not yet exist in everyday life. It is a normative summons or appeal to recognize the “fact that nature, as it stirs mortally and tenderly in its beauty, does not yet exist.”[26] An experience of natural beauty does not serve as a gateway back into a pre- or post-history of a naïve human sensorium from which agglomerations of human artifice have been excised like a cancer from an otherwise healthy body. Instead, the experience of nature beauty induces a sense of shame for what has become ordinary, a sense of shame that stems from a dedicated reduction of future possibility (i.e. the not-yet-existing as a cipher for nature) to that which exists: “The shame felt in the face of natural beauty stems from the damage implicitly done to what does not yet exist by taking it for existent. The dignity of nature is that of the not-yet-existing.”[27]

Rather than being an independently healthy body, retrievable in its integrity beneath distorting conventions, ordinary human consciousness participates in a pathological tendency to frame the promise of a transformed future to present human utility, rendering spirit into commodity “and what is today called meaning participates in this disaster.”[28] The dignity of the non-existent, of nature as a task, has been carried as a germ within “the hermetic character of art,” its illegibility from the perspective of ordinary consciousness, “art’s renunciation of any usefulness whatever” is an “afterimage of the silence that is the single medium through which nature speaks.”[29] In short, instead of rendering aesthetics loquaciously conversant in everyday life, Adorno’s thought urges a focus on that which cannot be made to speak in ordinary terms of human use: “The task of aesthetics is not to comprehend artworks as hermeneutical objects; in the contemporary situation, it is their incomprehensibility that needs to be comprehended.”[30]

Running in the opposite direction of the governing narrative of OA, Adorno’s Aesthetic Theory describes the promise of modernist artworks as tending towards the condition of non-human nature, redeeming the latter from its corruption under the regime of modern instrumental rationality, and approximating a “language of divine creation.”[31] (1997: 78) This promise, however, cannot help but be seen as somewhat paradoxical since it acknowledges the conflicted sense in which human beings are tasked with expressing the non-human and non-conceptual, intending to have no intention, redeeming via human artistic intervention a world damaged by humans, committed to a self-determining being-in-itself that does not yet exist reflected through a subject’s intention:

The being-in-itself to which artworks are devoted is not the imitation of something real but rather the anticipation of a being-in-itself that does not yet exist, of an unknown that –by way of the subject—is self-determining. Artworks say that something exists in itself, without predicating anything about it.[32]

This interpretation of the yet non-existent organizing telos of artworks could hardly be further from the thought that the history of modern art points to the possibility that “anything goes.” Indeed, nothing can be said to “go” anymore: “The sole path of success that remains open to artworks is also that of their progressive impossibility.”[33] Adorno’s text parts ways from the OA emphasis on recovering ordinary experience outside of the history of art forms. The license proffered by OA to indulge in a sense of the ordinary as given apart from artistic mediation will be resisted by Adorno since such an exteriorization arrests the liberating project of properly disenchanting human experience as well as its objects from instrumentalizing rationality. This corresponds to the method of a Negative Dialectics, which seeks “implicit history” as “possibility” as a means for penetrating “hardened objects,” “the possibility of which their reality has cheated the objects and which is nonetheless visible in each one.”[34] Evidently, the divergence here occurs precisely when the idea of the “ordinary” comes into view.

This line of thinking will be confronted by the question of why anyone would desire a “total” disenchantment unless one already glimpses a disaster at the heart of everyday life. A parallel disbelief would follow from hearing that the ordinary is a space liberated from the empty historical closures of specialized artifice, that is, unless one already judges the history of arts to be unilluminating sound and fury. Tracking Adorno’s reading of the history and unfulfilled promise of modern art is a way of pressing the question of whether a recovery of the conditions of sense-making and the experience of the everyday is independent of the work of art. The claim of OA rejects this denial and claims that it is now and always possible, for human beings to be able to reflect on their experiences and conditions of sense-making. The question now becomes: what sort of perspective could be achieved that would facilitate a judgement about what is called “ordinary” for an ecumenical audience and not merely for those who are already part of the congregation of OA or the Frankfurt School?

We can now indicate the relevance of Cavell and post-Wittgensteinian accounts of an aesthetics of the ordinary that neither abandons the history of art forms nor breaks with all communicative possibility. The project of an Ordinary Aesthetics after Cavell and Wittgenstein is one that holds that the ordinary, everyday, is a space of recovery and also a space that calls for an eventual becoming, a promise of return through an attention to the ordinary that not only is restorative but also evokes an “eventual” every day, the promise of which diurnally arises as unfulfilled, and that recognizes and valorises modernist conventions without framing nature exclusively as that which has been excluded from human convention.

The course of my argument so far anticipates an account of the “ordinary” as it intersects with considerations of conventions and an idea of what might be natural. It ought to be noted that these are not to be regarded as external to some idea of an aesthetics or a philosophy of art, but rather, precisely as the object of any reputed “Ordinary Aesthetics” worthy of its name.[35] Here I hope to thread a needle, the aperture of which stands in the locus identified by both the governing narrative of OA and Adorno’s aspirations for possibilities disclosed in the hermeneutical resistance of artworks. Identifying this aperture of intersection, I am suggesting, is bundled up with questions of when the ordinary can be identified, more specifically, when it dawns as a restorative measure, when it marks an antecedent departure and measures steps for recovery, or, simply, when something (an object or phrase) appears as ordinary.

These “specifications” may strike the reader as being overly precious with the notion of the “ordinary” since they all seem to overlook the tautological response: something appears to be ordinary in ordinary situations. But this response does not lend itself towards any perception or appreciation of what it would mean to accept such situations, such conditions, as ordinary. If anything, emphasizing the tautology makes it more difficult to understand how the ordinary could ever be an emphatic presence in experience. Accounting for the ordinary, in this way, draws upon an unspoken sense of the extraordinary, a rhetorical colouring that is added, in OA discourses, to the idea that artworks have increasingly come to inhabit only extraordinarily recherché objects and contexts. So the ordinary is that which is without artifice, something plainly there at the end of imagination, as Wallace Stevens sketched an idea of “The Plain Sense of Things,” “inanimate in an inert savoir.” “Yet,” as the poet goes on to claim, “the absence of imagination had/itself to be imagined” and imagined as an “inevitable knowledge.” To the extent that the governing narrative of OA falls under the persuasion of its readiness to equate the ordinary with that which is inevitable in experience, it is because we are apt to think of the ordinary as given to the registers of the human senses. Hence the conventions of artworks, which seem to be so many baseless strictures, appear as incredibly evitable.

The line taken by Wittgenstein, Cavell, and even Stevens in “The Plain Sense of Things” is just that the given is always mediated by language. Our exposure to the world is partially insulated by the idea that the world is not a collection of ordinary things but that even these ordinary things are interpellated and interpreted by what Wittgenstein and Cavell call “forms of life.” So, the first step to take in accounting for the ordinary, following Saito’s recommendation nearly to the letter, is not to think of it as a specialized region of ontology but (breaking here with Saito) to envision it as the discovery of a mutual attunement in language.[36]

Underscoring the givenness of forms of life, rather than the givenness of the objects of experience, is meant to have a disarming epistemological effect. This is what Cavell describes as the moral of scepticism. If the ordinary is something that comes into awareness as a mutual attunement, it is thoroughly crossed by lines of communication and the presence of at least imagined others. This crossing dispossesses me, as a representative for anyone, from having any exclusive or private command over the conditions of what is ordinary. Indeed, even in moments of privacy or personal experiences, the “conditions” delimiting the ordinary are given within an ongoing and incomplete inheritance of language. Such inheritance is incomplete, even for one who might entertain the self-regard of being a native speaker, “the inheritance of language is essentially never over and done with – though any number of accidents, or say fixations, inner or outer, may put an end to it.”[37]

Even if Cavell is right to take a broadly Kantian Copernican turn away from the givenness of objects towards a givenness of forms of life, repeatedly alerting his readers to the moral of scepticism that follows from this reorientation (i.e. that “the existence of the world and others in it is not a matter to be known, but one to be acknowledged” and that we are repeatedly confronted now with the question of how to acknowledge the world and others across our epistemological separateness from directly being present to them, their being transparently readable for us), it remains to be seen why this should render the ordinary (even as the discovery of mutual attunement) to be something preciously withdrawn from “ordinary” contexts. Cavell’s Wittgensteinian account of our relation to the ordinary is one that is “ordinarily” misaligned, frequently claiming a point that it is characteristic of human beings to disavow the human conditioning of their relation to language, the world, and others. This accusation holds, a fortiori, of questions or theses that are recognizable as having a philosophical or sceptical gist, but it is not the exclusive possession of a group of people that might be somehow identified ahead of time as “philosophers,” or a collection of thoughts called “metaphysical.” One relatable example can be found in Cavell’s 1986 Tanner Lecture, “The Uncanniness of the Ordinary,”[38] where he likens a search for the ordinary to Poe’s policemen in “The Purloined Letter” who are unable to find the desired letter simply because it is not hidden. Cavell adduces this passage from Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations: “The aspects of things that are most important for us are hidden because of their simplicity and ordinariness. (One is unable to notice something – because it is always before one’s eyes.)” (§129). It may already be obvious to the reader, but I will note anyway that, in the analogy with “The Purloined Letter,” Dupin – the detective who “solves” a royal difficulty by being able to see what is in front of everyone’s eyes, who liberates everyone involved in the caper by introducing another letter to beguile the beguiler of Poe’s tale, and where the case is known to be “solved” precisely because the coercive designs of the unprincipled villain, antecedently known to all involved as the villain, are now relieved of their force – stands in the place of Cavell’s image of the Ordinary Language Philosopher. The latter is not characterized by her acquaintance with all that might be hidden within arcane system but just by her ability to discern what lies in plain view, including a use of language that seems to arrest everyday life in a state of suspended philosophical vigilance; the Ordinary Language Philosopher is then able to provide other words (even in this case, words that would serve as a reminder for the villain to recall a previous encounter with Dupin) that disengage the suspension of everyday life and lead to a return to the familiar as if from out of a period of exile from it. It is not necessarily the case that the substitute words (i.e. Dupin’s facsimile of the purloined letter) contain “ordinary” terms (indeed, Dupin’s contains a verse from an eighteenth-century poem by Crébillon) but the “ordinary” names that which is achieved through the method preferred by the Wittgensteinian philosopher.

I run the risks of presenting the potentially hyperobtrusive parallels between the Ordinary Language Philosopher and Dupin because they provide further substance for Cavell’s judgement that Wittgenstein “speaks to us quite as if we have become unfamiliar with the world,”[39] a tone that will, on one hand, serve as a rebuke to the tautology of the ordinary as that which is given ordinarily, but, on the other, will only bear compelling evidentiary weight if one judges that human beings are capable of becoming lost to what might be thought to be most proximate to humans. If we are able to claim this proximity for works of art, as artefacts of human production if not always the comprehensive result of deliberate human intention, then, at the very least, we should suppose that OA’s and Adorno’s lines of thought approach a willingness to accept this depiction, since, for the former, it bespeaks the decades – if not centuries – long trend in various art worlds, and, for the latter, it would seem to be expressed by the famous opening lines of Aesthetic Theory, that it is “self-evident that nothing concerning art is self-evident anymore.”[40]

Following Cavell’s line of elaborating the consequences of this thought will sponsor a description of the ordinary as uncanny and will call for an adjusted sense of the identity of what is said to “return” from out of estrangement.

The return of what we accept as the world will … present itself as a return of the familiar, which is to say, exactly under the concept of what Freud names the uncanny. That the familiar is a product of the sense of the unfamiliar and of the sense of a return means that what returns … is never (just) the same.[41]

As that which is accomplished by and through the ordinary, to speak of a “return” is perhaps a misleading phenomenological marker, since not only is that which returns “never (just) the same,” and, hence, a putative return of what had not been there in the first place, but, also, the one who returns from this holiday or exile is given something that could not have been experienced before. In Philosophical Investigations, Wittgenstein notes a sense of achieved “peace” as the therapeutic telos of his philosophical method, and not only that but as “the real discovery” [Die eigentliche Entdeckung], which is implicitly contrasted against the illusory discovery of a “system of rules” [Regelsystem].[42] To risk stating the obvious again, which is a curious risk to run in the context of how the obvious is exactly what escapes notice, the ordinary can be said to resemble nothing so much as a revenant of human condition, the return of repressed boundaries or forms of agreement in language and judgement that are gathered together in the wild “whirl of organism” called human forms of life.[43] The question, to conclude, is how the Cavellian conception of the ordinary can be made to intervene in the differing visions of OA and Adorno with respect to its relation to aesthetics.

One of the more clearly illustrative moments of Philosophical Investigations commences with Wittgenstein describing a scenario in which a conflict emerges between the mandates of an alleged philosophical account of language and the actual practices of language use. Wittgenstein presents a parable of walking on ice as figurative of the ineptitude of a particularly rigid requirement of a “crystalline purity of logic”[44] if employed as a general idealization for the human conditions of walking. “We have got on to slippery ice where there is no friction and so in a certain sense the conditions are ideal, but also, just because of that, we are unable to walk. We want to walk: so we need friction. Back to the rough ground!”[45] Although comparatively coarse, as any moment of providing a bird’s-eye view over the terrain of Philosophical Investigations is likely to be, this figuration of walking on ice as precisely misrepresenting an idealized space for philosophical investigation also details that which is being investigated, that which I described earlier, following Cavell (following Emerson), as human condition.

But which ground is suitably rough for our purposes? How shall rough ground be recognized? What is “walking” in this figuration? My brief account of Cavell’s engagement with the notion of the “uncanniness of the ordinary” already presented reasons to suspect that we cannot just identify the rough ground by that which it is not. It is fruitless, on this account, to try to secure the ordinary in advance by insisting upon its contrariness to that which is extraordinary. The “ordinary” human drive towards inhumanity is not the least reason for the uselessness of this negative understanding. We are also in a position to highlight that the ordinary is not a region of an ontology; it is something that emerges in a “real discovery” and is better described as an attained relation to given forms of human life. This point must be kept in mind, since it will seem perfectly acceptable to OA theorists and Wittgensteinians alike to portray that the ordinary is that which must be turned to in order to undermine the confinements of abstruse conventions. The difference here is that there is no objective highest common factor in accounting for the “ordinary” for a Wittgensteinian mode of thought, whereas, for OA theorists, the ordinary is identifiable both in negative terms (i.e. the objects of experience that have been neglected in aesthetically prioritizing the work of art) and as oriented by a highest common factor (i.e. everything that could feature in the science of the human sensorium).[46] The rough ground is not guaranteed to be any ordinary object that one is likely to encounter, since the sceptical holiday from human condition might exactly be one where I am deeply attentive to exactly and only the given experiences of so-called ordinary objects: Moore’s envelope, Descartes’s ball of wax, a slanting chimney of unknown custodianship, the lilies of a stagnant and dirty pond. Though “ordinary” in an OA reckoning, the Wittgensteinian will need to pursue how an attention to such objects can draw one back to the ordinary. But there is also a critical edge to the Wittgensteinian–Cavellian thought in relation to OA.

Following Adorno’s line on the situation of artworks, we can say that nothing about the ordinary is self-evident, given without having found oneself lost to it. Perhaps it is subject to the same confusion concerning ‘nature’ as a given and fully present totality as opposed to ‘nature’ as marking the specific dignity of that which is unfolding. In any event, philosophy becomes a self-conscious and -revelatory project in the light of the ordinary appearing as that which unfolds from out of and releases human subjects from resistant fixtures. This indicates how the development of philosophical practice apes the fate of artworks. “The absence of imagination had/itself to be imagined.” Similarly, for Cavell, it might be said, how a certain register of objects arises to epistemologico-aesthetic prominence is not determined objective by the objects, but, rather, as the governing narrative of OA indicates, only through a historical exposure to what is now being isolated as illegible in modern art and aesthetics. We can hardly judge whether William Carlos Williams, for example, as a poet of occasionally “ordinary” items such as a famed red wheelbarrow, would have had the same reception were it not for the high-flying exertions of his contemporaries T. S. Eliot and Ezra Pound. Surely the same could be said for Beckett in the wake of Joyce. But neither Williams nor Beckett is disclosing the same things as earlier poets and writers who attended to, say, the low and the common: Wordsworth, say, or Clare.[47]

Cavell discusses a similar conditioning of experience by the achievements of conventions in artworks in describing when we can identify music as improvisatory. Focusing on an ability to hear something as improvisatory is a fecund topic to consider in reflecting on the possible discoveries of ostensible freedoms available only (or against?) in the presence of formulaic conventions.

In listening to a great deal of music, particularly to the time of Beethoven, it would, I want to suggest, be possible to imagine that it was being improvised. Its mere complexity, or a certain kind of complexity, would be no obstacle. … One can hear, in the music in question, how the composition is related to, or could grow in familiar ways, from a process of improvisation; as though the parts meted out by the composer were re-enactments, or dramatizations, of successes his improvisations had discovered …. If this could be granted, a further suggestion becomes possible. Somewhere in the development of Beethoven, this ceases to be imaginable.[48]

The capacity to hear music as a development whose genesis is improvisatory success is claimed by Cavell to only be possible “within contexts fully defined by shared formulas,” a place where “full, explicit improvisation traditionally exists.”[49] Surely, we might place ourselves, however unwillingly, in a position to listen to several trombonists and flautists freestyling, but without the control of a governing work (given in advance or alighted upon haphazardly in a discovery of a common interest in exploring, say, “Freebird”), their free flights will not be heard as improvised music.[50] Continuing Cavell’s thought: “The context in which we can hear music as improvisatory is one in which the language it employs, its conventions, are familiar or obvious enough.”[51] The use of “improvisation” is functioning here not only as a guiding convention for what might be called the praxis of the musician, but also describes an element of what an audience would be hearing. This thought also fits the measures of Adorno’s claim that the experience of beauty in nature and nature’s silence bears within it an implicit context for the evaluation of modernist artworks.

Now, a depiction of the human sensorium as a network of capacities that are essentially untrained and uninformed by conventions will find it difficult to account for the claim that someone cannot hear music as improvisatory without a controlling context of convention. We can also radicalize the thought, following either the Adorno path outlined by Bernstein or the Cavellian line that describes the given as the form of life in language, that even the sensuous exposure to something called ordinary, a spoon at six o’clock in the morning or a mushroom on a log a few steps off of a trail in a park, cannot even arise but for the control of the contexts of life-damaging instrumental reason (Adorno) or the whirl of organism profoundly crossed (and double-crossed) by language that are human forms of life (Cavell).

This is not to suggest that Cavell’s and Adorno’s visions of the ordinary are equal. Cavell shares Adorno’s conviction that the place of art works for philosophy now is no longer self-evident, and Adorno clearly anticipates a thesis so central to Cavell’s work that “all philosophical critique is today possible as the critique of language.”[52] The two philosophers, who both began their professional lives studying music albeit in quite different social and cultural contexts,[53] both single out the late works of Beethoven as a demarcating point for an end of subjectivity, or expressive spontaneity, in the face of conventions.[54] Adorno, in a 1937 essay on “Late Style in Beethoven,” detects subjectivity only in the “irascible gesture with which it takes leave of the works themselves”[55] or in the fusion of tensions that “[leave] the naked tone behind; that sets the mere phrase as a monument to what has been, marking a subjectivity turned to stone.”[56] Adorno portrays Beethoven’s late style as a heap of conventions, a “fractured landscape” through which subjectivity flits only as the light that permits an appearance, “not in order to express itself, but in order, expressionless, to cast off the appearance of art … [leaving] only fragments behind, and [communicating] itself, like a cipher, only through the blank spaces from which it has disengaged itself.”[57]

Thus in the very late Beethoven the conventions find expression as the naked representations of themselves. This is the function of the often-remarked-upon abbreviation of his style. It seeks not so much to free the musical language from mere phrases, as, rather, to free the mere phrase from the appearance of its subjective mastery.[58]

For Cavell, it is the experience of late Beethoven that bears testimony to the thought that “it is as if our freedom to act no longer depends on the possibility of spontaneity; improvising to fit a given lack or need is no longer enough.”[59] Cavell’s thought is to say that the exhaustion of a prior regime of relating subjectivity to convention only indicates a space for an as-yet-unavailable “rediscovery” of music that could compel a recognition of its having inherited this fragmented soundscape and its attendant subject. Though “the entire enterprise of action and of communication has become problematic” and “[t]he problem is no longer how to do what you want, but to know what would satisfy you,” the present choice (the choice within this present, one present to the conditions of what has become of conventions of meaning) “seem to be those of silence, or nihilism …, or statements so personal as to form the possibility of communication without the support of convention – perhaps to become the source of new convention.”[60]

Of course, not everything could fill in here as a continuation. Indeed, “nothing” might go here, and it is possible that our experience of concert music that could be regarded as having been composed in mourning the wake of Beethoven is at an end. What would “walking” mean here or discovering our ability to “go on”? At minimum, it must be remarked that Cavell’s depiction is not aiming at a new, more thoroughly Enlightened, disenchantment of the world through the work of art. Indeed, Cavell is not seeking to relieve a world of its pseudo-enchantments but, rather, always at a “rediscovery” that is never a mere return. In line with the dispossessing or disarming consequences of the givenness of forms of life, which lead to an acknowledgement of separateness in my relation to any other, any possible world that I and others could inhabit, Cavell (from the promptings of Thoreau as much as those of Kierkegaard’s Johannes de Silentio) depicts the world as the object of a doubled activity, heard in the homophones “morning” and “mourning”: the world is to be “regained every day, in repetition, regained as gone.”[61]

This final point is hardly generalizable, apart from whatever can be generalizable in the sense that walking unaided, just as waking (as both awakening and grieving), requires an ability to go on with and through these histories of exposure. Nothing could be a lasting response without exemplifying how one goes on or gets up every day. At times, Cavell frames a lesson after Emerson, Marx, or Nietzsche that, so far, we are not thinking for ourselves, and thus live in a kind of uncreated stasis called “conformity” before the advent of properly human history.[62] Cavell’s thought is not one of redeeming a world or a nature à venir through the silence of artworks or even through a project of critical or negative dialectical thought, because the ordinary, exactly as what might be attained through self-recovery within forms of life, requires (first and last) presence within a world that is beyond recovery by morality, metaphysics, or even works of art (especially after the “break” in a relation to the world of movies described in The World Viewed). Since such a world is only ever experienced as gone, since it is always something to be recovered, we might look towards some of Cavell’s earliest accounts of tragedy, especially the final 20 pages of “The Avoidance of Love,”[63] where he is attempting to square or at least counterpoise a diagnosis that we are “ineluctably actors” in worldly events and also that we have rendered ourselves as an “audience” to these events, or take our agency here as completely theatricalized (awaiting lines and assignments).[64]

I will conclude with two extended citations from “The Avoidance of Love,” which perhaps present Cavell at his most directly despairing (not only because of the war in Vietnam) shorn of the Romantic-Transcendentalist promises that console the lectures from the 1980s (This New Yet Unapproachable America and In Quest of the Ordinary).

What we do not know is what there is to acknowledge, what it is I am to make present, what I am to make myself present to. I know there is inexplicable pain and death everywhere, and now if I ask myself why I do nothing the answer must be, I choose not to. That is, doing nothing is no longer something which has a place insured by ceremony; it is the thing I am doing. … Tragedy, could it now be written, would not show us that we are helpless – it never did, and we are not. It would show us, what it always did, why we (as audience) are helpless.[65]

If a tragedy would not know how to look, which could bring presentness back, still it knows something: it knows that this ignorance is shared by all modernist arts, each driving into itself to maintain the conviction it has always inspired, to reaffirm the value which men have always placed upon it. It knows that, to make us practical, our status as audience will have to be defeated, because the theater no longer provides a respite from action, but one more deed of inaction, hence it knows that theater must be defeated, inside and out. … It knows that this requires that we reveal ourselves and that, as always, this is not occasioned by showing me that something happening is relevant to me … but by showing me something to which I am relevant, or irrelevant. … Our tragic fact is that we find ourselves at the cause of tragedy, but without finding ourselves.[66]

From this Cavellian position, one might summarize the criticism of OA by saying that it is in danger of capitulating to the already prevalent sense that we are destined to be an audience to the world and others by surrendering to and extending a condition of theater as basic to the human sensorium. One can summarize this position’s criticism of Adorno by accusing him of capitulating to philosophical spectatorship precisely by insisting on our tragic role and foreclosing any possibility of awakening, meaningfully, to presence. Although it is not a quiet spectatorship, not by any means. The reader might be able to perceive the self-accusation that is part of the opening lines of the introduction to Negative Dialectics: “Philosophy, which once seemed obsolete, lives on because the moment to realize it was missed. The summary judgment that it had merely interpreted the world … becomes a defeatism of reason after the attempt to change the world miscarried. … [P]hilosophy is obliged ruthlessly to criticize itself.”[67] Pursuing this line further, however, would lead to a separate and long consideration, one that is clearly central to Adorno’s aims in Negative Dialectics and an ongoing desideratum of the Wittgensteinian philosophical practice that Cavell inherits: the end of philosophy.[68] At the very least, it can be said that OA is not capable of envisioning an end (and, hence, a renewal) of its descriptive practice.[69] From both Adorno’s and Cavell’s perspectives, as I have cashed them out here, that is a measure of its distance from what has become of the ordinary.

  1. Funding information: Publishing costs have been covered from the European Research Council (ERC) under the European Union s Horizon 2020 research and innovation program (grant agreement no. 834759).

  2. Conflict of interest: Author states no conflict of interest.

References

Adorno, Theodor W. “Late Style in Beethoven.” In Essays on Music, edited by R. Leppert, trans. S. Gillespie. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 2002 [1937].Search in Google Scholar

Adorno, Theodor W. “Trying to Understand Endgame.” Tr. M. Jones. New German Critique 26 (1982 [1961]), 119–50.10.2307/488027Search in Google Scholar

Adorno, Theodor W. Negative Dialectics, trans. E. B. Ashton. New York, NY: Continuum, 2000 [1966].Search in Google Scholar

Adorno, Theodor W. Aesthetic Theory, edited by G. Adorno and R. Tiedemann, trans. R. Hullot-Kentor. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, 1997 [1970].Search in Google Scholar

Adorno, Theodor W. “Theses on the Language of the Philosopher.” In Adorno and the Need in Thinking, edited by Campbell Burke, Palarmek Kiloh, and Short. Toronto, ON: University of Toronto Press, 2007 [1973].10.3138/9781442683990-003Search in Google Scholar

Altieri, Charles F. Reckoning with the Imagination: Wittgenstein and the Aesthetics of Literary Experience. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2015.10.7591/9781501700552Search in Google Scholar

Benjamin, Walter. Illuminations: Essays and Reflections, edited by H. Arendt, trans. H. Zohn. New York, NY: Schocken Books, 1968.Search in Google Scholar

Berleant, Arnold. The Aesthetics of Environment. Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press, 1992.Search in Google Scholar

Bernstein, Jay M. Against Voluptuous Bodies: Late Modernism and the Meaning of Painting. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2006.10.1515/9781503624474Search in Google Scholar

Bertram, Georg. Art as Human Practice: An Aesthetics, trans. N. Ross. New York, NY: Bloomsbury Academic, 2019.10.5040/9781350063174Search in Google Scholar

Carlson, Allen and Arnold Berleant (eds.). The Aesthetics of Natural Environments. Toronto, ON: Broadview Press, 2004.Search in Google Scholar

Cavell, Stanley. Must We Mean What We Say? A Book of Essays. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press, 2002 [1969].10.1017/CBO9780511811753Search in Google Scholar

Cavell, Stanley. The Claim of Reason: Wittgenstein, Skepticism, Morality, and Tragedy. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 1999 [1979].10.1093/oso/9780195131079.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Cavell, Stanley. In Quest of the Ordinary: Lines of Skepticism and Romanticism. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press, 1988.10.7208/chicago/9780226417288.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Danto, Arthur C. After the End of Art: Contemporary Art and the Pale of History. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1997.Search in Google Scholar

Danto, Arthur C. The Wake of Art: Criticism, Philosophy, and the Ends of Taste, edited by G. Horowitz and T. Huhn. New York, NY: Routledge, 2011 [1998].Search in Google Scholar

Danto, Arthur C. “The Work of Art and the Historical Future.” In “Anything Goes”: The Work of Art and the Historical Future. Townsend Center Lecture at the University of California at Berkeley, 1998.Search in Google Scholar

Eldridge, Richard. The Persistence of Romanticism: Essays in Philosophy and Literature. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press, 2001.Search in Google Scholar

Fletcher, Angus. A New Theory for American Poetry: Democracy, the Environment, and the Future of Imagination. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2004.10.4159/9780674037014Search in Google Scholar

Guetti, Edward. “Ends of Life: Forms of Life as the ‘Ruins of an Enduring Fable’?” Philosophies 8:3 (2023), 46. 10.3390/philosophies8030046.Search in Google Scholar

Guetti, James L. Wittgenstein and the Grammar of Literary Experience. Athens, GA: The University of Georgia Press, 1993.Search in Google Scholar

Harman, Graham. Art and Objects. Medford, MA: Polity Press, 2020.Search in Google Scholar

Hegel, G. W. F. Hegel’s Aesthetics: Lectures on Fine Art. Volume 1, trans. T. M. Knox. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 1975 [1835].10.1093/actrade/9780198244981.book.1Search in Google Scholar

Horkheimer, Max and Theodor W. Adorno. Dialectic of Enlightenment: Philosophical Fragments, edited by G. Schmid Noerr, trans. E. Jephcott. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2002 [1947].Search in Google Scholar

Leddy, Thomas. The Extraordinary in the Ordinary: The Aesthetics of Everyday Life. Toronto, ON: Broadview Press, 2012.10.5040/9781350928527Search in Google Scholar

Light, Andrew and Jonathan M. Smith (eds.). The Aesthetics of Everyday Life. New York, NY: Columbia University Press, 2005.Search in Google Scholar

Moi, Toril. Revolution of the Ordinary: Literary Studies after Wittgenstein, Austin, and Cavell. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press, 2017.10.7208/chicago/9780226464589.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Perloff, Marjorie. 1996. Wittgenstein’s Ladder: Poetic Language and the Strangeness of the Ordinary. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press, 1996.10.7208/chicago/9780226924861.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Pippin, Robert. 2013. After the Beautiful: Hegel and the Philosophy of Pictorial Modernism. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press, 2013.10.7208/chicago/9780226079523.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Quigley, Peter. The Forbidden Subject: How Oppositional Aesthetics Banished Natural Beauty from the Arts. Cambridgeshire, UK: The White Horse Press, 2019.Search in Google Scholar

Quigley, Peter and Scott Slovic (eds.). Ecocritical Aesthetics: Language, Beauty, and the Environment. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 2018.10.2307/j.ctt2204p7fSearch in Google Scholar

Rawls, John. “Two Concepts of Rules.” The Philosophical Review 64:1 (1955), 3–32.10.2307/2182230Search in Google Scholar

Saito, Yuriko. “Everyday Aesthetics.” Philosophy and Literature 25:1 (April, 2001), 87–95. The Johns Hopkins University Press.10.1353/phl.2001.0018Search in Google Scholar

Saito, Yuriko. Aesthetics of the Familiar: Everyday Life and World-Making. Oxford Academic online edition, 2017. Accessed 1 Dec. 2022.10.1093/oso/9780199672103.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Shuster, Martin. “Nothing to Know: The Epistemology of Moral Perfectionism in Adorno and Cavell.” Idealistic Studies 44:1 (2014), 1–29.10.5840/idstudies20152619Search in Google Scholar

Shuster, Martin. “Education for the World: Adorno and Cavell.” In Dissonant Methods: Undoing Discipline in the Humanities Classroom, edited by A. Jaarsma and K. Dobson. Alberta: University of Alberta Press, 2019.Search in Google Scholar

Shuster, Martin. “Some Notes on Philosophy and Redemption: Adorno and Cavell.” Conversations: The Journal of Cavellian Studies 9 (2022), 85–9.10.18192/cjcs.vi9.6248Search in Google Scholar

Smith, Stephen Decatur. “‘We Look Away and Leap Around’: Music, Ethics, and the Transcendental in Cavell and Adorno.” Journal of Music Theory 54:1 (2010), 121–40.10.1215/00222909-2010-015Search in Google Scholar

Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Philosophical Investigations, edited by R. Rhees and G. E. M. Anscombe, trans. Anscombe. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing, 2002 [1953]. Third Edition Reprint.Search in Google Scholar

Yuedi, Liu and Curtis Carter (eds.). Aesthetics of Everyday Life: East and West. Newcastle-upon-Tyne, UK: Cambridge Scholars Publishing, 2014.Search in Google Scholar

Received: 2023-03-07
Revised: 2023-07-11
Accepted: 2023-07-14
Published Online: 2023-08-17

© 2023 the author(s), published by De Gruyter

This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.

Downloaded on 6.5.2024 from https://www.degruyter.com/document/doi/10.1515/opphil-2022-0254/html
Scroll to top button