Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-p2v8j Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-04T21:02:46.057Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Scientism and the value of scientific evidence for religious belief

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  15 September 2023

Jack Warman
Affiliation:
Department of Social Sciences, University of La Frontera, Temuco, Chile
Leandro De Brasi*
Affiliation:
Department of Social Sciences, University of La Frontera, Temuco, Chile
*
Corresponding author: Leandro De Brasi; Email: leandro.debrasi@ufrontera.cl

Abstract

This article presents a novel argument against an application of evidential scientism to religious belief. In particular, our target is those arguments at whose core lies the claim that it ought to be the case that, if one holds religious beliefs, then those beliefs are based on the best scientific evidence. Moreover, rather than focussing on the philosophical puzzles that usually fall within the purview of philosophers of religion, we are interested in the mundane beliefs of ordinary believers about their everyday interactions with God. Our argument combines recent work on epistemic partiality in close personal relationships with insights from analytic theology on the personal nature of believer's relationships with God. We argue that it's inappropriate for believers who take themselves to have a personal relationship with God to base their religious beliefs about God's nature on scientific evidence. In particular, it's precisely because these believers are in a personal relationship with God that it's sometimes inappropriate for them to form their beliefs about God's nature on the basis of scientific evidence.

Type
Original Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alston, W (2005) Beyond ‘Justification’: Dimensions of Epistemic Evaluation. New Haven: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Arpaly, N and Brinkerhoff, A (2018) Why epistemic partiality is overrated. Philosophical Topics 46, 3751.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barbour, IG (2000) When Science Meets Religion: Enemies, Strangers or Partners. New York, NY: Harper Collins Publishers.Google Scholar
Bonjour, L (1978) Can empirical knowledge have a foundation? American Philosophical Quarterly 15, 113.Google Scholar
Brooke, JH (1991) Science and Religion: Some Historical Perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Brown, NJL, Sokal, AD and Friedman, HL (2013) The complex dynamics of wishful thinking: the critical positivity ratio. American Psychologist 68, 801813.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Buckwalter, W (2020) Theoretical motivation of ‘ought implies can’. Philosophia 48, 8394.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buckwalter, W and Turri, J (2020) Knowledge, adequacy, and approximate truth. Consciousness and Cognition 83, 18.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Burch, M (2016) Religion and scientism: a shared cognitive conundrum. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 80, 225241.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, S (1984) Justification and Truth. Philosophical Studies 46, 279295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Connee, E and Feldman, R (2004) Evidentialism: Essays in Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crawford, L (2019) Believing the best: on doxastic partiality in friendship. Synthese 196, 15751593.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dawkins, R (2006) The God Delusion. London: Bantam Press.Google Scholar
Frank, DH (2013) Jewish perspectives on natural theology. In Manning, RR (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Natural Theology. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, pp. 137150.Google Scholar
Frazer, J (2013) Natural theology in eastern religions. In Manning, RR (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Natural Theology. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, pp. 166181.Google Scholar
Fredrickson, BL and Losada, MF (2005) Positive affect and the complex dynamics of human flourishing. American Psychologist 60, 678686.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Friedman, J (2020) The epistemic and the zetetic. Philosophical Review 129, 501536.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Froese, P and Bader, C (2010) America's Four Gods: What We Say about God and What That Says about Us. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Goldberg, S (2019) Against epistemic partiality in friendship: value-reflecting reasons. Philosophical Studies 176, 22212242.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haack, S (2012) Six signs of scientism. Logos and Episteme 3, 7595.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harris, S (2010) The Moral Landscape: How Science Can Determine Human Values. New York, NY: Free Press.Google Scholar
Harrison, P (2017) The Territories of Science and Religion. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Ichikawa, J and Steup, M (2018) The analysis of knowledge. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018 Edition). Available at https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/knowledge-analysis/ (accessed 22 April 2022).Google Scholar
Kawall, J (2013) Friendship and epistemic norms. Philosophical Studies 165, 349370.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keller, S (2004) Friendship and belief. Philosophical Papers 33, 329351.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kornblith, H (2018) Philosophy, science and common sense. In de Ridder, J, Peels, R and van Woudenberg, R (eds), Scientism: Prospects and Problems. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 127148.Google Scholar
Kurthy, M, Lawford-Smith, H and Sousa, P (2017) Does ought imply can? PLoS One 12, e0175206.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ladyman, J (2018) Scientism with a humane face. In de Ridder, J, Peels, R and van Woudenberg, R (eds), Scientism: Prospects and Problems. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 106126.Google Scholar
Liquin, E, Metz, E and Lombrozo, T (2020) Science demands explanation, religion tolerate mystery. Cognition 204, 117.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Marušić, B and White, S (2018) How can beliefs wrong? A Strawsonian epistemology. Philosophical Topics 46, 97114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morrison, RG (2013) Islamic perspectives on natural theology. In Manning, RR (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Natural Theology. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, pp. 150165.Google Scholar
Pew Research Center (2015) Religion and Science: Highly Religious Americans Are Less Like Than Others to See Conflict between Faith and Science. Available at https://www.pewresearch.org/internet/wp-content/uploads/sites/9/2015/10/PI_2015-10-22_religion-and-science_FINAL.pdf (accessed 22 April 2022).Google Scholar
Pigliucci, M (2018) The problem with scientism. APA Blog. Available at https://blog.apaonline.org/2018/01/25/the-problem-with-scientism/ (accessed 22 April 2022).Google Scholar
Pinker, S (2013) Science is not your enemy: an impassioned plea to neglected novelists, embattled professors, and tenure-less historians. New Republic, 6 August 2013.Google Scholar
Planting, A (2000) Warranted Christian Belief. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Principe, L (2015) ¿Scientism and the religion of science. In Williams, R and Robinson, D (eds), Scientism: The New Orthodoxy. London: Bloomsbury, pp. 4162.Google Scholar
Pritchard, D (2017) Faith and reason. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 81, 101118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenberg, A (2011) The Atheist's Guide to Reality. New York, NY: W. W. Norton.Google Scholar
Rosenberg, A (2017) Strong scientism and its research agenda. In Boudry, M and Pigliucci, M (eds), Science Unlimited? The Challenges of Scientism. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, pp. 203224.Google Scholar
Rosenberg, A (2018) Philosophical challenges for scientism (and how to meet them?). In de Ridder, J, Peels, R and van Woudenberg, R (eds), Scientism: Prospects and Problems. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 83105.Google Scholar
Schleifer McCormick, M (Ms) Belief as emotion.Google Scholar
Stenmark, M (2010) Ways of relating science and religion. In Harrison, P (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Science and Religion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 278295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strawson, PF (1962) Freedom and resentment. In Watson, G (ed.), Proceedings of the British Academy 48. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 125.Google Scholar
Stroud, S (2006) Epistemic partiality in friendship. Ethics 116, 498524.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stump, E (1979) Petitionary prayer. American Philosophical Quarterly 16, 8191.Google Scholar
Stump, E (2010) Wandering in Darkness: Narrative and the Problem of Suffering. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Talbot, B (2016) The best argument for ‘ought implies can’ is a better argument against ‘ought implies can’. Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy 3, 377402.Google Scholar
van Inwagen, P (1996) It is wrong, everywhere, always, for anyone, to believe anything upon insufficient evidence. In Jordan, J and Howard-Snyder, D (eds), Faith, Freedom and Rationality. Savage, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, pp. 137154.Google Scholar
van Leeuwen, N (2014) Religious credence is not factual belief. Cognition 133, 698715.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Leeuwen, N (2017) Two paradigms for religious representation: the physicist and the playground. Cognition 164, 206211.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wedgwood, R (2002) Internalism explained. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65, 349369.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, C (2013) The Science Delusion. Hoboken, NJ: Melville House.Google Scholar
Williams, R and Robinson, D (2015) Scienticism: The New Orthodoxy. London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar