Skip to main content
Log in

Methodological considerations for the mechanistic explanation of illusory representations in the context of psychopathology

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A mechanistic explanation is a desired outcome in many studies of perception. Such explanations require discovering the processes that contribute to the realization of a perceptual phenomenon at different levels of information processing. The present analysis aims at investigating the obstacles to develop such mechanistic explanations and their potential solutions in the context of psychopathology. Geometric-Optical Illusions (GOIs) are among perceptual phenomena that have been studied to understand psychopathology in various clinical populations. In the present analysis, the GOIs will be discussed as a methodological tool in the investigation of the mechanistic approach to understanding perception in such populations. I will argue that the fact that most such studies are mainly focused on the investigation of susceptibility to GOIs can only lead to classifying such phenomena or to reporting some correlations between different aspects of such phenomena with certain brain activities, without formulating a mechanistic explanation. The investigation of the variables that mediate perceptual phenomena at earlier stages of information processing is required for the formulation of such explanations. Thus, the objective of the present analysis is twofold: 1) showing how ignoring such variables have prevented the formulation of mechanistic explanations of responses to GOIs in clinical populations, such as schizophrenia and autism, 2) analyzing the methodological aspects of an effective approach in which a top-down guidance based on phenomenological insights (the first-person data) along with the insights provided by the existing theories help overcome obstacles in developing mechanistic explanations of GOIs.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Data availability

Not applicable.

Code availability

Not applicable.

References

  • Adámek, P., Langová, V., & Horáček, J. (2022). Early-stage visual perception impairment in schizophrenia, bottom-up and back again. Schizophrenia, 8(1), 27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adams, R. A., Stephan, K. E., Brown, H. R., Frith, C. D., & Friston, K. J. (2013). The computational anatomy of psychosis. Frontiers in Psychiatry, 4, 47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allen, G., & Courchesne, E. (2001). Attention function and dysfunction in autism. Frontiers in Bioscience-Landmark, 6(3), 105–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, E. J., Tibber, M. S., Schwarzkopf, D. S., Shergill, S. S., Fernandez-Egea, E., Rees, G., & Dakin, S. C. (2017). Visual population receptive fields in people with schizophrenia have reduced inhibitory surrounds. Journal of Neuroscience, 37(6), 1546–1556.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barch, D. M., Carter, C. S., Hachten, P. C., Usher, M., & Cohen, J. D. (1999). The “benefits” of distractibility: Mechanisms underlying increased Stroop effects in schizophrenia. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 25(4), 749–762.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Basso, A., Bisiach, E., & Faglioni, P. (1974). The Mueller-Lyer illusion in patients with unilateral brain damage. Cortex, 10(1), 26–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2006). Discovering cell mechanisms: The creation of modern cell biology. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2009). Molecules, systems, and behavior: Another view of memory consolidation. In J. Bickle (Ed.), Oxford handbook of philosophy and neuroscience (pp. 13–40). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2005). Explanation: A mechanist alternative. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 36(2), 421–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickle, J. (1998). Psychoneural reduction: The new wave. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bleuler, E. (1950). Dementia praecox or the Group of Schizophrenias. International Universities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boeree, C. G. (2000). Gestalt Psychology. Retrieved from http://webspace.ship.edu/cgboer/gestalt.html

  • Bonte, M. (1962). The reaction of two African societies to the Müller-Lyer illusion. The Journal of Social Psychology, 58(2), 265–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bower, M. E. (2020). Husserl on hallucination: A conjunctive reading. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 58(3), 549–579.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brosnan, M. J., Scott, F. J., Fox, S., & Pye, J. (2004). Gestalt processing in autism: Failure to process perceptual relationships and the implications for contextual understanding. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 45(3), 459–469.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butler, P. D., Silverstein, S. M., & Dakin, S. C. (2008). Visual perception and its impairment in schizophrenia. Biological Psychiatry, 64(1), 40–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caparos, S., Ahmed, L., Bremner, A. J., de Fockert, J. W., Linnell, K. J., & Davidoff, J. (2012). Exposure to an urban environment alters the local bias of a remote culture. Cognition, 122(1), 80–85. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2011.08.013

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1981). Eliminative materialism and propositional attitudes. The Journal of Philosophy, 78(2), 67–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cobrinik, L. (1959). The performance of brain-injured children on hidden-figure tasks. The American Journal of Psychology, 72(4), 566–571.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, R. (2018). Understanding the DSM-5: Stasis and change. History of Psychiatry, 29(1), 49–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coren, S. (1970). Lateral inhibition and geometric illusions. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 22(2), 274–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coren, S., & Miller, J. (1974). Size contrast as a function of figural similarity. Perception & Psychophysics, 16(2), 355–357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coren, S., Girgus, J. S., Erlichman, H., & Hakstian, A. R. (1976). An empirical taxonomy of visual illusions. Perception & Psychophysics, 20(2), 129–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F., & Bechtel, W. (2007). Top-down causation without top-down causes. Biology and Philosophy, 22(4), 547–563.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (1983). The nature of psychological explanation. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (2000). “How does it work?” vs. “what are the laws?” two conceptions of psychological explanation. In F. Keil & R. Wilson (Eds.), Explanation and cognition. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Fockert, J., Davidoff, J., Fagot, J., Parron, C., & Goldstein, J. (2007). More accurate size contrast judgments in the Ebbinghaus illusion by a remote culture. Journal of Experimental Psychology. Human Perception and Performance, 33(3), 738–742. https://doi.org/10.1037/0096-1523.33.3.738

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1991). Consciousness explained. Little, Brown.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eronen, M. I. (2019). The levels problem in psychopathology. Psychological Medicine, 1–7.

  • Feyerabend, P. (1962). Explanation, reduction and empiricism. In H. Feigl & G. Maxwell (Eds.), Minnesota studies in philosophy of science (Vol. 3). University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. K. (1965). On the “meaning” of scientific terms. The Journal of Philosophy, 62(10), 266–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1968). Psychological explanation. Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frith, U. (1989). Autism: Explaining the enigma. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frith, U., & Happé, F. (1994). Autism: Beyond theory of mind. Cognition, 50, 115–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (1997). Mutual enlightenment: Recent phenomenology in cognitive science. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 4(3), 195–214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2003). Phenomenology and experimental design. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 10(9–10), 85–99.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Sørensen, J. B. (2006). Experimenting with phenomenology. Consciousness and Cognition, 15(1), 119–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Zahavi, D. (2008). The phenomenological mind. An introduction to philosophy of mind and cognitive science. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gasper, P. (1992). Reduction and instrumentalism in genetics. Philosophy of Science, 59(4), 655–670.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghaemi, S. N. (2009). Nosologomania: DSM & Karl Jaspers' critique of Kraepelin. Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine, 4(1), 1–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Girgus, J. S., Coren, S., Durant, M., & Porac, C. (1975). The assessment of components involved in illusion formation using a long-term decrement procedure. Perception & Psychophysics, 18(2), 144–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gori, S., Molteni, M., & Facoetti, A. (2016). Visual illusions: An interesting tool to investigate developmental dyslexia and autism spectrum disorder. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 10, 175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goto, T., Uchiyama, I., Imai, A., Takahashi, S. Y., Hanari, T., Nakamura, S., & Kobari, H. (2007). Assimilation and contrast in optical illusions 1. Japanese Psychological Research, 49(1), 33–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gregory, R. L. (1978). Eyes and brain: The psychology of seeing (3rd ed.). McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gregory, R. L. (1980). Perceptions as hypotheses. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. B, Biological Sciences, 290(1038), 181–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gregory, R. L. (1987). Illusory contours and occluding surfaces. In The perception of illusory contours (pp. 81–89). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gregory, R. L. (1997). Visual illusions classified. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 1(5), 190–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greist-Bousquet, S., & Schiffman, H. R. (1981). The many illusions of the Muller-Lyer: Comparisons of the wings-in and wings-out illusions and manipulations of standard and dot forms. Perception, 10, 147–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Happé, F. (1994). Wechsler IQ profile and theory of mind in autism: A research note. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 35, 1461–1471.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Happé, F. (1996). Studying weak central coherence at low levels: Children with autism do not succumb to visual illusions. A research note. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 37, 873–877.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Happé, F. (1999). Autism: Cognitive deficit or cognitive style? Trends in Cognitive Science, 3, 216–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hara, M., Kosaka, S., Huang, J., Bleuler, H., & Yabuta, T. (2009). Müller-Lyer illusion effect on a reaching movement in simultaneous presentation of visual and haptic/kinesthetic cues. In 2009 IEEE/RSJ International Conference on Intelligent Robots and Systems (pp. 1253–1258). IEEE.

  • Hempel, C. G., & Oppenheim, P. (1948). Studies in the logic of explanation. Philosophy of Science, 15(2), 135–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henle, M. (1979). Phenomenology in gestalt psychology. Journal of Phenomenological Psychology, 10(1), 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hommel, B. (2020). Pseudo-mechanistic explanations in psychology and cognitive neuroscience. Topics in Cognitive Science, 12(4), 1294–1305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Houlard, N., Fraisse, P., & Hecaen, H. (1976). Effects of unilateral hemispheric lesions on two types of optico-geometric illusions. Cortex, 12(3), 232–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoy, J. A., Hatton, C., & Hare, D. (2004). Weak central coherence: A cross-domain phenomenon specific to autism? Autism, 8(3), 267–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hubel, D. H., & Wiesel, T. N. (1968). Receptive fields and functional architecture of monkey striate cortex. The Journal of Physiology, 195(1), 215–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaeger, T. (1978). Ebbinghaus illusions: Size contrast or contour interaction phenomena? Perception & Psychophysics, 24, 337–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaspers, K. (1963). General Psychopathology (transl. Hoenig, J. & Hamilton, M. W.). The University of Chicago Press.

  • Joober, R., & Tabbane, K. (2019). From the neo-Kraepelinian framework to the new mechanical philosophy of psychiatry: Regaining common sense. Journal of Psychiatry & Neuroscience: JPN, 44(1), 3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kendler, K. S. (2008). Explanatory models for psychiatric illness. The American Journal of Psychiatry, 165, 695–702.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kendler, K. S., Zachar, P., & Craver, C. (2011). What kinds of things are psychiatric disorders? Psychological Medicine, 41, 1143–1150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kéri, S., Kiss, I., Kelemen, O., Benedek, G., & Janka, Z. (2005). Anomalous visual experiences, negative symptoms, perceptual organization and the magnocellular pathway in schizophrenia: A shared construct? Psychological Medicine, 35(10), 1445–1455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • King, D. J., Hodgekins, J., Chouinard, P. A., Chouinard, V. A., & Sperandio, I. (2017). A review of abnormalities in the perception of visual illusions in schizophrenia. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 24(3), 734–751.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klosterkötter, J., Hellmich, M., Steinmeyer, E. M., & Schultze-Lutter, F. (2001). Diagnosing schizophrenia in the initial prodromal phase. Archives of General Psychiatry, 58(2), 158–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knol, H., Huys, R., Sarrazin, J. C., & Jirsa, V. K. (2015). Quantifying the Ebbinghaus figure effect: Target size, context size, and target-context distance determine the presence and direction of the illusion. Frontiers in Psychology, 6, 1679.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koffka, K. (1935). Principles of gestalt psychology. Harcourt, Brace.

    Google Scholar 

  • Köhler, W. (1950). Psychology and evolution. Acta Psychologica, 7, 288–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kraepelin, E. (1950). Dementia praecox and Paraphrenia. International Universities Press, Inc..

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. University of Chicago press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Love, B., Rouder, J., & Wisniewski, E. (1999). A structural account of global and local processing. Cognitive Psychology, 38, 291–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lutz, A., Lachaux, J. P., Martinerie, J., & Varela, F. J. (2002). Guiding the study of brain dynamics by using first-person data: Synchrony patterns correlate with ongoing conscious states during a simple visual task. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 99(3), 1586–1591.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marbach, E. (2010). Towards a formalism for expressing structures of consciousness. In S. Gallagher & D. Schmicking (Eds.), Handbook of phenomenology and cognitive science. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Massaro, D. W., & Anderson, N. H. (1971). Judgmental model of the Ebbinghaus illusion. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 89(1), 147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1960). In A. Danto & S. Morgenbesser (Eds.), The Meaning of Reduction in the Natural Sciences in Philosophy of Science. New York: World Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1961). The structure of science. Harcourt, Brace, and World.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1998). Reductionism and antireductionism. The limits of reductionism in biology, 213, 3–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Navon, D. (1977). Forest before trees: The precedence of global features in visual perception. Cognitive Psychology, 9(3), 353–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nemati, F. (2009). Size and direction of distortion in geometric-optical illusions: Conciliation between the Müller-Lyer and Titchener configurations. Perception, 38(11), 1585–1600.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nemati, F. (2017). Top-down Approach to the Investigation of the Neural Basis of Geometric-optical Illusions: Understanding the Brain as a Theoretical Entity. Archives of Neuroscience, 4(2), e33683. https://doi.org/10.5812/archneurosci.33683

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ninio, J. (1979). An algorithm that generates a large number of geometric visual illusions. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 79, 167–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Notredame, C. E., Pins, D., Deneve, S., & Jardri, R. (2014). What visual illusions teach us about schizophrenia. Frontiers in Integrative Neuroscience, 8, 63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Overgaard, S. (2018). Perceptual error, conjunctivism, and Husserl. Husserl Studies, 34(1), 25–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Panton, K. R., Badcock, D. R., & Badcock, J. C. (2016). A metanalysis of perceptual organization in schizophrenia, schizotypy, and other high-risk groups based on variants of the embedded figures task. Frontiers in Psychology, 7, 237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Park, S. C. (2019). Karl Jaspers’ general psychopathology (allgemeine psychopathologie) and its implication for the current psychiatry. Psychiatry Investigation, 16(2), 99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G., & Craver, C. (2011). Integrating psychology and neuroscience: Functional analyses as mechanism sketches. Synthese, 183(3), 283–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G., & Scarantino, A. (2010). Computation vs. information processing: Why their difference matters to cognitive science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 41(3), 237–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pizzamiglio, L., & Carli, R. (1974). Visual, tactile and acoustic embedded figures tests in patients with unilateral brain damage. Cortex, 10(3), 238–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pokropski, M. (2020). Phenomenology and functional analysis. A functionalist reading of Husserlian phenomenology. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 19(5), 869–889.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pokropski, M. (2022). Mechanisms and consciousness: Integrating phenomenology with cognitive science. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pomerantz, J. R. (1983). Global and local precedence: Selective attention in form and motion perception. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 112(4), 516.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1957). The aim of science. Ratio, I, 24–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1962). Truth, rationality, and the growth of scientific knowledge. In Conjectures and Refutations (pp. 215–50). Basic Books.

  • Pressey, A. W. (1967). A theory of the Mueller-Lyer illusion. Perceptual and Motor Skills, 25(2), 569–572.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1960). Minds and machines. In S. Hook (Ed.), Dimensions of mind: A symposium (pp. 138–164). Collier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1967). Psychological predicates. Art, Mind, and Religion, 1, 37–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quina-Holland, K. & Paszek D. S., (1979). Reducing illusion figures to dots: Not less but different. Paper presented at the Annual Meetings, Eastern Psychological Association, Philadelphia, Pennsylvania.

  • Quine, W. V. (1964). Ontological reduction and the world of numbers. The Journal of Philosophy, 61(7), 209–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rasmussen, E. T. (1953). Berkeley and modern psychology. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 4(13), 2–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, J. O. (1972). The psychology of visual illusion. Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ropar, D., & Mitchell, P. (2001). Susceptibility to illusions and performance on visuospatial tasks in individuals with autism. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 42(4), 539–549.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roy, J.-M., Petitot, J., Pachoud, B., & Varela, F. J. (1999). Beyond the gap: An introduction to naturalizing phenomenology. In J. Petitot, F. J. Varlea, B. Pachoud, & J.-M. Roy (Eds.), Naturalizing phenomenology (pp. 1–83). Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar, S. (1992). Models of reduction and categories of reductionism. Synthese, 91(3), 167–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schouten, M. K., & De Jong, H. L. (1999). Reduction, elimination, and levels: The case of the LTP-learning link. Philosophical Psychology, 12(3), 237–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shah, A., & Frith, U. (1983). An islet of ability in autistic children: A research note. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 24, 613–620.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shah, A., & Frith, U. (1993). Why do autistic individuals show superior performance on the block design task? Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 34, 1352–1364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shorter, E. (2015). The History of Nosology and the Rise of the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders. Dialogues in Clinical Neuroscience, 17, 59–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Silverstein, S. M. (2016). Visual perception disturbances in schizophrenia: A unified model. In The neuropsychopathology of schizophrenia (pp. 77–132). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Silverstein, S. M., & Keane, B. P. (2011). Perceptual organization impairment in schizophrenia and associated brain mechanisms: Review of research from 2005 to 2010. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 37(4), 690–699.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spiegelberg, H. (1972). Phenomenology in psychology and psychiatry: A historical introduction. Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spillmann, L. (2009). Phenomenology and neurophysiological correlations: Two approaches to perception research. Vision Research, 49(12), 1507–1521.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tsal, Y. (1984). A Müller–Lyer illusion induced by selective attention. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 36(2), 319–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uhlhaas, P. J., & Silverstein, S. M. (2003). The continuing relevance of gestalt psychology for an understanding of schizophrenia. Gestalt Theory, 25(4), 256–279.

    Google Scholar 

  • van der Heijden, A. H., & Stebbins, S. (1990). The information-processing approach. Psychological Research, 52(2–3), 197–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J. (1996). Neurophenomenology: A methodological remedy to the hard problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 3, 330–350.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiggins, O. P., Schwartz, M. A., & Spitzer, M. (1992). Phenomenological/descriptive psychiatry: The methods of Edmund Husserl and Karl Jaspers. In Phenomenology, Language & Schizophrenia (pp. 46–69). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Woodger, J. H. (1952). Biology and language. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yung, A. R., & McGorry, P. D. (1996). The initial prodrome in psychosis: Descriptive and qualitative aspects. Australian and New Zealand Journal of Psychiatry, 30(5), 587–599.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2003). Husserl’s phenomenology. Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2010). Naturalized phenomenology. In S. Gallagher & D. Schmicking (Eds.), Handbook of phenomenology and cognitive science (pp. 2–19). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

Not applicable.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Farshad Nemati.

Ethics declarations

Ethics approval

Not applicable.

Consent to participate

Not applicable.

Consent for publication

I give consent for publication of the manuscript.

Conflicts of interest/Competing interests

The author has no conflict of interest to disclose.

Additional information

Publisher’s note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Nemati, F. Methodological considerations for the mechanistic explanation of illusory representations in the context of psychopathology. Phenom Cogn Sci (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-023-09935-w

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-023-09935-w

Keywords

Navigation