Skip to main content
Log in

The pre-intentional, existential feelings, and existential dispositions

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The “pre-intentional” is a proposed category of mental states that conditions a subject’s experience of what is possible for them by, for example, modifying the motivational efficacy or experienced quality of intentional states, like beliefs or desires, without necessarily modifying their propositional content. Matthew Ratcliffe, who has coined the term, identifies the pre-intentional with existential feelings, senses of possibility like “feeling alive” or “feeling deadened,” and argues that these feelings are conditions of the possibility of the scope and valence of intentional states. Jussi Saarinen questions if existential feelings should be understood as consciously occurring episodes or background affective styles, which has implications for the problem of “bi-directionality”: how or if intentional states might affect the pre-intentional. I first argue that answering Saarinen requires, contra Ratcliffe, the introduction of a feeling-disposition distinction: existential feelings are not pre-intentional structures but ways of becoming aware of the “existential dispositions” that are pre-intentional structures. I then propose a new definition of the pre-intentional: existential dispositions are a category of states that are introspectively opaque and so ambiguous between being an intentional state, like a “quasi-belief,” or non-intentional state, like a reflex. This allows for a novel account of what I, following Saarinen’s terminology, call indirect bi-directionality, and thus of indirectly induced existential change, which Ratcliffe only understands as spontaneous. To clarify how intentional states may influence the pre-intentional also clarifies how change in, say, beliefs about what one’s experiences of depression signify may induce existential change that alleviates the suffering of these experiences.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Like Saarinen, I will also “not provide a critical assessment of Ratcliffe’s thinking in respect to its key philosophical sources” and will instead “discuss his account on its own terms” (2018, 364). In my conclusion, however, I will reflect on how what I take to be Ratcliffe’s central error is rooted in the history of phenomenology.

  2. On depression as a compulsion, see Roberts, 2001.

  3. Or: if it is, why stop at two layers of transcendental conditions?

  4. I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for this point.

  5. One case of this pertinent to the example of depression is Benedict Smith’s 2013 “Depression and Motivation.” For Smith, “the character of our bodily nature and not (or not just) our psychology is a basic feature of our agential capacities” (2). Following Merleau-Ponty, Smith rightly points out that perception is structured by a body schema that inclines one toward habitual tasks such that no reflective mental representation of, e.g., a task as doable, mug as reachable, or what have you, is necessary for action. But with the striking claim that motivation is “not psychological,” Smith slips from a concept akin to affordances into a kind of direct realism, locating motivation “in the world” and not “subjectivity” (9). This is functionally what I have called a “felt transcendental schema”: “the body” is supposed to operate as a contingent version of a transcendental schema, the contours of which may be apprehended from how we perceive rather than deduced purely rationally. However, by downplaying the role of reflection in identifying the structures of experience, embodiment comes to imply for Smith a directly perceivable transcendental schema, a mediator that itself needs no mediation to be grasped. This results in too strong of a claim: surely beliefs and desires are both features of “subjectivity” rather than “the world” in some important sense and conditions of motivation. Ratcliffe’s identification of the pre-intentional with existential feelings, I am arguing, is similarly too strong. It too confuses the mediated or what is given, existential feeling and the phenomenological world more broadly, and the mediator or structure of givenness, which I am calling existential dispositions.

  6. This of course raises a broader methodological question about what it means to do phenomenology. In seeking to uncover the structures of experience, those structures must be experienced. Here, I think the key takeaway is that phenomenology requires a method, or at least some practice or art. We are not constantly presented with the structures of our consciousness themselves in the way that we are presented with our existential feelings.

References

  • American Psychiatric Association (2013). Diagnostic and statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (5th edition.). Author.

  • Derrida, J. (2005). On Touching—Jean-Luc Nancy. Stanford University Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and Time. Translated by John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. Harper: San Francisco.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1968). The Visible and the Invisible. Edited by Claude Lefort. Translated by Alphonso Lingis. Northwestern University Press.

  • Noggle, R. (2016). Belief, quasi-belief, and obsessive-compulsive disorder. Philosophical Psychology.

  • Ratcliffe, M. (2008). Feelings of being: Phenomenology, Psychiatry and the sense of reality. Oxford University Press.

  • Ratcliffe, M. (2013). What is it to lose hope? Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 12, 597–614.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ratcliffe, M. (2015). Experiences of Depression: A study in Phenomenology. Oxford University Press.

  • Ratcliffe, M. (2020). “Existential feelings.” In The Routledge Handbook of Phenomenology of Emotion, edited by Thomas Szanto and Hilge Landweer, 249–60. Routledge.

  • Roberts, J. R. (2001). Mental illness, motivation and moral commitment. Philosophical Quarterly, 51(202), 41–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saarinen, J. A. (2018). A critical examination of existential feeling. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 17(2), 363–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (1994). The Moral Problem. Blackwell Publishing.

  • Smith, B. (2013). Depression and motivation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 12(4), 615–635.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swartzer, S. (2015). Humean Externalism and the argument from Depression. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 9(2), 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Devin Fitzpatrick.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Fitzpatrick, D. The pre-intentional, existential feelings, and existential dispositions. Phenom Cogn Sci (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-023-09937-8

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-023-09937-8

Keywords

Navigation