Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-5g6vh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-29T22:39:58.386Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Cruel Optimism of International Prison Regulation: Prison Ontologies and Carceral Harms

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 October 2023

Tom Kemp
Affiliation:
wrote his doctoral dissertation on the law and politics of immigration detention in the UK, looking at the practices of grassroots activist groups that organize alongside people in detention. Email: tom.kemp@nottingham.ac.uk.
Philippa Tomczak
Affiliation:
Principal Research Fellow in Criminology at the University of Nottingham and directs the prisonHEALTH research group. Email: Philippa.tomczak@nottingham.ac.uk.
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This article examines the development of international human rights standards and oversight mechanisms directed at addressing the negative effects of imprisonment. We identify this as the rules-based prison-regulation project, widely endorsed by international organizations and legal scholars. However, with a focus on the United Nations Standard Minimum Rules for the Treatment of Prisoners, we argue that this project has inherent limitations, as it is based on (a) a reductive understanding of carceral harms and (b) a rule-centric ontology of prisons. By challenging these foundations, we explore whether the project exemplifies “cruel optimism” (Berlant, 2011), where the pursuit of improved prison regulation could inadvertently hinder societal flourishing. We argue that the continuous search for new and better prison standards may perpetuate rather than alleviate the problems associated with imprisonment unless accompanied by explicit strategies for countering prison growth and dramatically reducing prisoner numbers, for building the democratic power of prisoners and communities targeted by imprisonment, and continual linkages between prison conditions and the wider political-economic institution of imprisonment. We conclude that engaging with prisons as sites of relational power in practice must underlie any quest to reduce the harms of imprisonment.

Type
Articles
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the American Bar Foundation

INTRODUCTION

The assumption that coherent international human rights standards and associated oversight mechanisms can make carceral institutions less harmful pervades scholarship and practice: according to Coyle (Reference Coyle2003, 9), human rights should suffuse “all aspects of good prison management.” Although prison regulation could refer to diverse activities concerned with “steering the flow of events and behaviour” (Braithwaite, Coglianese, and Levi-Faur Reference Braithwaite, Coglianese and Levi-Faur2007, 3), regulation typically centers on state-centric, legal or quasi-legal mechanisms (see van Zyl Smit Reference van Zyl Smit2010). The principal United Nations (UN) prison regulation instruments are the UN Standard Minimum Rules for the Treatment of Prisoners (SMRs; known as the Mandela Rules), the Convention Against Torture, and the Optional Protocol to the Convention Against Torture. These instruments place an expectation on states to reform prisons, focusing on prison conditions, management. and monitoring as apparent means of attaining greater human rights protection, safety, and transparency. These UN instruments have informed further regional instruments such as the European Prison Rules, produced by the European Council; the Principles and Best Practices on the Protection of Persons Deprived of Liberty in the Americas, adopted by the Organization of American States; and an array of guidelines and declarations by the African Commission on Human and People’s Rights.Footnote 1

The most recent 2015 revision of the SMRs received largely positive analyses. Hailing (Reference Hailing2019, 83) wrote that the Mandela Rules “inevitably have a huge impact on the establishment of human rights standards for prisoners in various countries and the actual improvement of the human rights situations of prisoners.” This 2015 revision process achieved an international consensus that was held to overcome “the presumed opposition between prisoner and facility safety” (Peirce Reference Peirce2018, 268). The revised Rules expand the requirements for states to inspect and monitor prisons, a feature that Rogan (Reference Rogan2021) argues should be replicated across European human rights instruments.

This international rules-based prison-regulation project is driven by well-resourced international nongovernmental and UN organizations including Penal Reform International; the UN Office of Drugs and Crime; and the UN Human Rights Council and UN Subcommittee on Prevention of Torture and other Cruel, Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or Punishment and is broadly supported by sociolegal, law, and criminology academics. Rogan (Reference Rogan2017, 3), for example, characterizes prisons as “eminently rule-bound institutions,” in which rules laid down by (inter)national legal regimes structure the daily lives of both prisoners and staff. Infusing human rights considerations into these rules is advocated as a means of improving prison management and oversight, with incremental improvements to prison rules ostensibly critical to progress. Rogan (Reference Rogan2021, 287) continues, “much more action is necessary to ensure that Europe has an optimal set of standards to direct the work of prison inspection and monitoring bodies.”

A common implication of rules-based prison-regulation project is the establishment of inspection and monitoring bodies that process complaints and produce myriad reports on prisons. For Padfield (Reference Padfield2018, 57), “the closed world of the prison needs both complex accountability mechanisms and clearer rules if high standards are to be effectively enforced.” Yet, standard setting and establishing oversight structures form only the point of departure in the rules-based prison-regulation project. This point of departure needs to be followed by examining the actual regulation of prison conditions—for example, through research assessing which regulatory standards best preserve human rights in practice, a challenge that

manifests itself differently in different parts of the world. In countries with developed national legal and bureaucratic structures, the question is how best to ensure that the existing structures conform to the wider norms. In less developed countries, national regulatory mechanisms need to be established and their compliance with international standards ensured at the same time. (van Zyl Smit Reference van Zyl Smit2010, 555)

Despite some recognition that human rights can be “hijacked’ by risk discourse that supports punitive infrastructures (Whitty Reference Whitty2011) rather than considering whether the rules-based prison-regulation project is fit for purpose in efforts to reduce carceral harms, scholars identifying limitations usually focus on incremental refinements—for example, examining how to effect a more optimal form of human rights management in prisons (Karamalidou Reference Karamalidou2017) or training legal and correctional officers in international human rights law and the SMRs to improve prison conditions (Prais Reference Prais2020). Too frequently, recognition that prisons across the world consistently fail to meet international legal and policy standards serves only to reaffirm belief in the rules-based prison-regulation project: strengthening human rights law and prison standards to better influence global practices of imprisonment (Tiroch Reference Tiroch2016).

Thus, we insert caution into the largely optimistic discussion about the potential for international human rights standards to ameliorate the harms of imprisonment. This is a conceptual article that focuses on theory building through theory adaptation, revising extant knowledge by introducing alternative frames of reference to propose a novel perspective (Jaakkola Reference Jaakkola2020). Here, we problematize van Zyl Smit’s Reference van Zyl Smit2010 call for empirical research about which regulatory standards best preserve human rights in practice instead highlighting fundamental limitations of the rules-based prison-regulation project both “on the books” and “in the cells.” We analyzed a range of academic and gray literature on imprisonment with a focus on conceptualizations of carceral harms, prison ontology, transcarceration, and coloniality. Placing data from these diverse sources in dialogue adds breadth, depth, complexity, and richness to our analysis (Denzin and Lincoln, Reference Denzin and Lincoln2018).

A conventional approach to evaluating the SMRs could entail a sociolegal gap study, highlighting the (in)effectiveness of legal instruments by comparing the law in the books and its perceived objectives with the law in action (Feeley Reference Feeley2001), as suggested by van Zyl Smit (Reference van Zyl Smit2010). Although Gould and Barclay (Reference Gould and Barclay2012) distinguish between early gap studies, which assumed a gap was a failure of the law, and advanced gap studies, which try to understand the conditions in which laws have the consequences they intended, gap studies approach risk, accepting the existing goals and framings of the rules-based prison-regulation project, thus deflecting attention from our more fundamental questions. Our approach begins with perceived gaps between the minimum standards and prison realities and in the ways that the rules imagine carceral harms and regulatory processes. However, and significantly, our gaps are starting points for fundamentally reconceptualizing relationships between international prison regulation and the growing global prisoner population rather than merely conceiving them as implementation gaps. A focus only on identifying and closing gaps between (quasi-)legal standards and practice would obscure the ways that the regulatory mechanisms themselves shape both how prison space becomes known and understood as well as limit the range of responses to the harms of imprisonment that are being pursued. For example, as we will discuss, through prison regulation, the performance of prisons is not judged on their long-term social outcomes but rather on their adherence to rules and standards that have an assumed but unevidenced relationship to delivering better societies.

We argue that international standards—in particular the United Nations Standard Minimum Rules for the Treatment of Prisoners—are problematically based on(a) a reductive understanding of carceral harms and (b) a rule-centric ontology of the prison. Regarding carceral harms, we argue that artificial distinctions between the inherent and excessive harms of imprisonment in the rules-based prison-regulation project frame the prison as fixable, despite evidence that all prison systems create excessive harms, and that the inherent nature of imprisonment contributes to its much-publicized problems. This reductive conceptualization of carceral harms draws attention to the operation of individual institutions and the conditions they create for individual prisoners, deflecting attention from what are frequently systemic issues. In contrast, we draw on interdisciplinary literature supporting a transcarceral approach to understanding carceral harms, which addresses the geographic and temporal reach of imprisonment: people pass through chains of carceral institutions rather than sitting inside single institutions, prisons harm families and communities of prisoners, and prisons have social and economic structural consequences that disproportionately affect particular social groups. Failing to attend to these inherent and transcarceral harms of imprisonment has facilitated numerous instances in which SMR adoption or implementation has coincided with expansions in prison populations, as we will go on to demonstrate.

Second, the rules-based prison-regulation project is based on a rule-centric ontology—in which state-determined rules and policies determine prison life. Therefore, this project fails to engage with contested ontologies of the prison (Bornstein Reference Bornstein2010). In other words, what a prison is—what ought to happen, who should have control, what is just, what subjects populate prisons—is contested within the prison itself. In turn, we argue that prisons are constituted relationally by power in practice, meaning that structural and interpersonal power relations drive both the imperative to imprison and the constitution of imprisonment. Power relations often operate along diverse and context-specific vectors of colonial, capitalist control, along with hierarchical orderings of gender, religion and race. State-determined rules and policies do not exist in a vacuum; rather, power relations between groups of prisoners, communities targeted by criminal justice systems, prison-centered charity and mutual aid groups (Carlton Reference Carlton2016), and wider cultural norms are significant in producing imprisonment. We argue that engaging with prisons as rule-determined institutions is reductionist and risks reaffirming the state’s vision and power. Although prisons everywhere are constituted by power in practice, Western prisons are often assumed to successfully produce the docile bodies of Foucault’s writing (1977; cf. Crewe, Liebling, and Hulley Reference Crewe, Liebling and Hulley2015). Where the bureaucratic state is less powerful—for example, in Latin America (Biondi and Collins Reference Biondi and Collins2016; Darke Reference Darke2018; Whitfield Reference Whitfield2018), Africa (Martin and Jefferson Reference Martin and Jefferson2019), Israel (Bornstein Reference Bornstein2010), and India (Arnold Reference Arnold, Arnold and Hardiman1994), prisons are more readily seen by scholars as being processually constituted by power relations between different groups—primarily prisoners and prison staff. By failing to attend to these relations, increasing prison bureaucracy consistently empowers the state over those who are imprisoned (Armstrong Reference Armstrong2018; Jefferson Reference Jefferson2022). Our understanding of power in practice aligns with processual notions of emergence, which presume that everything in the social world is continually being made, remade, and unmade (Abbott Reference Abbott2016; Renault Reference Renault2016) rather than being determined through replicable applications of legal schema in different contexts.

Throughout this analysis, we argue that (a) reductive understandings of carceral harms and (b) a rule-centric ontology of the prison risks the current prison-regulation project exemplifying “cruel optimism.” Cruel optimism, as Lauren Berlant (Reference Berlant2011, 1) articulates, occurs “when something you desire is actually an obstacle to your flourishing.” We demonstrate how the quest for more and better rules-based prison regulation risks forming an obstacle to rather than a route toward a flourishing society. Arguments for better regulation and accounts of prisons’ failures to meet standards provide important starting points. However, an endless search for new and better prison standards risks expanding and embedding flawed institutions rather than reducing harms. This is especially the case in the absence of explicit strategies for countering prison growth and dramatically reducing prisoner numbers, for building the democratic power of prisoners and communities targeted by imprisonment, and for making continual linkages being made between prison conditions and the wider political-economic institution of imprisonment. Moreover, rules-based prison regulation risks deflecting attention from these central issues. We do not question the commitment, passion, and expertise of the international community. However, in bringing Berlant’s work to bear on international rules-based prison regulation, we highlight that the need to do something about conditions in prisons sustains many compromised efforts for reform. The attachment to a particular mode of law, regulation, and reform is productive of fraught subjects and institutions: we as, for example, academics, nongovernmental organizations, and UN departments are constituted by a “cluster of promises” (Berlant Reference Berlant2011, 16) of a better future that are phantasmic to the extent that they betray the promise of a better society. Increasingly, our attachment to prison reform requires that we adopt “a position that seeks repair of what may be constitutively broken” (Berlant Reference Berlant2011, 227). Thus, the concept of cruel optimism requires us to question the most common sense of reform strategies and to connect them with an examination of the ontology and role of social institutions “outside the realms of ideal theory” (Meer Reference Meer2022, 2).

The concept of cruel optimism has been developed within critiques of multiple social movement projects, from the postwar social democratic state in Berlant’s own work, to the project of racial justice (Meer Reference Meer2022), to movements that centre on sexual consent as sufficient to preventing sexual violence (Kessel Reference Kessel2020). There is an ambivalence within this literature about whether identifying cruel optimism is something to admire and retain because progress and harm reduction can only be made through attempting the impossible (Meer Reference Meer2022; Ray Reference Ray2023). However, we suggest that the difficulties that we identify in this paper require changing approach, and toward the conclusion of this paper, we identify ways to reconceive prison regulation such that we can move beyond cruel optimism.

THE DEVELOPMENT AND CONSEQUENCES OF INTERNATIONAL PRISON REGULATION

The SMRs originated in the European enlightenment ideals of scientific criminology, legal standardization and civilization. They were initially drafted in 1929 by the International Penal and Penitentiary Commission, which began life as the International Penitentiary Congress, a collection of European and colonial state delegates, prison reform societies, lawyers and philanthropists in Middle Temple, London, in 1872 (Wines Reference Wines1873). After a brief life in the League of Nations, the Rules were resurrected by the UN Economic and Social Council in 1957 and were last updated and termed the Mandela Rules in 2015. In 2013, in anticipation of a review of the 1957 SMRs, UN Special Rapporteur on Torture and Other Cruel, Inhuman, or Degrading Treatment or Punishment Juan E. Mendez identified solitary confinement as comprising torture when used for punishment and called for the Rules to be updated in response (Méndez Reference Méndez2013). This pressure led to the 2015 revision, which left the structure broadly the same but targeted particular areas for update and modernized the language used. The updated areas were respect for prisoners’ inherent dignity, medical and health services, disciplinary measures and sanctions, investigations of deaths and torture in custody, protection of vulnerable groups, access to legal representation, complaints and independent inspection, and training of staff (Office for Democratic Institutions and Human Rights and Penal Reform International 2018).

In this section, we demonstrate that, despite this long history and role in internationally significant institutions, the influence of the SMRs on prison regimes around the world is difficult to determine. We argue that their most identifiable outcome is the stimulation of further regional and national rules and monitoring practices that comprise the slow, incremental improvement in minimum standards that are internationally expected of prison systems.

The SMRs are a soft law instrument that do not legally bind states. As there is no direct court-imposed sanction on states that do not adhere to their precepts, the Rules’ influence relies on being an “expressive statement that may shape legislation, policy, and legal decisions” (Peirce Reference Peirce2018, 272). Although the general ideas and rationalities contained in the rules have become part of prison management discourses and textbooks, it is surprisingly difficult to point to examples of successful implementation in particular jurisdictions. For example, van Zyl Smit’s (Reference Smit2019) argument for the existence of a “transnational legal ordering” that encompasses prison conditions identifies its influence by pointing to relatively obscure and sporadically occurring features of criminal justice—such as the transfer of prisoners between territories—as evidence.

The SMRs are sometimes directly adopted by national governments and legal systems. In some countries, particularly those which previously had no domestic legal provisions in this area, the SMRs have been granted a legal status that is enforceable by courts. For example, in 2005, the Argentinian supreme court incorporated the SMRs into the national constitution. In others, governments and prison management have adopted the SMRs to reshape how prisons are run. Nordic prison reforms have included “detailed descriptions of both the UN- and European prison rules” (Lappi-Seppälä and Koskenniemi Reference Lappi-Seppälä and Koskenniemi2018, 136). The Dominican Republic has undertaken extensive prison reforms with the objective of implementing international standards (Peirce Reference Peirce2021). In Thailand, the SMRs were implemented and tested in one prison in 2016: the Thonburi Remand Centre (Thailand Criminology and Corrections 2016). We will return to these examples in the discussion below.

Where the SMRs are not incorporated into an enforceable legal framework or implemented in practice, they sometimes have a mediated legal influence through courts that interpret human rights instruments in line with internationally agreed standards. The tightening of restrictions on solitary confinement in the 2015 Rules has been influential in Canadian Supreme Court cases to determine that the regime of solitary confinement was contrary to the Canadian Charter for Rights and Freedoms.Footnote 2 Peirce (Reference Peirce2018) argues this was because the Mandela Rules are seen to carry the internationally agreed expertise of penologists and prison managers.

More often, regional and national adoption of the minimum standards is through a further set of rules and standards in the translation from general principles of human rights to more finely grained rules for particular regimes (Armstrong Reference Armstrong2018). In Europe, the SMRs influenced the writing of the European Standard Minimum Rules in 1973, which attempted to incorporate the SMRs into the European framework. However, the European Court of Human Rights decided that failing to meet these standards did not necessarily constitute a breach of the prohibition of degrading treatment.Footnote 3 The European Standard Minimum Rules were replaced by the European Prison Rules in 1987, which were updated in 2006 and 2020 and are used by the Council of Europe to promote prison reform across Europe, in particular in post-soviet states (Cliquennois and Champetier Reference Cliquennois and Champetier2016; Walmsley Reference Walmsley1995).

Since the 1970s, the European Court of Human Rights has been gradually but significantly increasing its supervision of imprisonment and the last 20 years have seen more evidence that the European Prison Rules are influencing the Court’s decisions. Initially, complaints based on prison conditions failed because the court accepted that imprisonment inherently led to the loss of other rights and freedoms (van Zyl Smit and Snacken Reference Dirk and Snacken2011).Footnote 4 However, in Golder v UK (1975), the Court found that rights infringements against prisoners had to be accompanied by a condition of proportionality and legality. The European Court of Human Rights has traditionally been stronger in protecting procedural rights of prisoners that are explicitly protected under the European Convention on Human Rights than in intervening in prison administration and finding violations of Article 3 (the prohibition of torture, inhuman and degrading treatment) based on poor prison conditions (van Zyl Smit and Snacken Reference Dirk and Snacken2011). However, Peers v. Greece Footnote 5 determined that Article 3 could be applied to prison conditions even where the harmful conditions were not deliberately inflicted. In Ivan Karpenko v. Ukraine,Footnote 6 the court took note of the fact that the SMRs had not been followed in finding a violation of Article 3 and Article 8 regarding being deprived of social contact with other prisoners.

Similar moves have been made at the continental level in Africa and Latin America. In 1996, the African Commission appointed a Special Rapporteur on Prisons and Conditions of Detention, who has referenced the SMRs in reporting on African prisons and adjudicating prisoners’ rights cases before the Commission. The Rapporteur has also published further guidelines on the conditions of imprisonment: Resolution on the Adoption of the Ouagadougou Declaration and Plan of Action on Accelerating Penal and Prison Reform in Africa 2002 and the Robben Island Guidelines 2002. The Organization of American states adopted the Principles and Best Practices on the Protection of Persons Deprived of Liberty in the Americas in 2008 and this set of soft-law prison regulations has, notably, been far more willingly incorporated into the Inter-American Court of Human Rights’ case law than has been the case in Europe (Seatzu and Fanni Reference Seatzu and Fanni2015; Gronowska Reference Gronowska2017).

The SMRs also provide a significant basis for UN and civil society reports that may grant legal bases for reform efforts. The United Nations Human Rights Committee has referred to them when interpreting the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights—for example, that placing someone in a cell with no light constitutes degrading treatment contrary to Article 7 (van Zyl Smit Reference van Zyl Smit2010).Footnote 7 International and national monitoring organisations also draw on the SMRs to frame criticisms of prison systems. It remains true that “the practical effect of the Rules depends to a great extent upon the way they eventually permeate national and local law making, administrative regulations or correctional practice” (United Nations Secretariat 1970, 32).

The relatively successful processes of encouraging regional and national legal regimes to recognize and replicate the SMRs has occurred in a time when the problems of prisons have escalated globally. Significantly, global prisoner numbers are increasing: in 2003, there were over nine million people in prison, 19 years later we have over 11 million people in prisons, which are said to be in ever more crisis (Penal Reform International 2022). In the following sections, we provide an analysis of this prison-regulation project that attempts to explain why advancing rules-based prison regulation is consistent with such increasing prisoner numbers and crisis.

CONCEPTUALIZING CARCERAL HARMS

The Reductive Conceptualization of Carceral Harms

The Mandela Rules have a narrow and reductionist conception of the harms of imprisonment such that they prevent an adequate understanding of prison and its effects. In this section, we outline how the Rules problematically construct two categories of carceral harm. The harms in the first category result from excessively punitive prison conditions—such as lack of health care, absence of windows, torturous disciplinary regimes—that are said to be both illegitimate and reformable (nonessential to institution of imprisonment). In prisons that conform to the minimum standards, these avoidable harms would not occur. The second category of harms, implicitly referred to in the SMRs, includes those harms that are inherent to imprisonment. Research has found that imprisonment in all its forms imposes significant harms that are not contingent on prison conditions. For example, imprisonment is a stressor that can induce psychological disturbance among those with no prior disorder (Liebling Reference Liebling, Jewkes, Crewe and Bennett2007, 433). Drake (Reference Drake2018) draws comparisons between prison ethnographies in Zambia (Egelund Reference Egelund2016) and Norway (Shammas Reference Shammas2014) to show that, despite vast differences in prison conditions, similar existential fears and personal deprivations were foundational to the prisoner experience—psychological consequences of the loss of autonomy, relationships, heterosexual sex, for example.

The Rules attempt to address the first form of excessive harms, making them visible and rendering them unnecessary, illegitimate and addressable aspects of imprisonment. The SMRs explicitly seek to reduce harm that exceeds that which is “incidental to the justifiable separation or the maintenance of discipline” (Rule 3). They acknowledge the inherent suffering of prison, but the rules focus attention on the adverse prison conditions and the practices of prison management that govern the conditions of prisoners, foregrounding harms that occur locally—in time and space—to individual prisoners and the setting they are in. The archetypal form of harm is torture and inhuman and degrading treatment, as outlined in Rule 1. Attention is also given to less severe but important aspects of prison life such as the cleanliness of living spaces (Rule 17), the size of windows (Rule 14), access to health care (Rule 24), and sanitary equipment (Rule 15, 16, 18). It also incorporates aspects of prison bureaucracy, in so far as these might reduce harm, by separating prisoners into categories (for example, by gender, age, conviction) and limiting contact between them (Rule 11); keeping detailed records of prisoners (Rules 6–10); placing restrictions on the processes and forms of punishment, discipline, and restraint that are available to prison guards (Rules 36–49); ensuring there are complaints mechanisms (Rules 56–57); and ensuring there are prison inspections (Rules 83–85). The harms of failing to implement these measures are made visible by the Rules and, in being named, are presented as unnecessary aspects of imprisonment.

Of course, the differences between the conditions faced by prisoners are important: places with less disease and fewer deaths are of benefit. However, the inherent harms of imprisonment are concealed and implicitly accepted within this paradigm. This distinction problematically minimizes and invisibilizes significant harms that scholarship has identified as inherent to imprisonment and presents harms that are endemic to imprisonment globally as exceptional and reformable. This problematic conception of carceral harm allows rules-based regulation to function as a form cruel optimism by sustaining a fantasy that all prison systems could emulate an idealized vision of “acceptable” northern European prisons (Drake, Reference Drake2018).

Although the SMRs refer briefly to the “suffering inherent” to imprisonment (Rule 3), this is underresearched and underacknowledged in human rights and regulatory scholarship, which focuses on, for example, evaluating discrete prison programs or monitoring programs (Carver and Handley Reference Carver and Handley2020; Rogan Reference Rogan2021), paying close and perhaps disproportionate attention to small variations in carceral practice but relatively little to the inherent effects of imprisonment itself.

Moreover, widely recognized problems—including elevated mortality rates, disease, mental ill-health, drug dependency, and sexual violence that are endemic to prisoner populations globally (Wolff et al. Reference Wolffe, Cynthia Blitz, Bachman and Siegel2006; OHCHR 2019)—persist in all prisons systems, yet they are consistently represented as fixable by addressing aspects of prison management (Aon, Larson, and Brasholt Reference Aon, My Warborg Larson and Brasholt2018). Imprisonment is consistently directed at those from the most disenfranchised groups in any country: those who are poorest (Wacquant Reference Wacquant2009), least educated, those with mental health conditions and learning difficulties (Blagg, Tulich, and Bush Reference Blagg, Tulich and Bush2017), and those from populations that do not comply with social norms and who threaten political and economic elites. Prisons create and compound dispossession and social exclusion by enforcing harmful gender norms (Pemberton Reference Pemberton2013) and targeting oppressed racialized and indigenous groups (Razack Reference Razack2015; Stanley and Mihaere Reference Stanley and Mihaere2019; George et al. Reference George, Norris, Deckert and Tauri2020). Prisoners have consistently been significantly more likely to die at a younger age than people in the community due to long-standing factors including elevated rates of self-inflicted death among prisoners relative to the community (Zhong et al. Reference Zhong, Morwenna Senior, Amanda Perry, Shaw and Fazel2021), prison violence, the prevalence of communicable diseases, and inadequate health care (Liu et al. Reference Liu and de Oliveira2021). Indeed, Nordic countries that are often considered to have exceptional prisons were found to have the highest prisoner suicide rate in a study of 24 high-income countries (Fazel et al. Reference Fazel, Ramesh and Hawton2017; see also Morthorst et al. Reference Morthorst, Mehlum, Pàlsson, Mühlmann, Hammerlin, Madsen, Nordentoft and Erlangsen2021).

In addition, the SMRs function to render harms that are present in all prison systems as exceptional. The fact that there are significant gaps between the expectations of the SMRs and the realities of prison conditions is, of course, accepted by proponents of international penal regulation: it serves to justify the rules-based prison-regulation project and provides impetus for the development of monitoring institutions and procedures. However, the fact that no prison system systematically meets international standards is too rarely acknowledged. In the rules-based prison-regulation project, the problem is generally seen to occur in developing states that have low resources. However, even in Europe, where prison conditions are considered to be informed by human rights concerns (van Zyl Smit Reference van Zyl Smit2006), the Rules are systematically broken. Prisons in the UK, for example, routinely hold people in bleak cell conditions in which people shared unsuitable rooms with uncovered toilets, some of which were described as “cramped, squalid and unsuitable for habitation” and some “infested with vermin” (HMIP 2017, 3, 13). Slopping out—formally abolished in 1996 and contrary to Rule 15 of the SMRs—was still evident in UK prisons in 2019 (Bulman Reference Bulman2019; Casciani Reference Casciani2010).

Furthermore, solitary confinement was a flagship change to the 2015 SMRs revision. Rule 44 now recognizes that “solitary confinement shall refer to the confinement of prisoners for 22 hours or more a day without meaningful human contact. Prolonged solitary confinement shall refer to solitary confinement for a time period in excess of 15 consecutive days.” The Rules now prohibit indefinite and prolonged use of solitary confinement generally and its use on prisoners who have mental and physical disabilities that would be exacerbated by such conditions. Solitary confinement should now only be used in exceptional cases and for as short a time as possible and be subject to review. However, solitary confinement remains part of the ordinary running of prisons: in 2017, HMIP in England and Wales found that “in local prisons 31% of prisoners report being locked in their cells for at least 22 hours a day” (HMIP 2017, 3). Solitary confinement became the de facto condition of almost all prisoners in the UK during the COVID-19 pandemic. Her Majesty’s Inspectorate of prisons stated in July 2020 that “for the last 12 weeks, most prisoners had spent at least 23 hours locked up each day” (Robins, Reference Robins2020). In prisons and other detention settings, solitary confinement has been systematically imposed to deal with mental health crises and resistance. As UN Special Rapporteur on Torture and Other Cruel, Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or Punishment Nils Melzer noted in 2021, Closed Supervision Centres (CSC) that have been a part of UK prisons since 1998 are akin to solitary confinement. He noted that prisons are granted £100,000 annually for every inmate in CSCs and that decision making on who should be held in these centres may not be exclusively based on individual assessment (OHCHR, 2021). One prisoner, Kevin Thakrar, has been held in a CSC for over 11 years (Siddique, Reference Siddique2021). There is widespread use of segregation and cell confinement in UK immigration-detention settings to deal with mental health issues, to manage those at risk of self-harm, and as a tool to aid removal (Medical Justice 2015; Medical Justice and Bail for Immigration Detainees 2021).Footnote 8 In summary, the human rights focus on solitary confinement as an issue of human rights concern effaces the reality of imprisonment by rendering the systematic isolation of prisoners as a “bug” of imprisonment rather than a “feature” of it.

Even the well-regarded Nordic prison systems place people under stress that causes profound harm. Empirical studies have shown that Nordic prisons produce suffering through the deprivation of autonomy similar to that of prisons in harsher systems (Reiter, Sexton, and Sumner Reference Reiter, Sexton and Sumner2018). Nordic exceptionalism—the idea of a really-existing prison system that is small, well-resourced, causes little harm, and is characterized by openness—overlooks both the experiences of people imprisoned in supposedly humane prisons, which are marked by suffering (Drake Reference Drake2018), and the ways in which Nordic prisons continue to use harsh practices—for example, the widespread use of pretrial solitary confinement in prisons in Sweden, Denmark, and Norway (Smith Reference Smith, Ugelvik and Dullum2011). Ultimately, the notion of Nordic exceptionalism feeds the fantasy that it would be possible to transform all prison systems, from the more technologically advanced but overly punitive systems in the US and UK, to places where prisons are poorly resourced and more overcrowded and where there is a high level of poverty and unemployment in the general population (Sarkin Reference Sarkin2008), to prison systems that, to use Penal Reform International’s mission statement, “uphold human rights for all and do no harm” (Penal Reform International 2023).

To summarize, the SMRs construct an artificial distinction between carceral harms that are exceptional and those that are inherent and enduring. This section has argued that this delineation is problematic because prison standards are breached systematically and the inherent and enduring harms of imprisonment are rendered invisible. The labeling and treatment of Rules as minimum standards when these are in practice only aspirational serves to diminish abilities to properly appreciate and respond to the harms of imprisonment, contributing to what Jefferson (Reference Jefferson2022, 8) calls “structural blindness.” Thus, the presentation of carceral harm in the SMRs allows regulation to function as a form of cruel optimism by obscuring the inherent harms of imprisonment and problematically presenting the excessive harms as fixable.

Reconceiving Carceral Harms: A Transcarceral Approach

The conception of carceral harm in the SMRs has a further deficiency: by misrepresenting prisons as bounded, isolated institutions they preclude analysis of the prison as part of a transcarceral chain of institutions that marginalize, surveille, supervise, and imprison. Here, we argue that it is necessary to shift toward an understanding of the prison as an institution with substantial (yet rarely acknowledged) geographical and temporal reach to reckon with carceral harms that occur at a distance from the prison space and time as well as those that are collectively rather than individually felt. These radiating harms are systematically produced consequences of imprisonment but are too commonly conceptually distanced from the direct treatment of an individual prisoner contained in a single institution at a single point. The SMR’s focus on the contemporaneous effects of carceral institutions on an individual prisoner is challenged by ethnographic and sociolegal approaches that “take[s] issue with the most commonly attributed feature of ‘the’ prison [in the human rights literature]: its presumed closed, walled-off, separateness from society” (Martin and Jefferson Reference Martin and Jefferson2019, 137).

In their focus on producing rules for implementation by prison management, the SMRs conceive the treatment of prisoners largely in terms of a static prisoner that remains in one institution long term. However, the prison is “structurally connected to other penal institutions” (Ellis Reference Ellis2021, 180). Flows into prisons are influenced by experience of both the school system (Mallett Reference Mallett2016) and the care system (Day, Bateman, and Pitts Reference Day, Bateman and Pitts2020). Once under the supervision of the criminal justice system, people are transferred through distinct carceral institutions—for example, to and from police custody—and frequently secure mental health facilities (Leonard, Sanders, and Shaw Reference Leonard, Sanders and Shaw2021) and immigration detention (BiD 2013). Each new environment requires the detainee to familiarize themselves with a different set of expectations, challenges, rules, personnel, and oversight bodies. As sets of Rules and oversight bodies are attached to discrete institutions, systemic issues that travel between distinct institutions are often missed.

The Rules’ focus on the contemporary experience of prison itself overlooks the longitudinal harms to which prison contributes. The harms of imprisonment can be felt after a prison sentence. Evidence of the criminogenic character of imprisonment (Cid Reference Cid2009; Gaes and Camp Reference Gaes and Camp2009) means that prisons are likely to exacerbate harm. This is to say little of the prison’s effects on employment (Holzer Reference Holzer, Raphael and Stoll2009), housing (Greenberg and Rosenheck Reference Greenberg and Rosenheck2008; Madoc-Jones et al. Reference Madoc-Jones, Caroline Hughes, Sarah Dubberley, Ahmed, Lockwood and Wilding2018), and health, along with elevated mortality rates among prisoners after release—especially among women prisoners (Carlton and Segrave Reference Carlton and Segrave2011). These long-term effects of imprisonment compound histories of dispossession and exclusion faced by the communities targeted by imprisonment. This longitudinal view of carceral harm is expressed by Carlton and Segrave (Reference Carlton and Segrave2011, 556):

The accounts offered by women and caseworkers consistently challenged the notion of incarceration as an isolated traumatic event. Rather, we found that state intervention and institutionalization often featured throughout these women’s lives. In this regard, the focus on the “pains’ of imprisonment and the impacts of incarceration is replaced by a broader conceptualization of traumatic experiences and an examination of the interaction between these experiences of structural disadvantage and institutional harms inflicted across a lifetime.

As innovations in carceral geography and criminology have illuminated, more work is needed to understand how the prison space is inscribed into individuals and groups, who carries the burden of incarceration with them in ways that index further harm (Moran Reference Moran2014; Chamberlen Reference Chamberlen2016; Keenan Reference Keenan and Philippopoulos-Mihalopoulos2019). The geography of prison harm is not limited to the life paths of the prisoner; rather, the range of people who are harmed by imprisonment exceeds the prisoner. Families, dependents, friends, and communities of the imprisoned are harmed by imprisonment. Kincaid, Roberts, and Kane (Reference Kincaid, Roberts and Kane2019) found that 312,000 children are affected by parental imprisonment in the UK each year, with 54% of prisoners having children under 18. Partners of prisoners deal with loss of income, increased expenditure, social isolation, and extra burdens of childcare (Murray Reference Murray, Liebling and Maruna2005). Because particular communities within each jurisdiction are overpoliced, imprisonment results in significant community-based social disruption (Clear, Rose, and Ryder Reference Clear, Rose and Ryder2001). These combine to create an intergenerational effect of prison on future adults’ mental health and interaction with the prison system—65% of prisoners’ sons are later subject to criminalization (Kincaid, Roberts, and Kane Reference Kincaid, Roberts and Kane2019). Prison staff are themselves harmed by working in the stressful prison environments, in particular because of the proximity to the inevitable and distressing events of prisoner suicides (Banwell-Moore et al., Reference Banwell-Moore, Tomczak, Wainwright, Traynor and Hyde2022).

Finally, moments of harm and grief are often starting points for addressing root causes (Brown Reference Brown2021). The prison perpetuates cycles of violence through dispossession, inequality, and stress on mental and physical health by channeling responses to harm into a punitive rather than reparatory and transformative mode (GenerationFIVE 2017). We should count these opportunity harms—the failure to take paths that will prevent similar harms happening in future—as part of the harms of growing imprisonment.

As a document that is used to direct prison reform discourse across sectors and to legitimize prison policy by nation states, the Rules’ narrow institutional focus fails to account for significant carceral harms. The SMRs are agreed by states that want to maintain sovereignty over their criminal justice systems (Peirce Reference Peirce2018), illuminating why the SMRs exclude these features of the prison. Yet, the effect is to create, in Owers’s (Reference Owers and Jewkes2007, 17) words, a “virtual prison” not just in the heads of prison administrators (as in Owers’s work) but in the prison monitoring community and wider project of rules-based prison regulation (See also Carlen Reference Carlen2008).

Thus, prison regulation must contend with the transcarceral nature of punitive states rather than limiting the understanding of prison to contemporaneous analysis of the dyadic relation between the individual prisoner and the prison state (Palacios Reference Palacios2016). This requires recognizing and responding to harms that result from the flows of people—staff, prisoners, visitors—in and out of the prison; through chains of carceral institutions—for example, the care–prison pathway; the longitudinal harms of imprisonment for individuals, families, and communities; and the adverse social, environmental, and economic consequences of prisons. Adopting such a perspective reveals the limited and narrow imaginary of carceral harm that underlies international rules-based prison regulation while valuably extending attention throughout an individual’s journey through criminal justice institutions and to the effects of imprisonment on a wider group of people than the imprisoned.

Rates of Imprisonment: The Elephant in the Room

By failing to reckon with the broad array of harms of imprisonment, rules-based prison regulation risks enabling the expansion of carceral harms. It is striking that the Mandela Rules fail to mention, let alone express, targets regarding prisoner numbers or rates. Although there are frequent gestures toward reducing the numbers of remand prisoners and using alternative sentences in UN reports and in the Tokyo Rules for noncustodial sentences, there is a problematic and long-running assumption that improvements in prison conditions and the development of alternatives to imprisonment will inevitably reduce prison populations.

In 1970, the UN Secretariat acknowledged that “the movement to keep as many offenders as possible out of the institutions had already gathered momentum when the Rules were established. The Rules acknowledge this in tone if not in terminology” (United Nations Secretariat 1970, 4, emphasis added). Notwithstanding whether this assumption was fair in 1970, over the subsequent 50 years continued belief that human rights, prison standards, and the development of alternatives to imprisonment will result in overall reductions in imprisonment has been demonstrably complacent. Yet, the assumption that human rights and penal regulation have inherently decarceral effects is still frequently defended (van Zyl Smit and Snacken Reference Dirk and Snacken2011). Consequently, efforts to reform imprisonment subsume decarceral strategies: for example, in 2020 Penal Reform International had a total expenditure of £4 million, with £1.8 million going toward prison reform and just £17,000 allocated to reducing the use of imprisonment (Penal Reform International 2021).

It is notable that efforts to incorporate the SMRs into national law and practice consistently coincide with expansions of the inherently harmful prison system. Implementation of the SMRs into Argentinian law, for example, coincided with an increase in the rate of imprisonment (rates given per 100,000 population) from 174 in 2015 to 230 in 2018, representing around 28,000 more prisoners.Footnote 9 In Thailand, experimenting with a “full implementation’ of the SMRs in one prison occurred alongside an increase in the imprisonment rate from 437 in 2016 to 516 in 2020, an increase of 58,000 prisoners.Footnote 10 Uganda’s imprisonment rate expanded from 87 in 2002 to 133 in 2014, which entailed almost tripling its prison estate to hold 40,000 additional prisoners, with the Ugandan Prison Service attracting substantial external funding through seeking to “be a center of excellence in providing human rights–based correctional service in Africa” (Martin Reference Martin2014, 71).Footnote 11 After the Dominican Republic implemented prison reforms in 2003, the prison population increased significantly from 14,000 to 26,000 (Peirce Reference Peirce2021). The coincidences of SMR implementation and expansions in prison populations must be a central consideration for all nongovernmental organizations (NGOs), academics, and practitioners concerned with ameliorating the harms of imprisonment. In the remainder of this section, we explore the central analytical distortions that produce the idea that addressing prison conditions will have a decarceral effect, paying particular attention to overcrowding and alternatives to detention.

Despite decades of SMRs and moves toward a transnational legal ordering of imprisonment, overcrowding still affects the majority of prison systems, “with more than 50 UN Member States operating prison services at more than 150 per cent of their official capacity” (United Nations 2021, 5). Calls to reduce overcrowding are not a straightforward good and must be problematized. Increasing imprisonment results in overcrowding, which exposes more people to the inherent harms of imprisonment, but commentators very frequently focus on overcrowding primarily as a barrier to the achievement of adequate prison conditions (Council of Europe 2022). The discourse around overcrowding produces ostensibly convincing demands that can unfortunately easily be routed toward reforms facilitating prison expansion and potentially increased privatization (Carlton Reference Carlton2016). For example, the UN’s rhetoric in the 2021 Common Position on Incarceration sounds positive. It espouses the need for “effective and sustainable reform efforts [that] require a holistic reform approach aimed at addressing the root causes of overincarceration and overcrowding, and shifting policies towards prevention and alternatives to imprisonment” (United Nations 2021, 15). However, the specifics of which root causes of overincarceration are to be addressed and a clear idea of what exactly the community is trying to prevent are lacking. For example, decriminalization programs would be one effective way to address the root causes of overincarceration (Robinson Reference Robinson, Buxton, Margo and Burger2020), but the UN’s statement could just as easily be read as supporting an increase in criminalization and preventative detention under the guise of crime prevention. This vague discourse creates unfocused efforts to address overcrowding, which gesture at reduction while risking the expansion of carceral systems and the proliferation of all their enduring harms.

Similarly, the development of alternatives to incarceration is well recognized to be insufficient to reduce imprisonment rates. In fact, there is an association in some countries (such as France, Portugal, Greece, and Spain) between the introduction of alternatives and increases in prison populations (Tabar, Miravalle, and Torrente Reference Tabar, Miravalle and Torrente2016). The promotion of alternatives also masks net-widening effects of many alternatives to incarceration (Cohen Reference Cohen1985). The promotion of alternatives tends to be oriented toward punishment (curfews, tagging, unpaid work) that are promoted within an increasingly privatized criminal justice market (Worrall Reference Worrall, Carlen and França2019) rather than being founded on principles of minimal intervention and transformative-justice approaches to preventing and resolving harm (GenerationFIVE 2017; Ben-Moshe Reference Ben-Moshe, Fritsch, Monaghan and van der Meulen2022).

Large prison populations subject more people, families, and communities to harmful, expensive, and largely dysfunctional institutions; this problem cannot be reduced to the inhumane and dangerous conditions that overcrowding gives rise to. Since the 1970s, the number of people imprisoned globally has increased, reaching 11.5 million in 2022 (Prison Reform International 2022). The idea that UN documents and reports can effectively communicate disapproval of increasing numbers of people being imprisoned through the tone of their writing and allusions to root causes is misguided. Part of the problem is that the project of prison regulation separates the external governance of the prison (who is incarcerated) from the internal governance (the requirements for prison management). In the next section, we argue that this separation of is premised on an inadequate ontology of the prison itself. Shifting to a view of imprisonment as part of a chain of transcarceral institutions that is shaped by power in practice rather than shaped only by institutionally specific rules is the focus of the next sections.

CONTESTED PRISON ONTOLOGIES

Prisons Are (Un)Ruly Institutions

The rules-based prison-regulation project has stimulated the proliferation of rules used in prison management and mechanisms to monitor prisons. However, this focus on establishing and improving the rules by which prisons run frequently fails to bolster the power of prisoners to challenge conditions (See Hughett Reference Hughett2019). On the contrary, the evidence we discuss in this section shows that international penal regulation processes frequently exclude prisoners from decision making, strengthen prison bureaucracy, and increase the responsibilities of prisoners (Armstrong Reference Armstrong2018). This section argues that regulation efforts based on conceptualizations of the prison as a rule-defined institution are likely to consolidate state power over communities that are targeted by imprisonment, highlighting that this implication can no longer be overlooked by the rule-making communities.

Advocates of a more unified system of incrementally improving legal standards for prisons conceptualize prisons as rule-bound institutions (Rogan Reference Rogan2017). Consequently, improving the framework of rules through which prisons operate and prisons’ adherence to that framework appears the best, or perhaps the only, way to improve prison conditions. This apparently rule-bound nature allows prisons to be seen as core elements of democracy. Creating a rule-compliant prison helps to fulfil the prison’s role in state building through producing institutions that are seen to hold rule of law and liberal democratic values (Drake Reference Drake2018). Indeed, in 2010, the UN Department of Peacekeeping Operations wrote that “prisons are an essential link in the rule of law chain” (cited in Drake Reference Drake2018, 6). The reality that punitive institutions are run essentially through the discretionary powers of prison staff is anathema to the pervasive republican-democratic notion that legitimate state power cannot be arbitrary in the sense that it does not follow “effective, common-knowledge” procedural rules (Lovett Reference Lovett2012).

However, as Lazar (Reference Lazar2019) argues, the fact that carceral institutions can apparently adhere to a consistent set of rules does not preclude the prisoner’s experience of domination. The growing number of rules that prisons are expected to comply with does not necessarily result in more power for those in prison to challenge conditions they perceive as unjust (Hughett Reference Hughett2019) nor in fewer people being exposed to dominating conditions. Even if we accept that prisons do adhere to rules imposed on them, making a dominating institution more predictable does not make it less dominating.

Prisons and their current forms of rule-based regulation are profoundly undemocratic. Throughout the history of the SMRs, the existing practice and knowledge of correctional managers and officers have been influential. In 1978, Rubin Kraiem, writing in support of implementation of the SMRs, said that to incorporate human rights standards in prisons “requires that we assume the positions both of the philosopher and of the correctional officer” (1978, 159). The clear and consistent omission is prisoners themselves. Kraiem’s sentiment of moderation was echoed in Penal Reform International’s attempts to moderate the demands of other civil society actors in the Mandela Rules revision and in the influential contributions of corrections officers in that process (Peirce Reference Peirce2018). The SMRs have been created through engagement with the criminological expertise of informants, prison governors, NGOs, and governments. Prisoners’ views were excluded from the Mandela Rules redesign (Peirce Reference Peirce2018), as were the voices of organizations who were more critical of imprisonment. This mirrors the exclusion of prisoners’ views from the recommendations of other international oversight bodies such as the European Committee for the Prevention of Torture and Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or Punishment (O’Connell and Rogan Reference O’Connell and Rogan2022).

Moreover, extensive scholarship has identified how extending human rights regimes into prisons can bolster bureaucracy and the power of the prison system over those it confines and can lead to increased funding that enlarges prisons. For example, Armstrong (Reference Armstrong2018) details how human rights approaches to prison rules can produce myriad capillary rules and a vast bureaucracy surrounding the prison, along with renewed legitimacy. Examples of this tendency can be gleaned from around the world. In Argentina and Chile, “rehabilitation programmes ended up combined with managerial standards and priorities that facilitated privatization of prisons and eventually got displaced for security priorities” (Hathazy Reference Hathazy2016, 165). In Uganda, the implementation of human rights in prisons became a form of governance that “invigorates bureaucratic power and enables institutional reproduction” (Martin Reference Martin2017, 247). Hannah-Moffat (Reference Hannah-Moffat2004), in reference to Canadian prisons, argues that the legalisation of rights and the managerial conception of rights as risk mean that rights are increasingly hard to claim. In Scotland, Armstrong (Reference Armstrong2018) notes how the success of a legal challenge to a slopping-out regime in 2005 and subsequent (unrealized) fear of large compensation pay-outs led to the Scottish Prison Service being granted in excess of half a billion pounds in prison infrastructure investment, which would likely enable an increase in the prison population.

Furthermore, tendencies within rules-based prison regulation encourage surveillance and security processes being conducted on prisoners. In the commentary on Rule 54 of the European Prison Rules, the Council of Europe writes that “individual prisoners, particularly those subject to medium or maximum security restrictions, will also have to be personally searched on a regular basis to make sure that they are not carrying items which can be used in escape attempts, or to injure other people or themselves, or which are not allowed, such as illegal drugs.” This guide for managing prisons accepts and even promotes potentially invasive body searches “on a regular basis” based upon broad collective categorizations. The imprecise wording of SMRs also works to justify breaches in, for example, the name of security. For example, Rule 1 of the Mandela Principles asserts,

All prisoners shall be treated with the respect due to their inherent dignity and value as human beings. No prisoner shall be subjected to, and all prisoners shall be protected from, torture and other cruel, inhuman or degrading treatment or punishment, for which no circumstances whatsoever may be invoked as a justification. The safety and security of prisoners, staff, service providers and visitors shall be ensured at all times.

As Armstrong (Reference Armstrong2018) notes, while purporting to be a blanket rule against degrading treatment, this rule reincorporates the language of safety and security as a justification for prison conditions that may interfere with a prelegal sense of human dignity. The result is a system in which degrading treatment—strip searching, isolation, etc.—can come to be understood as part of a rights-respecting practice or even one operating within a rubric of care (See Kemp Reference Kemp2019).

More widely, human rights discourse risks reshaping fundamental penal logics as part of human rights practice. The history of poorly remunerated work and training programs in prisons—which in many places were the prison’s economic objective—is reconceived as something for the benefit of prisoners themselves (Browne Reference Browne2007; Mantouvalou Reference Mantouvalou2021). Human rights can even serve as justification for imprisonment itself by presenting crime as a human rights violation for which imprisonment is the cure (Karamalidou Reference Karamalidou2017). Nondiscrimination and equality laws in the Scottish prison system were applied equally to staff and prisoners—with no regard to the power differentials between them—meaning that prisoners complaining about their treatment might be held to have “breached rights to respect and dignity of staff if they complain about their confinement conditions while uttering a race- or gender-based epithet” (Armstrong Reference Armstrong2018, 20).

Human rights law may even allow the imposition of degrading treatment for prison management reasons. The weak protection of degrading treatment in prisons is not limited to soft-law human rights mechanisms. Where rules are found in legally enforceable human rights standards—for example, as part of the prohibition on torture—this can be considered a de jure defence against degrading treatment, obfuscating conditions which, in any other setting, would be seen to be “degrading treatment.” These mechanisms purporting to protect against degrading treatment in fact require evidence of improper intent to find breaches of Article 3. In A v UK (2009), the court found that “in order for a punishment or treatment associated with it to be ‘inhuman’ or ‘degrading’, the suffering or humiliation involved must go beyond that inevitable element of suffering or humiliation connected with a given form of legitimate treatment or punishment.” In deciding whether prison conditions contravene Article 3, the court will look at the justificatory reasoning for the condition—in turn undermining Article 3’s status as an absolute right (See, for example, Ocalan v. Turkey in relation to solitary confinement, Yankov in relation to forced head shaving).Footnote 12

To summarize, it is problematic that increasing the rule-boundedness of prisons is seen as the primary tool of progress, not least because the effects of increasing human rights and rule-based regulation are far from clear. The making of rules is based on penological expertise that elevates state, academic, and prison management discourses above more critical voices and those of prisoners. And, once in place, rules are difficult for those in prison to use to their advantage. The idea that the prisons, places that operate through the discretionary power of staff, can be subject to rule-based regulation that ameliorates the significant harms they produce is central to our claim of cruel optimism. This ontological understanding of the prison as definable by rules is also a part of the affective draw—comforting, hopeful—to the project. The next section offers a starting point for alternative prison ontologies which could better inform strategies to combat prison harms.

The Power-in-Practice Ontology of Prisons

The international prison-regulation project is based on a rule-centric ontology of prison. This ontological approach positions rules as the primary determinant of prison conditions and generates an imaginary of a benign, nondominating institution that upholds and conforms to rules (Carlen Reference Carlen2008). Thus, this approach conceals the ways that prisons are relational and constituted by power in practice: determined not only by statist legal regimes but also by social, cultural, and economic dynamics. Prison ethnographers Martin and Jefferson (Reference Martin and Jefferson2019, 138) sum this up: prison life is poorly represented in “the formal functions of the prison as established by law, implemented by organizational reform and assessed by universal standards.” In opposition, they argue that prisons are fundamentally relational: “defined by the contingent intersubjective relations among the people who populate these institutions, and not simply by the formal functions that prison actors fulfil or fail at” (2019, 137). In practice, imprisonment is shaped by context-specific imperatives of elite, colonial and capitalist control along with hierarchical orderings of gender, religion, and race (Stanley and Smith Reference Stanley and Smith2015). This section argues that these dynamics drive the imperative to imprison, the constitution of imprisonment and, currently, its rules-based regulation.

The rules-based prison-regulation project exists within a historical imaginary in which the modern prison system and efforts to reform it are both positioned as context-neutral legal instruments that replicate European advancements in criminal justice in other parts of the world. For Coyle (Reference Coyle2005, 3), the modern prison system “has its roots in the north-east of the United States and in Western Europe and has subsequently spread around the world, often in the wake of colonial expansion.” Prison reform has also always been a project with an international vision.Footnote 13 Indeed, the original motivation for the SMRs was the desire to spread the “enlightened’ British prison system around the world. For example, the 1929 Minimum Standards were driven by “British initiative and the propagandist activities of interested persons in Great Britain, following the revelation of distressing barbarities in the penal systems of a great many foreign countries” (Candler Reference Candler1930, 109). This echoes broader neocolonial development narratives which seek to correct the deficiencies of institutions in the Global South that were initially imposed on colonized countries with expertise from international NGOs. The SMRs are part of the colonial-development nexus, in which international institutions financed and largely influenced by wealthy colonial states exert influence over states in the Global South (Hearn Reference Hearn2007). As Whitfield (Reference Whitfield2018, 4) writes regarding the Latin American context, “examination of the uneven social distribution of punishment in post-colonial Latin America reveals the ways in which it reproduces colonial hierarchies, not least because the ability to punish effectively is also a sign of modernity and progress.” Indeed, Europe is singled out as particularly successful at institutionalizing regulation: van Zyl Smit (Reference van Zyl Smit2010, 509) writes that in Africa and the Americas “there are treaties and enforcement mechanisms that are similar to those in Europe, but they are apparently not as effective as their European counterparts.”

This view of prison reform obscures the ways that transplanting an institution into different contexts changes its purpose and character. Colonial prisons were built as modes of colonial domination and control, having different functions to prisons in the metropole in relation to discipline and class formation (Arnold Reference Arnold, Arnold and Hardiman1994; Branch Reference Branch2005). For example, prisons were systematically used in India from 1790 by the East India Company (Anderson, Reference Anderson2007). Their place in upholding British power is evidenced by the 1857 Indian uprisings against British rule, during which mutineers conducted 41 jail breaks, releasing over 23,000 prisoners (Anderson Reference Anderson2007). In contrast, British and European prisons emerged along with an expansion of all forms of punishment during a period in which the disciplining of a recently urbanized factory labor force was the main economic goal (Melossi and Pavarini Reference Melossi and Pavarini2018; Moore Reference Moore2019). Therefore, the prison has fulfilled diverse purposes that furthered the ends of the powerful. Prisons were used in colonial and metropolitan contexts to further context-specific ends rather than emerging, fully conceived, during the European Enlightenment and being reproduced under colonial rule (See Moore Reference Moore2014, Reference Moore2015).

Local differences in the drive to establish prisons coincide with differences in the power composition of established prisons. For example, Arnold (Reference Arnold, Arnold and Hardiman1994) found that contest and protest were significantly more visible in India’s colonial prisons than in Foucault’s (Reference Foucault and Sheridan1977) understanding of French prisons filled with docile, disciplined prisoner bodies. Regarding Israeli prisons holding Palestinians, Bornstein (Reference Bornstein2010, 462) highlights “struggles over what kind of agency is possible, who has power to act, and who must submit as obedient object.” Following rule-centric conceptualizations of imprisonment and its regulation obfuscates how prisons are shaped also by the actions, views, and resources of prisoners and communities around the prisons. Even in England and Wales, where prisons are typically understood in bureaucratic terms, emerging scholarship illustrates the influence of prisoner actions in determining regulatory changes through campaign, protest, and riot (Kemp Reference Kemp2022). Our contention is that these relational, power-in-practice features of prison ontology are critical to understanding the divergent ways that human rights are put into effect in prisons and orienting toward alternative routes toward challenging prison harms.

The connections between the social function of prisons and their relational constitution are seen across contemporary systems. The overrepresentation of marginalized groups—shaped through relations of indigeneity, religion, class, race, sexuality, and disability—is a common feature of all prison regimes (Ben-Moshe and Magaña Reference Ben-Moshe and Magaña2014). Moreover, the technology of detention is adapted to new political imperatives over time. In the UK in the 2000s, the increase in the use of immigration detention, followed by the establishment of specific prisons for foreign national offenders, coincided with increased suspicion of Muslim communities and in the politicization of migration. Between 2002 and 2015, UK imprisonment rose 20%, whereas the Muslim prisoner population rose more than doubled from 5,502 to 12,225 (Shaw, Reference Shaw2015). Again, the changing purpose of imprisonment shifted the constitution of these carceral institutions, generating different sorts of subjectivity, resistance, and changes in the likelihood of neglect, abuse, and poor conditions (Bosworth Reference Bosworth2011, Reference Bosworth2012).

In summary, the differences in purpose and make-up of prisons and the roles of power in practice in shaping the institutional lives of prisons are effaced by regulatory frameworks that prioritize rule application and managerial practice. Consequently, a primary effect of rules-based international prison regulation is to connect and subsume globally diverse carceral institutions under the same apparently benign, justificatory logic. As Piacentini and Katz (Reference Piacentini and Katz2017, 222) write, “it is through the diffusion of human rights law into international human rights obligations, trickling down to domestic laws, national prison service policies outlining fair and transparent decision-making, where legal links and obligations between penal systems are made.” The current naivety to power in practice means that regulation fails to displace social inequalities that prisons often entrench (see Razack Reference Razack2012) and, thus, is always incorporable into and risks enabling a new generation of punitive institutions by offering—for example, directions on how to build legitimized “human rights compliant” prisons.Footnote 14

BEYOND CRUEL OPTIMISM?

This article has critiqued the content and form of international prison regulation. Regarding content, we have illustrated how the SMRs misrepresent the nature of carceral harms, addressing imprisonment primarily as a rule-based institution, problematically obscuring the contested constitution and emergence of prisons. We have drawn on scholarship to argue that prisons are constituted primarily by relational sociopolitical power in practice and that prisons produce a range of harms beyond the immediate effect on individuals from unacceptable prison conditions. As a result, rules-based prison regulation is inherently assimilable into existing criminal justice systems. In so far as it is claimed to stem the tide of harm that prison systems create, rules-based prison regulation is an example of what Berlant calls cruel optimism—being a project that shores up rather than destabilizing the powerful imaginary of the prison as a rule bound entity. Consequently, scholars and the international community must move away from the problematic yet pervasive idea that “new knowledge, better rules and more professionalism” are all that is needed to respond to the failures of prisons (Jefferson Reference Jefferson2022, 2).

Pessimistic readings of the benefits of rules-based prison regulation are not new. Proponents of rules usually reply that these readings play into the hands of punitive policy makers because if it is thought that nothing can be done to improve prisons, then they need not try to make conditions better (Sparks and Bottoms Reference Sparks and Anthony1995). Furthermore, advocates of the current regulatory approach also suggest that although everyone knows that prisoner numbers are important, in the absence of success in limiting numbers and a collapse in the global system of imprisonment, something needs to be done about prison conditions. As noted in the introduction, there is a reading of cruel optimism that instills a nobility to the “compulsion to repeat” the optimistic act, which risks again and again having to survive disappointment in in pursuit of success (Meer Reference Meer2022, 4). In this section, we contest this pessimistic reading by suggesting useful positions that international prison reform and monitoring communities could adopt. We contend that the harms of prisons globally can be tackled in ways that do not further enable mass incarceration, without purporting to provide a step-by-step guide toward fixing the prison system.

Our argument highlights the need to engage with the political-economic nature of imprisonment rather than pursuing strategies that are blind to prisons’ roles in social structures of control and dispossession. Doing this means learning from and bolstering the power of communities targeted by imprisonment to challenge imprisonment, prevent harms, and resolve conflicts outside the criminal justice system. It means going beyond the bureaucratic state as the object and subject of strategy. It opens possibilities for realizing the ways that prisoners, communities, activists, and NGOs can influence the power in practice within the prison by witnessing, amplifying, and creating communities of opposition within and across the prison walls (Kemp, Reference Kemp2019, Reference Kemp2022; Tomczak, Reference Tomczak2021). Consistently, it is local mutual aid groups that sound the alarm over failings because they are responsive to the needs of prisoners (Spade Reference Spade2020). Funding, amplifying, and supporting—for example, prisoner unions and prisoner-led mutual aid groups—can be one way to do this, but care must be taken not to co-opt or direct them. However, this is undermined by the rules-based prison regulation-project, as the Mandela Rules and other instruments create their own materiality and authority by creating domains of knowledge about which one has to display expertise to participate in policy discourse.

In so far as pushes for change focus on state reforms, international prison regulation must be founded on reductionist strategies. International prison rules should explicitly and consistently acknowledge and exemplify the inherent harms of imprisonment and have the reduction in imprisonment rates as their explicit goal. Without doing so, all rules will play into a well-worn reformist trap that provides justification for prison building and harmful, excessive means of control and punishment. The concept of nonreformist reforms is vital here. Kaba et al. (Reference Kaba, Berger and Stein2017) define nonreformist reforms as “measures that reduce the power of an oppressive system while illuminating the system’s inability to solve the crises it creates” (see also Mathiesen Reference Mathiesen2014). In arguing that nonreformist reforms could form a basis for international prison oversight bodies, Lamble (Reference Lamble2022, 1) writes, “[a] key question to consider is not only whether a proposed reform will reduce harm and suffering, but whether it simultaneously works to reduce the size, scope, and power of the system?” Examples of nonreformist reforms include advocating a moratorium on prison building; responding to overcrowding through releasing certain categories of prisoners; and repealing laws that target oppressed groups such as those that criminalize drugs, sex work, immigration, protest, and property offences. Refocusing on nonreformist reforms will require making tough decisions not to work in collaboration with reform programs that involve building new prisons. And in places where existing prisons are not fit for human habitation, it means insisting on developing strategies that respond to harms and conflicts using nonpunitive methods (GenerationFIVE 2017).

Implementing these changes requires a shift in how we conceptualize penal regulation. Despite holding radical potential, regulation efforts tend to locate forms of monitoring which seek to stabilize systems and make them persist. Thus, international prison regulation often proposes monitoring systems that coexist with the systems they regulate, rather than working to fundamentally change them. Resisting tendencies to simply (re)design regulatory systems, we should think of how regulatory interventions could destabilize problematic systems—exposing their failures while reducing their scope. Simultaneously, these regulatory interventions must adopt a system-centric as opposed to institution-centric model of analysis and evaluation. Carving up criminal justice institutions has the effect of narrowing responsibility, curtailing accountability, and allowing people to fall through gaps (Borakove et al. Reference Borakove, Wosje, Cruz, Wickman, Dibble and Harbus2015). This requires focusing on systemic failures in outcomes—for example, in safety, equality, and survival—as well as failures to attain standards for individual institutions.

This discussion should not be taken to criticize uses of prisoners’ human rights to discursively challenge the legitimacy of incarceration (Simon Reference Simon2019). Using the rhetorical power of rights and their associated depoliticized, neutral, and fact-finding face to persuade the public and prison officials to change may be a necessary starting point for such interventions. However, to counter uses of human rights that are complicit in upholding existing systems that advance dispossession, advocates need to rethink human rights, beyond their ossification in institutionalized, state-centric forms (Goodale Reference Goodale2022). Ultimately, allowing human rights to justify the building of additional prisons that will widen the use of incarceration is self-defeating.

CONCLUSION

The article has critiqued the international rule-based prison-regulation project, which proposes that adherence to incrementally improving networks of rules is the optimal means of limiting the harmful effects of prisons. This project has had some positive effects on conditions faced by prisoners and itemizes some of the ways prisons routinely fail to meet standards. However, we have argued that the Mandela Rules and international prison regulation efforts based on them currently adopt a reductive conception of carceral harms and a flawed ontology of the prison. We have argued for a transcarceral approach to prison harms, illustrating that prisons have geographic and temporal reach; are linked to other carceral institutions; produce collective harms on families and communities of prisoners; and have adverse structural, social, and economic consequences for particular social groups. Furthermore, we have illustrated an ontology that conceptualizes the prison as constituted by power in practice. Understanding the prison as a political technology that is shaped by the local socioeconomic functions it serves is critical to understanding and developing means to challenge prison expansion. Without this, the project of rules-based international prison regulation constitutes cruel optimism.

What, then, are the consequences of understanding prison reform as a cruel optimism? Taking Berlant’s cue, the international penal reform community needs to build objects that can facilitate rather than undermining flourishing, democratic, nonpunitive societies. Along the way, we need to unlearn the ways of seeing and responding to the world that play into regulatory efforts coinciding with global prison expansion. In particular, our analysis suggests that unlearning the moves that isolate prison conditions as a humanitarian issue from the recognition that imprisonment is a political and economic technology is a central starting point. We have suggested redirecting resources to bolster groups challenging imprisonment and ensuring efforts are founded on the concept of nonreformist reforms to facilitate a reductionist trajectory.

In international reform discourse, Mandela’s remark that “no one truly knows a nation until one has been inside its jails. A nation should not be judged by how it treats its highest citizens, but its lowest ones” is ubiquitous (For example, United Nations 2021, 1). It is frequently mobilized to highlight the humanitarian import of the project of reform and to emphasize that there is a continuity between Mandela’s struggle against lawful racial violence and segregation, and the rules-based prison-regulation project. To the extent that Mandela’s decontextualized remark takes us away from thinking about the scale and scope of prison power and its role in embedding structural injustices and leads us to imagine an abstract individual prisoner in a generic jail, our analysis suggests that it may be an unhelpful starting point for thinking about reducing the harms of imprisonment. During Mandela’s imprisonment, the South African apartheid state offered him release on the condition that he publicly renounced the violence of the antiapartheid movement. In response, he said, “Only free men can negotiate; prisoners cannot enter into contracts” (The Guardian, 2013). This quotation, drawing attention to the inherently repressive power relations that sustain carceral spaces and the side-lining of prisoners and their communities from organized reform efforts would be a better starting point for understanding what prisons do and how to respond to their harms.

Acknowledgments

The authors would like to thank the anonymous reviewers for their helpful and generative feedback. No new data were created during this study. This research was funded by the UKRI under the project “Prison Regulation, for Safer Societies: Participatory, Effective, Efficient?”

CONFLICTS OF INTEREST

None.

Footnotes

He has published an article on detention visiting and hospitality in Theoretical Criminology and has an article in Social Movement Studies on prefigurative politics, postrepresentational politics, and immigration detention activism. Tom is a Research Fellow on the UKRI funded “Prison Regulation for Safer Societies: Participatory, Effective, Efficient?”

Kemp T. “Prefiguration and the Postrepresentational Politics of Antideportation Activism.” (2022). Social Movement Studies 1.

Kemp T. “Solidarity in Spaces of ‘Care and Custody’: The Hospitality Politics of Immigration Detention Visiting.” (2019). Theoretical Criminology.

This work was supported by her funding from UK Research and Innovation [grant number MR/T019085/1]; the Economic and Social Research Council under the University of Nottingham Impact Accelerator Award and Nottingham Impact Accelerator Knowledge Exchange Prize; and SPF-QR funding awarded to the University of Nottingham by Research England (2021). Directly related to this manuscript, she has published:

TOMCZAK, P. 2022. “Highlighting ‘Risky Remands’ through Prisoner Death Investigations: People with Very Severe Mental Illness Transitioning from Police and Court Custody into Prison on Remand.” Frontiers in Psychiatry: Forensic Psychiatry.

TOMCZAK, P., and COOK, C. 2022. “Bereaved Family ‘Involvement’ in (Prisoner) Death Investigations: Whose ‘Satisfaction’?” Social and Legal Studies.

BANWELL-MOORE, R. et al., 2022. “‘The Human Toll’: Highlighting the Unacknowledged Harms of Prison Suicide Which Radiate across Stakeholder Groups. Incarceration: An International Journal of Imprisonment, Detention and Coercive Confinement.

TOMCZAK, P. 2021. “Reconceptualizing Multisectoral Prison Regulation: Voluntary Organisations and Bereaved Families as Regulators.” Theoretical Criminology.

TOMCZAK, P., and MCALLISTER, S, 2021. Prisoner Death Investigations: A Means for Improving Safety in Prisons and Societies? Journal of Social Welfare and Family Law 43, no. 2: 212–30

TOMCZAK, P., 2018. Prison Suicide: What Happens Afterwards? University of Bristol Press.

University of Nottingham, Nottingham, NG7 2RD, United Kingdom

1. Such as the Kampala Declaration on Prison Conditions in Africa and Plan of Action (1996), Robin Island Guidelines (2002), the Ouagadougou Declaration and Plan of Action on Accelerating Prisons and Penal Reform in Africa (2002).

2. Corporation of the Canadian Civil Liberties Association v. Her Majesty the Queen, (2017) ONSC 7491, 43 CR (7th) 153; British Columbia Civil Liberties Association v. Canada (Attorney General), (2018) BCSC 62, 43 CR (7th) 1.

3. See Eggs v. Switzerland, application no. 7341/76, October 19, 1979; X v. Germany, application no. 235/56, June 10, 1958.

4. In areas of prison conditions “Strasbourg has done little more than legitimate the existing practice of most States” (Livingstone Reference Livingstone2000).

5. ECHR 279 (2001); Peers v. Greece, application no. 28524/95, April 19, 2001.

6. ECHR 392 Karpenko v. Ukraine, application no. 45397/13, December 16, 2021.

7. For example, see Suleimenov vs. Kazakhstan (CCPR/C/119/D/2146/2012); Barkovsky vs. Belarus (CCPR/C/123/D/2247/2013) on the Human Rights Committee’s use of the SMRs in finding breaches of article 10 and article 7 of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights.

8. These reports point to the limits of the definition of solitary confinement which seem to rule that cell confinement with another prisoner does not count as a harmful form of practice.

12. Ocalan v Turkey, application no. 46221/99, May 12, 2005; Yankov v Bulgaria, application no. 39084/97, December 11, 2003. Similarly, Mavronicola (Reference Mavronicola2015, 135–366) writes, “Attributing the adjective ‘inhuman’ or ‘degrading’ to punishment or treatment associated with it is dependent on a complex assessment to which the crime committed by the individual or the particular risk of harm he or she poses at a given time to self or others may be relevant. This is in line with human dignity, which requires a minimum level of respect for our mutual humanity, including as regards our exercise of agency. Punishment which ‘matches’ the offence committed by the individual can be viewed as respectful of the individual’s dignity in reflecting an appropriate response to conceptions of individual responsibility, and the limits of individual autonomy embodied in the criminal law and criminal justice system more broadly.”

13. Early prison reformers Jonas Hanway, John Howard travelled across Europe in the late 1790s. Allexis de Tocqueville was sent by the French to US to gather information on prison management in 1830s. Elizabeth Fry produced reports on Danish prisons to the Danish royal family that changed how Danish prisons were run. Latter day reforming British prison commissioner, Alexander Paterson, traveled widely including notable trips to colonial Burma to inspect prisons (Brown Reference Brown2007).

References

REFERENCES

Abbott, Andrew. 2016. Processual Sociology, illustrated edition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, Clare. 2007. Indian Uprising of 1857-8: Prisons, Prisoners and Rebellion. London: Anthem Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aon, Maha, My Warborg Larson, Marie, and Brasholt, Marie. 2018. “Suicide & Self-Harm in Prisons.” Dignity Danish Institute Against Torture. https://www.dignity.dk/wp-content/uploads/publication_series_no23.pdf.Google Scholar
Armstrong, Sarah. 2018. “Securing Prison through Human Rights: Unanticipated Implications of Rights-Based Penal Governance.” The Howard Journal of Crime and Justice 57, no. 3: 401–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arnold, David. 1994. “The Colonial Prison: Power, Knowledge and Penology in Nineteenth-Century India.” In Subaltern Studies VIII: Essays in Honour of Ranajit Guha, edited by Arnold, David and Hardiman, David, 148–84. New Delhi: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Banwell-Moore, Rebecca, Tomczak, Philippa, Wainwright, Lucy, Traynor, Catherine, and Hyde, Sara. 2022. “‘The Human Toll’: Highlighting the Unacknowledged Harms of Prison Suicide Which Radiate across Stakeholder Groups.” Incarceration 3, no. 2: 120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ben-Moshe, Liat. 2022. “Refuting Carceral Logics and Their Alternatives.” In Disability Injustice: Confronting Criminalization in Canada, edited by Fritsch, Kelly, Monaghan, Jeffrey, and van der Meulen, Emily, 304–29. Vancouver: UBC Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ben-Moshe, Liat, and Magaña, Sandy. 2014. “An Introduction to Race, Gender, and Disability: Intersectionality, Disability Studies, and Families of Color.” Women, Gender, and Families of Color 2, no. 2: 105–14.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berlant, Lauren Gail. 2011. Cruel Optimism. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
BiD (Bail for Immigration Detainees). 2013. “Detention under Immigration Powers in UK Prisons: Severe Restrictions on Access to Justice.” January 23, 2013. http://www.biduk.org/sites/default/files/2013-09-23%20BID%20Briefing%20Detainees%20in%20Prison%20%281%29.pdf.Google Scholar
Biondi, Karina, and Collins, John F.. 2016. Sharing This Walk: An Ethnography of Prison Life and the PCC in Brazil. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blagg, Harry, Tulich, Tamara, and Bush, Zoe. 2017. “Indefinite Detention Meets Colonial Dispossession: Indigenous Youths with Foetal Alcohol Spectrum Disorders in a White Settler Justice System.” Social & Legal Studies 26, no. 3: 333–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Borakove, M. Elaine, Wosje, Robin, Cruz, Franklin, Wickman, Aimee, Dibble, Tim, and Harbus, Carolyn. 2015. “From Silo to System: What Makes a Criminal Justice System Operate Like a System?” MacArthur Foundation, April 30, 2015. http://www.safetyandjusticechallenge.org/wp-content/uploads/2015/07/From-Silo-to-System-30-APR-2015_FINAL.pdf.Google Scholar
Bornstein, Avram. 2010. “Palestinian Prison Ontologies.” Dialectical Anthropology 34, no. 4: 459–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bosworth, Mary. 2011. “Deportation, Detention and Foreign-National Prisoners in England and Wales.” Citizenship Studies 15, no. 5: 583–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bosworth, Mary. 2012. “Subjectivity and Identity in Detention: Punishment and Society in a Global Age.” Theoretical Criminology 16, no. 2: 123–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Braithwaite, John, Coglianese, Cary, and Levi-Faur, David. 2007. “Can Regulation and Governance Make a Difference?’ Regulation & Governance 1, no. 1: 17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Branch, Daniel. 2005. “Imprisonment and Colonialism in Kenya, c.1930-1952: Escaping the Carceral Archipelago.” The International Journal of African Historical Studies 38, no. 2: 239–65.Google Scholar
Brown, Adrienne Maree. 2021. We Will Not Cancel Us: And Other Dreams of Transformative Justice. Chico, CA: AK Press.Google Scholar
Brown, Ian. 2007. “A Commissioner Calls: Alexander Paterson and Colonial Burma’s Prisons.” Journal of Southeast Asian Studies 38, no. 2: 293308.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Browne, Jaron. 2007. “Rooted in Slavery: Prison Labor Exploitation.” Race, Poverty & the Environment 14, no. 1: 4244.Google Scholar
Bulman, May. 2019. “Prisoners Disposing of Human Waste via Cell Windows Due to ‘Degrading’ Sanitation System, Finds Report.” The Independent, September 26, 2019. https://www.independent.co.uk/news/uk/home-news/prisoners-forced-to-dispose-of-human-waste-via-cell-windows-finds-report-a9120176.html.Google Scholar
Candler, Marjorie O. 1930. “The International Charter for Prisoners.” Transactions of the Grotius Society 16:107–18.Google Scholar
Carlen, Pat, ed. 2008. Imaginary Penalties. Portland, OR: Willan Publishing.Google Scholar
Carlton, Bree. 2016. “Penal Reform, Anti-Carceral Feminist Campaigns and the Politics of Change in Women’s Prisons, Victoria, Australia.” Punishment & Society 20, no. 3: 283307.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carlton, Bree, and Segrave, Marie. 2011. “Women’s Survival Post-Imprisonment: Connecting Imprisonment with Pains Past and Present.” Punishment & Society 13, no. 5: 551–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carver, Richard, and Handley, Lisa. 2020. “Evaluating National Preventive Mechanisms: A Conceptual Model.” Journal of Human Rights Practice 12, no. 2: 387408.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Casciani, Dominic. 2010. “Inmates ‘Slopping Out’ 14 Years after Ban.” BBC News, October 27, 2010. https://www.bbc.co.uk/news/uk-11630152.Google Scholar
Chamberlen, Anastasia. 2016. “Embodying Prison Pain: Women’s Experiences of Self-Injury in Prison and the Emotions of Punishment.” Theoretical Criminology 20, no. 2: 205–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cid, José. 2009. “Is Imprisonment Criminogenic? A Comparative Study of Recidivism Rates between Prison and Suspended Prison Sanctions.” European Journal of Criminology 6, no. 6: 459–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clear, Todd R., Rose, Dina R., and Ryder, Judith A.. 2001. “Incarceration and the Community: The Problem of Removing and Returning Offenders.” Crime & Delinquency 47, no. 3: 335–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cliquennois, Gaëtan, and Champetier, Brice. 2016. “The Economic, Judicial and Political Influence Exerted by Private Foundations on Cases Taken by NGOs to the European Court of Human Rights: Inklings of a New Cold War?European Law Journal 22, no. 1: 92126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, Stanley. 1985. Visions of Social Control: Crime, Punishment, and Classification. New York: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Council of Europe. 2022. “Anti-Torture Committee Calls for Setting a Limit to the Number of Inmates in Every Prison and Promoting Non-Custodial Measures.” April 24, 2022. https://www.coe.int/en/web/cpt/-/anti-torture-committee-calls-for-setting-a-limit-to-the-number-of-inmates-in-every-prison-and-promoting-non-custodial-measures?s=08.Google Scholar
Coyle, Andrew. 2003. “A Human Rights Approach to Prison Management.” Criminal Behaviour and Mental Health 13, no. 2: 7780.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Coyle, Andrew. 2005. Understanding Prisons: Key Issues in Policy and Practice. Maidenhead: Open University Press.Google Scholar
Crewe, Ben, Liebling, Alison, and Hulley, Susie. 2015. “Staff-Prisoner Relationships, Staff Professionalism, and the Use of Authority in Public- and Private-Sector Prisons.” Law & Social Inquiry 40, no. 2: 309–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darke, Sacha. 2018. Conviviality and Survival. Cham: Palgrave MacMillian.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Day, Anne-Marie, Bateman, Tim, and Pitts, John. 2020. “Surviving Incarceration: The Pathways of Looked after and Non-Looked after Children into, through and out of Custody.” (working paper, University of Bedfordshire). https://uobrep.openrepository.com/bitstream/handle/10547/623926/Survivingincarcerationfinal.pdf?sequence=3&isAllowed=y.Google Scholar
Denzin, Norman and Lincoln, Yvonna (eds). 2018. The Sage Handbook of Qualitative Research. Los Angeles: Sage.Google Scholar
Drake, Deborah. 2018. “Prisons and State Building: Promoting ‘The Fiasco of the Prison’ in a Global Context.” International Journal for Crime, Justice and Social Democracy 7, no. 4: 115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ellis, Rachel. 2021. “Prisons as Porous Institutions.” Theory and Society 50, no. 2: 175–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fazel, Seena, Ramesh, Taanvi, and Hawton, Keith. 2017. “Suicide in Prisons: An International Study of Prevalence and Contributory Factors.” The Lancet Psychiatry 4, no. 12: 946–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feeley, Malcolm M. 2001. “Three Voices of Socio-Legal Studies Social Science in the Law: Theoretical Issues and Methodological Problems.” Israel Law Review 35, no. 2: 175204.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foucault, Michel. 1977. Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison, translated by Sheridan, Alan. London: Penguin.Google Scholar
Gaes, Gerald G., and Camp, Scott D.. 2009. “Unintended Consequences: Experimental Evidence for the Criminogenic Effect of Prison Security Level Placement on Post-Release Recidivism.” Journal of Experimental Criminology 5, no. 2: 139–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
George, Lily, Norris, Adele N., Deckert, Antje, and Tauri, Juan, editors. 2020. Neo-Colonial Injustice and the Mass Imprisonment of Indigenous Women. Cham: Springer International Publishing.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodale, Mark. 2022. Reinventing Human Rights. Redwood City, CA: Stanford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gould, Jon B., and Barclay, Scott. 2012. “Mind the Gap: The Place of Gap Studies in Sociolegal Scholarship.” Annual Review of Law and Social Science 8, no. 1: 323–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greenberg, Greg A., and Rosenheck, Robert A.. 2008. “Homelessness in the State and Federal Prison Population.” Criminal Behaviour and Mental Health 18, no. 2: 88103.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gronowska, Bożena. 2017. “Inter-American Prison Rules: Creating a Normal Life Behind Bars.” Comparative Law Review 21:3152. https://www.theguardian.com/world/2013/dec/06/nelson-mandela-life-quotes.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hailing, Li. 2019. “The Mandela Rules: New Standards for the Human Rights of Prisoners.” Advances in Sciences and Humanities 4, no. 6: 7784.Google Scholar
Hannah-Moffat, K. 2004. “Losing Ground: Gendered Knowledges, Parole Risk, and Responsibility.” Social Politics: International Studies in Gender, State & Society 11, no. 3: 363–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hathazy, Paul. 2016. “Remaking the Prisons of the Market Democracies: New Experts, Old Guards and Politics in the Carceral Fields of Argentina and Chile.” Crime, Law and Social Change 65, no. 3: 163–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hearn, Julie. 2007. “African NGOs: The New Compradors?Development and Change 38, no. 6: 10951110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
HMIP (HM Inspectorate of Prisons). 2017. “Life in Prison: Living Conditions.” October 4, 2017. https://www.justiceinspectorates.gov.uk/hmiprisons/wp-content/uploads/sites/4/2017/10/Findings-paper-Living-conditions-FINAL-.pdf.Google Scholar
Holzer, Harry J. 2009. “Collateral Costs: Effects of Incarceration on Employment and Earnings among Young Workers.” In Do Prisons Make Us Safer, edited by Raphael, Steven and Stoll, Michael, 239–66. New York: Russell Sage Foundation.Google Scholar
Hughett, Amanda Bell. 2019. “A ‘Safe Outlet’ for Prisoner Discontent: How Prison Grievance Procedures Helped Stymie Prison Organizing During the 1970s.” Law & Social Inquiry 44, no. 4: 893921.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jaakkola, Elina. 2020. “Designing Conceptual Articles: Four Approaches.” AMS Review 10, no. 1: 1826.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jefferson, Andrew M. 2022. “Prison Reform and Torture Prevention under ‘Compromised Circumstances.’” Criminology & Criminal Justice, online first edition.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaba, Mariam, Berger, Dan, and Stein, David. 2017. “What Abolitionists Do.” Jacobin, August 24, 2017. https://jacobin.com/2017/08/prison-abolition-reform-mass-incarceration.Google Scholar
Karamalidou, Anastasia. 2017. Embedding Human Rights in Prison. London: Palgrave Macmillan UK.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keenan, Sarah. 2019. “A Prison around Your Ankle and a Border in Every Street: Theorising Law, Space and the Subject.” In Routledge Handbook of Law and Theory, edited by Philippopoulos-Mihalopoulos, Andreas, 7190. Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar
Kemp, Tom. 2019. “Solidarity in Spaces of ‘Care and Custody’: The Hospitality Politics of Immigration Detention Visiting.” Theoretical Criminology 25, no. 2: 249–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kemp, Tom. 2022. “Prefiguration and the post-representational politics of anti-deportation activism.” Social Movement Studies, online first edition.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kessel, Alisa. 2020. “The Cruel Optimism of Sexual Consent.” Contemporary Political Theory 19, no. 3: 359–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kincaid, Sarah, Roberts, Manon, and Kane, Eddie. 2019. Children of Prisoners: Fixing a Broken System. Crest, February 2019. https://www.nicco.org.uk/userfiles/downloads/5c90a6395f6d8-children-of-prisoners-full-report-web-version.pdf.Google Scholar
Kraiem, Rubin. 1978. “Prisoners’ Rights and the Standard Minimum Rules for the Treatment of Offenders.” International Journal of Offender Therapy and Comparative Criminology 22, no. 2: 156–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lamble, Sarah. 2022. “Bridging the Gap between Reformists and Abolitionists: Can Non-Reformist Reforms Guide the Work of Prison Inspectorates?” World Prison Brief. https://www.prisonstudies.org/news/bridging-gap-between-reformists-and-abolitionists-can-non-reformist-reforms-guide-work-prison-0.Google Scholar
Lappi-Seppälä, Tapio, and Koskenniemi, Lauri. 2018. “National and Regional Instruments in Securing the Rule of Law and Human Rights in the Nordic Prisons.” Crime, Law and Social Change 70, no. 1: 135–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lazar, Orlando. 2019. “A Republic of Rules: Procedural Arbitrariness and Total Institutions.” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 22, no. 6: 681702.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leonard, Sarah-Jayne, Sanders, Caroline, and Shaw, Jennifer J.. 2021. “Managing Returns to Prison from Medium-Secure Services: Qualitative Study.” BJPsych Open 7, no. 4: 111.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Liebling, Alison. 2007. “Prison Suicide and Its Prevention.” In Handbook on Prisons, edited by Jewkes, Yvonne, Crewe, Ben and Bennett, Jamie, 423–46. Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar
Liu, Yiran E., Everton Ferreira Lemos, Crhistinne Cavalheiro Maymone Gonçalves, de Oliveira, Roberto, Andrea da Silva Santos, Agne Oliveira do Prado Morais, Mariana Garcia Croda, et al. 2021. “All-Cause and Cause-Specific Mortality during and Following Incarceration in Brazil: A Retrospective Cohort Study.” PLOS Medicine 18, no. 9: 120.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Livingstone, Stephen. 2000. “Prisoners’ Rights in the Context of the European Convention on Human Rights.” Punishment & Society 2, no. 3: 309–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lovett, Frank. 2012. A General Theory of Domination and Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Madoc-Jones, Iolo, Caroline Hughes, Caro Gorden, Sarah Dubberley, Karen Washington-Dyer, Ahmed, Anya, Lockwood, Kelly, and Wilding, Mark. 2018. “Rethinking Preventing Homelessness amongst Prison Leavers.” European Journal of Probation 10, no. 3: 215–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mallett, Christopher A. 2016. “The School-to-Prison Pipeline: A Critical Review of the Punitive Paradigm Shift.” Child and Adolescent Social Work Journal 33, no. 1: 1524.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mantouvalou, Virginia. 2021. “Working Prisoners Are Trapped in State-Mediated Structures of Exploitation: Using Them Only to Fill Brexit Labour Shortages Is a Bad Idea.” London School of Economics and Political Science (blog). British Politics and Policy at LSE, September 27, 2021. https://blogs.lse.ac.uk/politicsandpolicy/prisoners-labour-shortages/.Google Scholar
Martin, Tomas Max. 2014. “Reasonable Caning and the Embrace of Human Rights in Ugandan Prisons.” Focaal 2014, no. 68: 6882.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, Tomas Max. 2017. “Scrutinizing the Embrace of Human Rights in Ugandan Prisons: An Ethnographic Analysis of the Equivocal Responses to Human Rights Watch Reporting.” Journal of Human Rights Practice 9, no. 2: 247–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, Tomas Max, and Jefferson, Andrew M.. 2019. “Prison Ethnography in Africa: Reflections on a Maturing Field.” Politique Africaine 155, no. 3: 131152.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mathiesen, Thomas. 2014. The Politics of Abolition Revisited. Abingdon: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mavronicola, Natasa. 2015. “Crime, Punishment and Article 3 ECHR: Puzzles and Prospects of Applying an Absolute Right in a Penal Context.” Human Rights Law Review, 15, no. 4: 721–43.Google Scholar
Medical Justice. 2015. “‘A Secret Punishment’: The Misuse of Segregation in Immigration Detention.” October 2015. https://medicaljustice.org.uk/wp-content/uploads/2022/02/2015_A-Secret-Punishment_Final.pdf.Google Scholar
Medical Justice and Bail for Immigration Detainees. 2021. “‘Every Day Is like Torture’: Solitary Confinement & Immigration Detention.” Medical Justice, February 2021 https://medicaljustice.org.uk/wp-content/uploads/2022/02/2021_SolitaryConfinement_Final.pdf.Google Scholar
Meer, Nasar. 2022. The Cruel Optimism of Racial Justice. Bristol: Policy Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Melossi, Dario, and Pavarini, Massimo. 2018. The Prison and the Factory. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Méndez, Juan E. 2013. Interim Report of the Special Rapporteur on Torture and Other Cruel, Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or Punishment (a/68/295). United Nations Office on Drugs and Crime, October 7, 2013. UNODC/CCPCJ/EG.6/2013/INF/2. https://www.unodc.org/documents/justice-and-prison-reform/SPECIAL_RAPPORTEUR_EN.pdf.Google ScholarPubMed
Moore, John. M. 2015. “The “New Punitiveness in the Context of British Imperial History.” Criminal Justice Matters 101, no. 1: 1013.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moore, John M. 2014. “Is the Empire Coming Home?’ Papers from the British Criminology Conference 14:3148.Google Scholar
Moore, John M. 2019. “Expansion, Crisis, and Transformation: Changing Economies of Punishment in England, 1780–1850. Social Justice 46, no. 4: 530.Google Scholar
Moran, Dominique. 2014. “Leaving behind the ‘Total Institution’? Teeth, Transcarceral Spaces and (Re)Inscription of the Formerly Incarcerated Body.” Gender, Place & Culture 21, no. 1: 3551.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morthorst, Britt Reuter, Mehlum, Lars, Pàlsson, Sigurdur P., Mühlmann, Charlotte, Hammerlin, Yngve, Madsen, Trine, Nordentoft, Merete, and Erlangsen, Annette. 2021. “Suicide Rates in Nordic Prisons 2000–2016.” Archives of Suicide Research 25, no. 3: 704–14.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Murray, Joseph. 2005. “The Effects of Imprisonment on Families and Children of Prisoners.” In The Effects of Imprisonment, edited by Liebling, Alison and Maruna, Shadd, 442–64. Cullompton, UK: Willan Publishing.Google ScholarPubMed
O’Connell, Ciara, and Rogan, Mary. 2022. “Monitoring Prisons in Europe: Understanding Perspectives of People in Prison and Prison Staff.” Law & Social Inquiry, 48, no. 1: 205–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Office for Democratic Institutions and Human Rights and Penal Reform International. 2018. “Guidance Document on The Nelson Mandela Rules: Implementing the United Nations Revised Standard Minimum Rules for the Treatment of Prisoners.” Penal Reform International, July 2018. https://cdn.penalreform.org/wp-content/uploads/2018/07/MR_Guidance_Doc.pdf.Google Scholar
OHCHR (Office of the United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights). 2019. “Human Rights in the Administration of Justice.” Human Rights Council, July 30, 2019. https://documents-dds-ny.un.org/doc/UNDOC/GEN/G19/247/98/PDF/G1924798.pdf.Google Scholar
OHCHR (Office of the United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights). 2021. “United Kingdom: UN expert raises alarm over abuse of Close Supervision Centres.” https://www.ohchr.org/en/press-releases/2021/05/united-kingdom-un-expert-raises-alarm-over-abuse-close-supervision-centres.Google Scholar
Owers, Anne. 2007. “Imprisonment in the Twenty-First Century: A View from the Inspectorate.” In Handbook on Prisons, edited by Jewkes, Yvonne, 122. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Padfield, Nicola. 2018. “Monitoring Prisons in England and Wales: Who Ensures the Fair Treatment of Prisoners?Crime, Law and Social Change 70, no. 1: 5776.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Palacios, Lena. 2016. “Challenging Convictions: Indigenous and Black Race-Radical Feminists Theorizing the Carceral State and Abolitionist Praxis in the United States and Canada.” Meridians 15, no. 1: 137–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peirce, Jennifer. 2018. “Making the Mandela Rules: Evidence, Expertise, and Politics in the Development of Soft Law International Prison Standards.” Queen’s Law Journal 43, no. 2: 263–96Google Scholar
Peirce, Jennifer. 2021. “‘It Was Supposed to Be Fair Here’: Human Rights and Recourse Mechanisms in the Dominican Republic’s Prison Reform Process.” Journal of Human Rights 21, no. 1: 119.Google Scholar
Pemberton, Sarah. 2013. “Enforcing Gender: The Constitution of Sex and Gender in Prison Regimes.” Signs 39, no. 1: 151–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Penal Reform International. 2021. Annual Report 2020. December 2021. https://cdn.penalreform.org/wp-content/uploads/2021/12/PRI-Annual-Report-2020-FINAL.pdf.Google Scholar
Penal Reform International. 2022. Global Prison Trends 2022. May 2022. https://cdn.penalreform.org/wp-content/uploads/2022/05/GPT2022.pdf.Google Scholar
Penal Reform International Website. 2023. “Homepage.” https://www.penalreform.org/.Google Scholar
Piacentini, Laura, and Katz, Elena. 2017. “Carceral Framing of Human Rights in Russian Prisons.” Punishment & Society 19, no. 2: 221–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prais, Victoria. 2020. “The Implementation in Canada of the UN Standard Minimum Rules for the Treatment of Prisoners: A Practitioner’s Perspective.” Journal of Human Rights Practice 12, no. 3: 730–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ray, Victor. 2023. “Pessimism of the Intellect, Cruel Optimism of the Will.” Ethnic and Racial Studies 46, no. 13: 2917–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Razack, Sherene. 2012. “Memorializing Colonial Power: The Death of Frank Paul.” Law & Social Inquiry 37, no. 4: 908–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Razack, Sherene. 2015. Dying from Improvement: Inquests and Inquiries into Indigenous Deaths in Custody. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Reiter, Keramet, Sexton, Lori, and Sumner, Jennifer. 2018. “Theoretical and Empirical Limits of Scandinavian Exceptionalism: Isolation and Normalization in Danish Prisons.” Punishment & Society 20, no. 1: 92112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Renault, Emmanuel. 2016. “Critical Theory and Processual Social Ontology.” Journal of Social Ontology 2, no. 1: 1732.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robins, Jon. 2020. “Inmates at HMP Maidstone Not Received Any Contact since Lockdown.” The Justice Gap, July 6, 2020. https://www.thejusticegap.com/inmates-at-hmp-maidstone-not-received-any-contact-since-lockdown/.Google Scholar
Robinson, Imani. 2020. “Towards an Abolitionist Drug Policy Reform.” In The Impact of Global Drug Policy on Women: Shifting the Needle, edited by Buxton, Julia, Margo, Giavana, and Burger, Lona, 259–69. Bingley, UK: Emerald Publishing Limited.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rogan, Mary. 2017. “Human Rights and Correctional Health Policy: A View from Europe.” International Journal of Prisoner Health 13, no. 1: 39.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rogan, Mary. 2021. “Prison Inspection and Monitoring: The Need to Reform European Law and Policy.” European Journal on Criminal Policy and Research 27, no. 2: 285305.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sarkin, Jeremy. 2008. “Prisons in Africa: An Evaluation from a Human Rights Perspective.” Sur. Revista Internacional de Direitos Humanos 5:2251.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Seatzu, Francesco, and Fanni, Simona. 2015. “A Comparative Approach to Prisoners’ Rights in the European Court of Human Rights and Inter-American Court of Human Rights Jurisprudence.” Denver Journal of International Law and Policy 44, no. 1: 2140.Google Scholar
Shammas, Victor Lund. 2014. “The Pains of Freedom: Assessing the Ambiguity of Scandinavian Penal Exceptionalism on Norway’s Prison Island.” Punishment & Society 16, no. 1: 104–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shaw, Danny. 2015. “Why the Surge in Muslim Prisoners?” BBC News, March 11, 2015. https://www.bbc.co.uk/news/uk-31794599.Google Scholar
Siddique, Haroon. 2021 “Fifty-Two Prisoners in Close Supervision Units ‘That May Amount to Torture.’” The Guardian, July 26, 2021. https://www.theguardian.com/society/2021/jul/26/52-held-close-supervision-prison-units-may-amount-torture.Google Scholar
Simon, Jonathan. 2019. “For a Human Rights Approach to Reforming the American Penal State.” Journal of Human Rights Practice 11, no. 2: 346–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Peter Scharff. 2011. “A Critical Look at Scandinavian Exceptionalism.” In Penal Exceptionalism? Nordic Prison Policy and Practice, edited by Ugelvik, Thomas and Dullum, Jane, 3857. London: Taylor & Francis.Google Scholar
Spade, Dean. 2020. Mutual Aid: Building Solidarity During This Crisis (and the Next). New York: Verso Books.Google Scholar
Sparks, Richard, and Anthony, Bottoms. 1995. “Legitimacy and Order in Prisons.” The British Journal of Sociology 46, no. 1: 4562.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stanley, Elizabeth, and Mihaere, Riki. 2019. “The Problems and Promise of International Rights in the Challenge to Maori Imprisonment.” International Journal for Crime, Justice and Social Democracy 8, no. 1: 117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stanley, Eric A., and Smith, Nat. 2015. Captive Genders: Trans Embodiment and the Prison Industrial Complex. Chico, CA: AK Press.Google Scholar
Tabar, Omid Firouzi, Miravalle, Michele, and Torrente, Giovanni. 2016. “Reducing the Prison Population in Europe: Do Community Based Sentences Work?” European Prison Observatory. http://www.prisonobservatory.org/upload/EPO_2_WS1_Final_report.pdf.Google Scholar
Thailand Criminology and Corrections. (2016). “Implementation of the Nelson Mandela Rules in Thailand.” July 18, 2016. http://thaicriminology.com/implementation-of-the-nelson-mandela-rules-in-thailand.html.Google Scholar
The Guardian . 2013. “Nelson Mandela quotes: ‘Real Leaders Must Be Ready to Sacrifice All for the Freedom of Their People.’” December 6, 2013.Google Scholar
Tiroch, Katrin. 2016. “Modernizing the Standard Minimum Rules for the Treatment of Prisoners: A Human Rights Perspective.” Max Planck Yearbook of United Nations Law Online 19 (1): 278304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tomczak, Philippa. 2021. ‘Reconceptualizing Multisectoral Prison Regulation: Voluntary Organizations and Bereaved Families as Regulators.” Theoretical Criminology 26, no. 3: 494514.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
United Nations. 2021. “United Nations System Common Position on Incarceration.” UNODC, April 2021. https://www.unodc.org/res/justice-and-prison-reform/nelsonmandelarules-GoF/UN_System_Common_Position_on_Incarceration.pdf.Google Scholar
United Nations Secretariat. 1970. The Standard Minimum Rules for the Treatment of Prisoners in the Light of Recent Developments in the Correctional Field.” Fourth United Nations Congress on the Prevention of Crime and the Treatment of Offenders. August 26, 1970. http://fsu.digital.flvc.org/islandora/object/fsu%3A547447/datastream/OBJ/view/The_Standard_Minimum_Rules_for_the_Treatment_of_Prisoners_in_the_Light_of_Recent_Developments_in_the_Correctional_Field.pdf.Google Scholar
van Zyl Smit, Dirk. 2006. “Humanising Imprisonment: A European Project?’ European Journal on Criminal Policy and Research 12, no. 2: 107–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Zyl Smit, Dirk. 2010. “Regulation of Prison Conditions.” Crime and Justice 39, no. 1: 503–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smit, van Zyl, Dirk. 2019. “International Prison Standards and Transnational Criminal Justice.” UC Irvine Journal of International, Transnational, and Comparative Law 4, no. 1: 97–123.Google Scholar
Dirk, van Zyl Smit, and Snacken, Sonja. 2011. Principles of European Prison Law and Policy: Penology and Human Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wacquant, Loïc J. D. 2009. Punishing the Poor: The Neoliberal Government of Social Insecurity. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Walmsley, R. 1995. “The European Prison Rules in Central and Eastern Europe: Progress and Problems.” European Journal on Criminal Policy and Research 3, no. 4: 7390.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whitfield, Joey. 2018. Prison Writing of Latin America. New York: Bloomsbury Academic.Google Scholar
Whitty, Noel. 2011. “Human Rights as Risk: UK Prisons and the Management of Risk and Rights.” Punishment & Society 13, no. 2: 123–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wines, Enoch Cobb. 1873. Report on the International Penitentiary Congress of London Held July 3-13, 1872. Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office.Google Scholar
Wolffe, Nancy, Cynthia Blitz, Jing Shi, Bachman, Ronet, and Siegel, Jane. 2006. “Sexual Violence Inside Prisons: Rates of Victimization.” Journal of Urban Health 83, no. 5: 835–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Worrall, Anne. 2019. “The Other Prices of Privatised Justice: Marketing Prison Alternatives.” In Justice Alternatives, edited by Carlen, Pat and França, Leandro Ayres, 290305. Abingdon: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zhong, Shaoling, Morwenna Senior, Rongqin Yu, Amanda Perry, Keith Hawton, Shaw, Jenny, and Fazel, Seena. 2021. “Risk Factors for Suicide in Prisons: A Systematic Review and Meta-Analysis.” The Lancet Public Health 6, no. 3: e16474.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed