Skip to main content
Log in

On the roles of anaphoricity and questions in free focus

  • Published:
Natural Language Semantics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The sensitivity of focus to context has often been analyzed in terms of focus-based anaphoric relations between sentences and surrounding discourse. The literature, however, has also noted empirical difficulties for the anaphoric approach, and my goal in the present paper is to investigate what happens if we abandon the anaphoric view altogether. Instead of anaphoric felicity conditions, I propose that focus leads to infelicity only indirectly, when the semantic processes that it feeds—in particular, exhaustification and question formation—make an inappropriate contribution to discourse. I outline such an account, in line with Roberts (In Papers in semantics, Vol. 49 of Working papers in linguistics, 91–136, The Ohio State University, 1996) and incorporating recent insights from Büring (In Questions in discourse, Vol. 36 of Current research in the semantics/pragmatics interface, 6–44, Leiden: Brill, 2019) and Fox (In Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 22, 403–434, 2019). This account, which I motivate on conceptual grounds, has no anaphoric conditions on focus placement and has only an economy condition as a potential felicity condition on focus. However, there are cases where the fine control offered by anaphoricity seems needed, either to block deaccenting that would be licensed by a question or to allow local deaccenting that is not warranted by a question. Such cases challenge non-anaphoric accounts such as the present one and appear to support recent anaphoric proposals such as Schwarzschild (In Making worlds accessible. Essays in honor of Angelika Kratzer, 167–192, 2020), Wagner (In The Wiley Blackwell companion to semantics, Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 2020), and Goodhue (Journal of Semantics 39: 117–158, 2022). I argue that this potential motivation for anaphoricity is only apparent and that to the extent that anaphoric conditions on focus from the literature are not inert, they are in fact harmful.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Halliday (1967), Chomsky (1969), Bolinger (1972), Dretske (1972), Jackendoff (1972), von Stechow (1981), Selkirk (1984), Rochemont (1986), Rooth (1992), Williams (1997), and Schwarzschild (1999), among many other works. For recent overviews and further developments see Büring (2016) and Wagner (2020).

  2. For early observations regarding contrast and a proposal that incorporates a contrastive requirement on focus see Jackendoff (1972, pp. 242–245).

  3. In the context of Exh, the alternatives are not of the entire assertion (which includes Exh) but rather of the argument of Exh, often referred to as the prejacent. For presentational convenience I talk about the alternatives of an assertion rather than of a prejacent, but this is not meant to imply a position as to whether a given example should be parsed with Exh.

  4. The roots of this assumption go back at least to Jackendoff (1972, p. 246).

  5. As far as I can tell, Roberts’s (1996) original account is fully compatible with the kinds of non-salient questions assumed here. More recently, Büring (2019) provides an explicit argument that non-salient questions can be focal targets.

  6. As usual, a partition of a set S is a set of nonempty, disjoint sets—sometimes referred to as cells—whose union is S.

  7. Büring (2019) proposes a different condition on good questions that I believe aims at capturing a very similar intuition to that expressed by Partition-by-Exhaustification. In terms of technical implementation, Büring’s (2019) condition differs from Partition-by-Exhaustification in disallowing entailment between elements of the question denotation and therefore rules out questions such as {“She saw some of the convertibles”, “She saw all of the convertibles”}. This is problematic in view of arguments in the literature that entailment relations are possible between the elements of question denotations and that it is only in the pragmatics that these entailment relations are eliminated (see Fox 2019 and references therein). Partition-by-Exhaustification is a principled way to avoid this worry while maintaining Büring’s view that questions are how contrast effects in focus should be understood.

  8. For example, suppose that the answer in (10) had ‘most’ instead of ‘all’ and that the target question were {“She brought some of her convertibles”, “She brought most of her convertibles”, “She brought all of her convertibles”}. Obtaining the inference that she brought most but not all of her convertibles would involve exhaustifying the answer (in addition to the exhaustification of the elements of the question in order to satisfy Partition-by-Exhaustification).

  9. This is a non-exhaustive list. Among other things it does not include F-to-Accent, which as mentioned above I have set aside in the present discussion. It also does not include the accommodation of an expectation, which is an ingredient that I argue for in Sect. 5 below. The table also does not mark connections between ingredients (e.g., that both F-to-Exhaustification and F-to-Question rely on the focus alternatives of F-to-Semantics).

  10. In the present section the examples are provided without F-marking so as to avoid prejudging the question of whether the adjective, the noun, or both are F-marked.

  11. A different and much-discussed illustration of apparent local anaphoric deaccenting is Rooth’s (1992) farmer-example:

    1. i.

      An American/American farmer met a Canadian farmer

    I do not attempt a full account of (i) here and will only mention that as far as I can see the support it offers to Anaphoricity is considerably weaker than it seems. An anaphoric approach, as outlined by Rooth (1992), could let the subject and the direct object be each other’s anaphoric antecedents (possibly with material internal to each of these arguments serving as antecedents to material in the other). But if that were possible, consider what would happen if ‘American’ and ‘Canadian’ were absent. In that case, the two arguments would be identical, so if mutual antecedence were possible, each argument would be given by virtue of the other, and the sentence should have the accent pattern #“A farmer met a farmer” (cf. “He saw you”, where the given constituents are the two pronouns and nothing else), contrary to fact. Note also that the accent pattern in (i) holds even if we change ‘Canadian’ to ‘American’ so as to make the entire direct object given, as in the following continuation of (i):

    1. ii.

      (The following evening…) an American/American farmer met an American farmer

    Since the direct-object DP ‘an American farmer’ is given in (ii), there is no need to F-mark ‘American’ for anaphoric purposes, so by Minimality it should not be F-marked. And yet, F-marking of ‘American’ seems required in this case, just as it was in (i). I conclude that, appearances to the contrary notwithstanding, farmer-sentences do not furnish an argument for Anaphoricity, at least not as currently formulated in the literature.

  12. I thank Danny Fox for discussion of this matter.

  13. As before, I set aside the possibility that the assertion is parsed with an exhaustivity operator. Specifically, it is conceivable that the assertion itself has an F-marker on the entire DP and an exhaustivity operator that associates with it, in addition to its question-related narrow F-marker on the adjective.

  14. In particular, Büring (2019) notes that naive accommodation of a question can lead to overgeneration. He uses such cases to support his claim that deaccenting requires a salient antecedent. As mentioned above, this claim is not about F-marking being anaphoric and is therefore compatible in principle with the present account.

References

  • Allerton, D. J. 1978. The notion of givenness and its relations to presupposition and to theme. Lingua Amsterdam 44: 133–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anvari, Amir. 2021. Cell effability and apparent redundancy effects. Unpublished manuscript.

  • Bade, Nadine, and Konstantin Sachs. 2019. EXH passes on alternatives: A comment on Fox and Spector (2018). Natural Language Semantics 27: 19–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bar-Lev, Moshe E., and Danny Fox. 2020. Free choice, simplification, and innocent inclusion. Natural Language Semantics 28: 175–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bar-Lev, Moshe E., and Danny Fox. 2022. On fatal competition and the nature of distributive inferences. Unpublished manuscript, TAU and MIT.

  • Beaver, David, and Brady Clark. 2008. Sense and sensitivity: How focus determines meaning. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bolinger, Dwight. 1972. Accent is predictable (if you’re a mind-reader). Language 48: 633–644.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Büring, Daniel. 2015. Unalternative semantics. In Proceedings of SALT 25, eds. Sarah D’Antonio, Mary Moroney, and Carol Rose Little, 550–575.

    Google Scholar 

  • Büring, Daniel. 2016. Intonation and meaning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Büring, Daniel. 2019. Focus, questions and givenness. In Questions in discourse, ed. Klaus von Heusinger, Edgar Onea, and Malte Zimmermann. Vol. 36 of Current research in the semantics/pragmatics interface, 6–44. Leiden: Brill

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Büring, Daniel. 2012. What’s given (and what’s new) in the theory of focus? In Proceedings of BLS 34, February 8–10 2008, eds. Sarah Berson et al., 403–424. Berkeley: Berkeley Linguistics Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chafe, Wallace L. 1974. Language and consciousness. Language 50: 111–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia, Gennaro, Danny Fox, and Benjamin Spector. 2012. Scalar implicature as a grammatical phenomenon. In Semantics: An international handbook of natural language meaning, eds. Paul Portner, Claudia Maienborn, and Klaus von Heusinger. Vol. 3, Chap. 87, 2297–2331. Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, Noam. 1969. Deep structure, surface structure, and semantic interpretation. Bloomington: Indiana University Linguistics Club.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luka Crnič, Emmanuel Chemla, and Danny Fox. 2015. Scalar implicatures of embedded disjunction. Natural Language Semantics 23: 271–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, Fred I. 1972. Contrastive statements. Philosophical Review 81: 411–437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fox, Danny. 2004. Implicatures and exhaustivity, class 1. Handout for a seminar given at USC.

  • Fox, Danny. 2007. Free choice disjunction and the theory of scalar implicatures. In Presupposition and implicature in compositional semantics, eds. Uli Sauerland and Penka Stateva. 71–120. London: Palgrave-Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fox, Danny. 2019. Partition by exhaustification: Comments on Dayal 1996. In Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 22, eds. Uli Sauerland and Stephanie Solt, 403–434.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fox, Danny. 2020. Partition by exhaustification: Towards a solution to Gentile and Scharwarz’s puzzle. Unpublished manuscript.

  • Fox, Danny, and Martin Hackl. 2006. The universal density of measurement. Linguistics and Philosophy 29: 537–586.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fox, Danny, and Roni Katzir. 2011. On the characterization of alternatives. Natural Language Semantics 19: 87–107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fox, Danny, and Benjamin Spector. 2018. Economy and embedded exhaustification. Natural Language Semantics 26: 1–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodhue, Daniel. 2022. All focus is contrastive: On polarity (verum) focus, answer focus, contrastive focus and givenness. Journal of Semantics 39: 117–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Groenendijk, Jeroen, and Martin Stokhof. 1984. Studies in the semantics of questions and the pragmatics of answers, PhD dissertation, Universiteit van Amsterdam, Amsterdam.

  • Halliday, Michael A. K. 1967. Notes on transitivity and theme in English, part II. Journal of Linguistics 3: 199–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamblin, C. L. 1973. Questions in Montague English. Foundations of Language 10: 41–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackendoff, Ray. 1972. Semantic interpretation in generative grammar. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Karttunen, Lauri. 1977. Syntax and semantics of questions. Linguistics and Philosophy 1: 3–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Katzir, Roni. 2013. A note on contrast. Natural Language Semantics 21: 333–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Katzir, Roni. 2014. On the roles of markedness and contradiction in the use of alternatives. In Semantics, pragmatics, and the case of scalar implicatures, ed. Salvatore Pistoia Reda, 40–71. London: Palgrave-Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Katzir, Roni, and Raj Singh. 2015. Economy of structure and information: Oddness, questions, and answers. In Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 19, ed. Eva Csipak and Hedde Zeijlstra, 302–319.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krifka, Manfred. 1995. The semantics and pragmatics of polarity items. Linguistic Analysis 25: 1–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krifka, Manfred. 2004. Focus and/or context: A second look at second occurrence expressions. In Context-dependence in the analysis of linguistic meaning, eds. Hans Kamp and Barbara Partee, 187–207. New York: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladd, Robert D. 1980. The structure of intonational meaning, Chaps. 3–4. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, David. 1988. Relevant implication. Theoria 54: 161–174.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, Craige. 1996. Information structure in discourse: Towards an integrated formal theory of pragmatics. In Papers in semantics, eds. Jae-Hak Yoon and Andreas Kathol. Vol. 49 of Working papers in linguistics, 91–136. The Ohio State University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rochemont, Michael. 1986. Focus in generative grammar. Amsterdam: Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rooth, Mats. 1992. A theory of focus interpretation. Natural Language Semantics 1: 75–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rooth, Mats. 1996. Focus. In Handbook of contemporary semantic theory, ed. S. Lappin, 271–297. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sauerland, Uli. 2004. Scalar implicatures in complex sentences. Linguistics and Philosophy 27: 367–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sauerland, Uli. 2005. Don’t interpret focus! Why a presuppositional account of focus fails, and how a presuppositional account of givenness works. In Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 9, eds. Emar Maier, Corien Bary, and Janneke Huitink, 370–384. Nijmegen: University of Nijmegen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwarzschild, Roger. 1999. GIVENness, AvoidF and other constraints on the placement of accent. Natural Language Semantics 7: 141–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwarzschild, Roger. 2020. The representation of focus, givenness and exhaustivity. In Making worlds accessible. Essays in honor of Angelika Kratzer, eds. Rajesh Bhatt, Ilaria Frana, and Paula Menendez Benito, 167–192.

    Google Scholar 

  • Selkirk, Elisabeth. 1984. Phonology and syntax: The relation between sound and structure. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spathas, Giorgos. 2010. Focus on anaphora: Accent placement and the syntax and semantics of anaphors, PhD dissertation, Universiteit Utrecht.

  • Jon Scott Stevens. 2014. Against a unified analysis of givenness and focus. In Proceedings of WCCFL 31, ed. Robert E. Santana-LaBarge, 438–446.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, Kai. 1994. Restrictions on quantifier domains, PhD dissertation, University of Massachusetts, Amherst.

  • von Stechow, Arnim. 1981. Topic, focus and local relevance. In Crossing the boundaries in linguistics, eds. Wolfgang Klein and Willem J. M. Levelt, 95–130. New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, Michael. 2006. Givenness and locality. In Proceedings of SALT 16, eds. Jonathan Howell and Masayuki Gibson, 295–312. Ithaca: CLC Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, Michael. 2012. Focus and givenness: A unified approach. In Contrasts and positions in information structure, eds. Ivona Kučerová and Ad Neeleman, 102–147. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, Michael. 2020. Prosodic focus. In The Wiley Blackwell companion to semantics, eds. Gutzmann Daniel, Lisa Matthewson, Cécile Meier, Hotze Rullmann, and Thomas Ede Zimmermann. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Edwin. 1997. Blocking and anaphora. Linguistic Inquiry 28: 577–628.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Special thanks to Moysh Bar-Lev, Daniel Büring, Danny Fox, Florian Schwarz, and Roger Schwarzschild for their patient and extremely helpful comments on multiple revisions of this paper. I am also very grateful to Itai Bassi, Aya Chayat, Luka Crnič, Milica Denić, Dan Goodhue, Aron Hirsch, Manfred Krifka, Fereshteh Modarresi, Ezer Rasin, Aviv Schoenfeld, Raj Singh, Giorgos Spathas, Yasu Sudo, Tue Trinh, and Michael Wagner, as well as the audiences at MIT, McGill, CNRS, Leipzig University, Tel Aviv University, ZAS, the University of Göttingen, the ENS, and HUJI.

Funding

This work has been supported by a TAU Breakthrough/Schmidt Futures grant and by a Leibniz ZAS Visiting Fellowship.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Ethics declarations

Competing Interests

The author has no conflicts of interest to declare relevant to the content of this article.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Katzir, R. On the roles of anaphoricity and questions in free focus. Nat Lang Semantics 32, 65–92 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-023-09214-z

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-023-09214-z

Keywords

Navigation