Skip to main content
Log in

Supervaluationism, Modal Logic, and Weakly Classical Logic

  • Published:
Journal of Philosophical Logic Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A consequence relation is strongly classical if it has all the theorems and entailments of classical logic as well as the usual meta-rules (such as Conditional Proof). A consequence relation is weakly classical if it has all the theorems and entailments of classical logic but lacks the usual meta-rules. The most familiar example of a weakly classical consequence relation comes from a simple supervaluational approach to modelling vague language. This approach is formally equivalent to an account of logical consequence according to which \(\alpha _1, \ldots , \alpha _n\) entails \(\beta \) just in case \(\Box \alpha _1, \ldots , \Box \alpha _n\) entails \(\Box \beta \) in the modal logic S5. This raises a natural question: If we start with a different underlying modal logic, can we generate a strongly classical logic? This paper explores this question. In particular, it discusses four related technical issues: (1) Which base modal logics generate strongly classical logics and which generate weakly classical logics? (2) Which base logics generate themselves? (3) How can we directly characterize the logic generated from a given base logic? (4) Given a logic that can be generated, which base logics generate it? The answers to these questions have philosophical interest. They can help us to determine whether there is a plausible supervaluational approach to modelling vague language that yields the usual meta-rules. They can also help us to determine the feasibility of other philosophical projects that rely on an analogous formalism, such as the project of defining logical consequence in terms of the preservation of an epistemic status.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Availability of data and materials

Not applicable.

References

  1. Avron, A. (1991). Simple consequence relations. Information and Computation, 92, 105–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Asher, N., Dever, J., & Pappas, C. (2009). Supervaluations debugged. Mind, 118, 901–933.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Bledin, J. (2014). Logic informed. Mind, 123, 277–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Brandom, R. (1994). Making it Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Chellas, B. Modal Logic: An Introduction (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1980). Reprinted with corrections 1988.

  6. Chellas, B., & Segerberg, K. (1994). Modal logics with the Macintosh rule. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 23, 67–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Cobreros, P. (2008). Supervaluationism and logical consequence: A third way. Studia Logica, 90, 291–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Cobreros, P. (2011). Supervaluationism and classical logic. In R. Nouwen, R. van Rooji, U. Sauerland & H. C. Schmitz (Eds.), Vagueness in communication (pp. 51–63). Berlin: Springer.

  9. Edgington, D. (1993). Wright and Sainsbury on higher-order vagueness. Analysis, 53, 193–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Field, H. (2008). Saving Truth from Paradox. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  11. Fine, K. (1975). Vagueness, truth and logic. Synthese, 30, 265–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Graff Fara, D. (2004). Gap principles, penumbral consequence, and infinitely higher-order vagueness. In J. C. Beall (Ed.), Liars and heaps: New essays on paradox (pp. 195–221). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  13. Heck, R. K. (1993). A note on the logic of (higher-order) vagueness. Analysis, 53, 201–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Hyde, D. (1997). From heaps and gaps to heaps of gluts. Mind, 106, 641–660.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Iemhoff, R. (2015). On rules. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 44, 697–711.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Jeřábek, E. (2005). Admissible rules of modal logics. Journal of Logic and Computation, 15, 411–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Keefe, R. (2000). Supervaluationism and validity. Philosophical Topics, 28, 93–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Keefe, R. (2000). Theories of Vagueness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Kripke, S. A. (1963). Semantical analysis of modal logic I: Normal propositional calculi. Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, 9, 67–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Lemmon, E. An Introduction to Modal Logic: The Lemmon Notes (Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 1977). Written in collaboration with Dana Scott. Edited by Krister Segerberg.

  21. Lorenzen, P. (1955). Einführung in die operative Logik und Mathematik Vol. 78 of Grundlehren der mathematischen Wissenschaften (Springer-Verlag, Berlin).

  22. Loś, J., & Suszko, R. (1958). Remarks on sentential logics. Indagationes Mathematicae, 20, 177–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Machina, K. (1976). Truth, belief, and vagueness. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 5, 47–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. McGee, V., & McLaughlin, B. (1995). Distinctions without a difference. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 33, 203–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. McGee, V., & McLaughlin, B. P. (2004). Logical commitment and semantic indeterminacy: A reply to Williamson. Linguistics and Philosophy, 27, 123–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Popper, K. (1947). New foundations for logic. Mind, 56, 193–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Prawitz, D. (2015). Explaining deductive inference. In H. Wansing (Ed.), Dag Prawitz on proofs and meaning (pp. 65–100). Cham: Springer.

  28. Ripley, D. (2012). Conservatively extending classical logic with transparent truth. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 5, 354–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Rybakov, V. V. (1997). Admissibility of Logical Inference Rules Vol. 136 of Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics (Elsevier, Amsterdam).

  30. Sahlqvist, H. (1975). Completeness and correspondence in the first and second order semantics for modal logic. In S. Kanger (Ed.), Proceedings of the third scandinavian logic symposium (Vol. 82 of Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, pp. 110–143). Elsevier.

  31. Schechter, J. (forthcoming). Epistemic characterizations of validity and level-bridging principles. Philosophical Studies.

  32. Schechter, J. (2011). Juxtaposition: A new way to combine logics. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 4, 560–606.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Shapiro, S. (2006). Vagueness in Context. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  34. Smiley, T. (1963). Relative necessity. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 28, 113–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Sundholm, G. (2012). “Inference versus consequence" revisited: Inference, consequence, conditional, implication. Synthese, 187, 943–956.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. Sundholm, G. (1983). Systems of deduction. In D. Gabbay & F. Guenthner (Eds.), Handbook of philosophical logic (Vol. 1, pp. 133–188). Dordrecht: Reidel.

  37. Varzi, A. (2007). Supervaluationism and its logics. Mind, 116, 633–676.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Williams, J. R. (2008). Supervaluationism and logical revisionism. Journal of Philosophy, 105, 192–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Williamson, T. (1988). Assertion, denial and some cancellation rules in modal logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 17, 299–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. Williamson, T. (1992). An alternative rule of disjunction in modal logic. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 33, 89–100.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Williamson, T. (1994). Vagueness. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Williamson, T. (1996). Some admissible rules in modal systems with the Brouwerian axiom. Logic Journal of the IGPL, 4, 283–303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  43. Williamson, T. (2018). Supervaluationism and good reasoning. Theoria, 33, 521–537.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  44. Wright, C. (1992). Is higher order vagueness coherent? Analysis, 52, 129–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Riki Heck, Stephan Krämer, Stephan Leuenberger, and Bruno Whittle for discussion. Thanks to two anonymous referees for extensive and helpful comments.

Funding

No funding was received to assist with the preparation of this manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

Not applicable.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joshua Schechter.

Ethics declarations

Ethical Approval

Not applicable.

Competing interests

The author has no competing interests to declare.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Schechter, J. Supervaluationism, Modal Logic, and Weakly Classical Logic. J Philos Logic 53, 411–461 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-023-09737-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-023-09737-0

Keywords

Navigation