Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-75dct Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-04T13:50:40.323Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

An Epistemic Injustice Critique of Austin's Ordinary Language Epistemology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 February 2024

Savannah Pearlman*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Howard University in Washington, DC, USA

Abstract

J. L. Austin argues that ordinary language should be used to identify when it is appropriate or inappropriate to make, accept, or reject knowledge claims. I criticize Austin's account. In our ordinary life, we often accept justifications rooted in racism, sexism, ableism, and classism as reasons to dismiss knowledge claims or challenges, despite the fact such reasons are not good reasons. Austin's Ordinary Language Epistemology (OLE) inadvertently classifies the discounting of knowledge claims in classic cases of epistemic injustice as legitimate ordinary maneuvers. I provide recommendations for revision of OLE and offer a means of distinguishing between dismissals in cases of epistemic injustice and their legitimate counterparts.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Hypatia, a Nonprofit Corporation

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Anderson, Elizabeth. 2012. Epistemic justice as a virtue of social institutions. Social Epistemology 26 (2): 163–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Antony, Louise. 2016. Bias: Friend or foe? Reflections on Saulish skepticism. In Implicit bias and philosophy, vol. 1. Metaphysics and epistemology, ed. Brownstein, Michael and Saul., Jennifer Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Austin, J. L. 1946/1970. Other minds. In Philosophical papers, ed. Urmson, J. O. and Warnock, Geoffrey James. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Austin, J. L. 1956/7. A plea for excuses. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ns 57: 130.Google Scholar
Basu, Rima. 2018. The wrongs of racist beliefs. Philosophical Studies 176 (9): 24972515.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Basu, Rima. 2019. Radical moral encroachment: The moral stakes of racist beliefs. Philosophical Issues 29 (1): 923.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Basu, Rima, and Schroeder, Mark. 2019. Doxastic wronging. In Pragmatic encroachment in epistemology, ed. Kim, Brian and McGrath, Matthew. Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar
Bauer, Nancy. 2015. How to do things with pornography. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baz, Avner. 2012. When words are called for. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brownstein, Michael and Saul, Jennifer, eds. 2016. Implicit bias and philosophy, vol. 1. Metaphysics and epistemology. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davis, Emmalon. 2016. Typecasts, tokens, and spokespersons: A case for credibility excess in testimonial injustice. Hypatia 31 (3): 485501.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fanon, Franz. 1967. Black skin, white masks. New York: Grove Press.Google Scholar
Fricker, Miranda. 2007. Epistemic injustice: power and the ethics of knowing. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gellner, Ernest. 1959. Words and things. London: Victor Gollancz.Google Scholar
Gerken, Mikkel. 2019. Pragmatic encroachment and the challenge from epistemic injustice. Philosopher's Imprint 19 (15): 119.Google Scholar
Hanfling, Oswald. 1999. Philosophy and ordinary language: The bent and genius of our tongue. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Hornsby, Jennifer. 1993. Speech acts and pornography. Women's Philosophy Review 10: 3845.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hornsby, Jennifer. 1995. Disempowered speech. Philosophical Topics 23 (2): 127–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ichikawa, Jonathan. 2020. Contextual injustice. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 30 (1): 130.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kaplan, Mark. 2018. Austin's way with skepticism: An essay on philosophical method. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Langton, Rae. 1993. Speech acts and unspeakable acts. Philosophy and Public Affairs 22 (4): 293330.Google Scholar
Lewis, David. 1983. Scorekeeping in a language game. Philosophical Papers Volume I. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Marcuse, Herbert. 1964. One-dimensional man: Studies in the ideology of advanced industrial society. Boston: Beacon Press.Google Scholar
Medina, José. 2013. The epistemology of resistance: Gender and racial oppression, epistemic injustice, and resistant imaginations. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pohlhaus, Gale Jr.. 2017. Varieties of epistemic injustice. In The Routledge handbook of epistemic injustice, ed. Kidd, I. J., Pohlhaus, G., and Medina, J. M.. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Ryle, Gilbert, and Findlay, J. N.. 1961. Use, usage and meaning. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes 35: 223–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Silberzahn, R., et al. 2018. Many analysts, one data set: Making transparent how variations in analytic choices affect results. Advances in Methods and Practices in Psychological Science 1 (3): 337–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Uschanov, T. P. (2002). Ernest Gellner's criticisms of Wittgenstein and ordinary language philosophy. In Marx and Wittgenstein: Knowledge, morality and politics, ed. Gavin Kitching and Nigel Pleasants. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Wertheimer, Alan. 1976. Is ordinary language analysis conservative? Political Theory 4 (4): 405–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Young, Iris Marion. 2014. Five faces of oppression. In Diversity, social justice, and inclusive excellence, ed. Asumah, S. N. and Nagel, M.. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Yuan, Li et al. 2019. Gender differences in large-scale and small-scale spatial ability: A systematic review based on behavioral and neuroimaging research. Frontiers in Behavioral Neuroscience 13: 128.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed