The reassessment of intentionality as “tendency” or “drive,” already important when the intentionality at stake designates the directedness of lived experiences toward a particular object, might be even more crucial when the orientation toward others is concerned. How do drives and affects intermingle within our intersubjective life and fashion our relations to others? The present paper will address this question by focusing on a particular or even primary kind of intersubjectivity: the mother–child relationship, that received a particular, yet still insufficiently noticed attention in early phenomenology. Scheler and Husserl both analyse this relationship, indeed, in terms that imply drive intentionality as well as affective intentionality (that is, for what concerns the mother, maternal instinct and maternal love). In their view, this relation also has a crucial ethical significance, and may even be taken to be paradigmatic for ethical relationships as such. Accordingly, drive intentionality is understood as an instinctive orientation toward others,Footnote 1 that love takes up and develops, thus providing an affective and even instinctive ground for ethical behaviour. All this implies the departure from an ethics exclusively grounded on the primacy and sufficiency of reason, while also suggesting that drives and affects must be part of a complete phenomenology of reason.Footnote 2

To show this progression from tendencies and drives to affectivity and ethics, I will first (I) examine the Husserlian account of the mother–child relationship and its profound relevance for an understanding of intersubjective life through the prism of generativity, which amounts to insisting on the “generative connection” of subjectivities. From this point of view, the mother–child relationship appears as a primary form of intersubjectivity that has a considerable impact on the beginnings of subjectivity as well as on world-constitution, since it implies a specific form of intercorporeality and the remarkable intertwining of two spheres of experience. The instinctive orientation toward others, that exemplarily manifests itself in the case of the mother and the child, is also one of the most prominent expressions of drive-intentionality. Furthermore, as I will attempt to show in a second moment (II), it is by paying particular attention to the ethical dimension of maternal conduct that Husserl is led not only to part with Brentano’s ethics of the highest practical Good but also to recognize the remarkable teleological continuity that exists between instincts, feelings and ethical behaviour and that demands to reconsider the idea of an ethics of pure reason. It is why the mother’s instinctive and loving valuation of her child(ren) can become a paradigm for a new understanding of ethical life as consisting in “duties of love”. An inquiry into Scheler’s phenomenological analytic of love (III) will provide us with an alternative account of the mother–child relationship that fruitfully challenges the supposed continuity between maternal instinct and maternal love, but also rests on a conception of instinct which is less careful to avoid its naturalization. Scheler’s main point, however, is that maternal love implies a resistance to the tendency of identification (Einsfühlung) with the child that is so powerful in instinct, and thus necessarily develops itself as love of another person. Having established this, a final section (IV) will seek to highlight both the divergences and the convergences of Husserl’s and Scheler’s accounts of motherhood and to argue for the complementarity of the manners in which they understand the peculiarities of this intersubjective, affective and ethical situation.

The Mother–Child Relationship and the Instinctive Orientation Toward Others: The Husserlian Account

The publication of Husserl’s research manuscripts has provided, since the 1970s, significantly new insights into his phenomenology of intersubjectivity, famously outlined in the Fifth Cartesian Meditation. This is particularly the case for his research from the 1930s, which reveals the increasing importance of the “generative problems” of phenomenology, that the published work only stealthily mentions.Footnote 3 The genetic account of transcendental life, which deals with immanent temporality and self-temporalization, is thereby significantly complemented by the generative one, which insists on the fact that each subjectivity belongs to a “generative connection (generativer Zusammenhang)Footnote 4” that fashions the peculiarity of both its intersubjective and its historicalFootnote 5 life. In one of the C-Manuscripts from the early thirties, Husserl even speaks of “the connection of transcendental generations (Zusammenhang der transzendentalen Generationen)” as highly determinant for the subject of world-constitution (Husserl, 2006: 392, Hua Mat VIII), thus clearly stressing the transcendental significance of generativity and providing one of the many confirmations that the field of the “generative problems” fully belongs to transcendental phenomenology.Footnote 6

Generativity chiefly manifests itself through the fact that one is born,Footnote 7 which expresses the relational, intersubjective, and even intercorporeal emergence of each subjectivity. This is why, in an Arbeitsmanuskript from 1933 or 1934 published in Husserliana XLII, Husserl can raise the “questions concerning what is properly < meant by > ‘procreation’ from a monadic [i.e., transcendental] point of view (die Fragen, was, monadisch gesehen, unter dem Titel ‘Zeugung’ eigentlich < zu verstehen > ist)” (Husserl, 2014: 25, Hua XLII). The famous “Universal Teleology” research manuscript from September 1933 convergently deals with procreation (Zeugung), as it is involved in sexual drive,Footnote 8 and with “drive intentionality (Triebintentionalität),” as it designates the (sexual and social: “geschlechtlich-sozial”) orientation toward others. The research field that is thus delineated, Husserl adds at this occasion, comprises the “problems relating to parents and, above all, to mother and child, which also arise in connection with the problematic of copulation (die Probleme Eltern, oder vor allem, Mutter und Kind, die aber auch im Zusammenhang der Kopulationsproblematik erwachsen)” (Husserl, 1973b: 594, Hua XV). Such issues are undoubtedly even more difficult to tackle nowadays when medically-assisted procreation multiplies the forms of parenthood and makes it possible to dissociate genetic motherhood and gestation, on the one hand, and gestation and maternity, on the other.Footnote 9 Admittedly, Husserl does not distinguish between biological parenthood and social parenthood, no doubt because he sees them as going mostly hand in hand. However, it is important to stress that both forms of parenthood must be considered when dealing with the “generative connection” of subjectivities, insofar as this connection concerns not only procreation and birth but also the fact that the child’s progressive awakening to consciousness and the development of her directedness toward the world and the others are relational or intersubjective processes themselves.

It is true, nonetheless, that Husserl is particularly interested in the mother–child relationship that is built through pregnancy or gestation, as he specifically reflects on the fact that birth is preceded by a prenatal life—an original or primary childhood (Urkindlichkeit), as he says—which already implies a certain kind of intentionality and world-possession; and this primary, original intentionality must precisely be described as instinctive. Thus, in another research manuscript from 1933–34 that aims to disclose, once again, the “universal teleology” running through “the process of the global constitution since the very beginnings” (its title is “Enthüllungsgang der universalen Teleologie als Gang der gesamten Konstitution von den Anfängen an”), Husserl contends that an “‘instinctive’ relatedness to the world (‘instinktive’ Weltbezogenheit)” begins in the mother’s womb, during prenatal life (Husserl, 2014: 222, Hua XLIIFootnote 10), as it is passively triggered through affection and sensitive stimulation long before the awake, conscious life can commence. One of the C-Manuscripts edited by Dieter Lohmar in 2006 also argues that it is already since the “primary childhood (Urkindheit)” spent within the maternal womb that the child has a life of interests oriented toward the world and toward beings, that is, an “instinctive intentionality (instinktive Intentionalität)”. For this reason, and insofar as, in world-constitution, that which is constituted closely depends on the constituting subject, Husserl can state that “the world itself has a childhood (Die Welt selbst also hat Kindheit und wächst heran zur reifen Welt)” (Husserl, 2006: 74, Hua Mat VIII). The manuscripts recently published as Studien zur Struktur des Bewusstseins also confirm that world-constitution responds (to quote a text from the beginning of the thirties) to “instincts toward worldliness (Instinkte der Weltlichkeit)” (Husserl, 2020b: 174, Hua XLIII/3) which are distinct, Husserl suggests, from the very first instincts that lead a newborn to seek the presence of her mother.Footnote 11

Importantly, it is not only the relationship to the world but also the orientation toward others that Husserl regards as instinctive.Footnote 12 And it is also in this respect that he repeatedly stresses the significance of what counts for him as the most original intersubjective bond: the relationship to the mother, as she often is the most prominent of the “first others (die ersten Anderen)” (Husserl, 1973b: 604, Hua XV) that a child encounters in her life.Footnote 13 Accordingly, Husserl claims that the “instinctive relatedness to others (instinktive Bezogensein auf Andere)” that commands the beginning of our intersubjective life originates in the relation to the mother (“auf die Mutter in der Genesis von Anfang an” (Husserl, 2014: 461, Hua XLII)). The child’s instinctive orientation toward the mother—or, one should add, toward the primary caregiver or attachment figure who occupies the maternal position when the (genetic, gestational or social) mother herself is absent—is firstly “intertwined with the instinct of nourishment and with the instinct of objectivation,” but afterwards progressively develops itself into specific feelings, turning “into empathy and < into the > most original human love, the love for the mother (Der Instinkt zur Mutter hin, verflochten mit dem Nahrungsinstinkt und dem Instinkt der Objektivierung, arbeitet sich aus in der Einfühlung und < in der > ursprünglichsten menschlichen Liebe, als Liebe zur Mutter)” (Husserl, 2014: 465, Hua XLII). Such a progressive and even teleological development of intentional and intersubjective life pleads for the acknowledgment of a remarkable continuity between instinct and affectivity.

Empathy and love are nonetheless possible only when the mother has been identified as an other. Immediately after birth, as well as during prenatal life or during “primary childhood,” the separation of the self and the other has not yet been made. Husserl pays particular attention to this situation that is unique and irreplaceable within subjective and intersubjective life: in another research manuscript from 1932, he mentions “the child in the mother’s womb, with sensory fields undergoing smooth changes (Das Kind im Mutterleib, mit Empfindungsfeldern, die im glatten Wandel sind),” and then elaborates in a marginal annotation:

The child within the mother. Don’t we have <here> an intertwining (ein Ineinander) of primordialities, which is not based on empathy (Einfühlung)? Does the mother possess, among her inner sensory fields—which, due to their smooth mutability, do not lead to any objectifying configuration—also those of the child, her sensations of movement, her kinaestheses? If not, what kind of community is this? In what way does the mother suffer when the child does not feel well? (Husserl, 2014: 27, Hua XLII)

As we can see, Husserl questions here the gestational experience of the mother and what we might call its transcendental meaning: what kind of intersubjectivity is built through the intercorporeality of pregnancy? Can the mother live the Urkind’s sensations and movements as her own? How does she experience the fact that the pre-infantFootnote 14 is someone else and also belongs to her own body? These classical interrogations that the philosophical and phenomenological account of pregnancy has abundantly put forth since Beauvoir, Kristeva, and YoungFootnote 15 are raised here by the founder of phenomenology himself.Footnote 16

If Husserl often describes the relationship between mother and child—which he also depicts in a 1927 text as the “most original genetic continuity” (Husserl, 1973a: 504, Hua XIV)—as “formed instinctively in an original manner (ein ursprünglich instinktiv sich ausbildender Konnex)” (Husserl, 1973b: 582, Hua XV), one has to ask, though, what is the meaning of the instinct in question. Does it remain true to the precept of avoiding the naturalization of transcendental life? Otherwise said, does it completely dismiss a biological or naturalistic understanding of instinct? And most of all, can we bestow instinct a properly transcendental meaning? Undoubtedly, the fact that the mother will always stand out as the first other toward whom we are instinctively oriented is also in line with Husserl’s traditional (if not patriarchalFootnote 17) vision of family. This vision is manifest, for instance, in a 1921 text where the reference to what is “natural” overshadows the historical, social and cultural as well as the transcendental dimension of intersubjective life. The question as to whether the naturalization of this life is successfully avoided at all times also emerges when one reads the following: “In the family community that develops in a natural way, we easily see that what comes first is the solicitude (Fürsorge) of the mother for the children, which develops in a natural and naive way” (Husserl, 1973a: 180, Hua XIV). More generally (and also more optimistically), to quote an even earlier text (from 1916–1918), Husserl believes that “in the relationship between parents and children” we are dealing with an “original drive to satisfy the needs of others, to alleviate the suffering of others (ursprünglicher Trieb zur Stillung fremder Bedürfnisse, zur Beseitigung fremder Leiden)” (Husserl, 2014: 85, Hua XLII). The drives that govern parental behaviours are undoubtedly depicted here in an overly simplistic and insufficiently nuanced manner, in a regrettable indifference to the penetrating insights that history, cultural anthropology, sociology, psychology or psychoanalysis had already started to provide with respect to them. Such an indifference can also be regretted when Husserl plainly claims that the mother, “with her maternal instincts, ‘lives in the child’ (Die Mutter mit ihren Mutterinstinkten ‘lebt im Kinde’)” (Husserl, 2006: 170, Hua Mat VIII). If motherhood is thus undoubtedly idealized in a way that makes it impossible to account for the immense variety and even the radical heterogeneity of maternal conduct, it is also in order to present it as a vocation (see Donohoe, 2010) and to make it function as an ethical paradigm. This means that mothers are also idealized insofar as, for Husserl, they count as unrivalled models from the outset, since their instinctive orientation toward their children, insofar as it is likely to develop into love, is supposed to make them act like good mothers.

The Absolute Ought of Maternal Love, a Paradigm for Ethics

The ethical dimension of the reference to the mother grounds in a conception of maternal love as absolute and unconditioned, which plays a clearly paradigmatic role in Husserl’s late ethics.Footnote 18 This striking peculiarity has drawn the attention of scholars even previous to the publication of the ethical research manuscripts from the Freiburg period in Husserliana, volume XLII.Footnote 19 In one of these texts, Husserl famously writes that “the mother is subject to the absolute ought of her maternal love, the duty to care for the object of her love (Die Mutter steht unter dem absoluten Sollen ihrer mütterlichen Liebe, ihr Geliebtes zu besorgen)” (Husserl, 2014: 357, Hua XLII). The good of her child is the supreme value for her, and this shows, for Husserl, that “individual vocation is always directed toward values, but can also be blind and instinctive, as in the case of the originally blind maternal instinct (dieser individuelle Ruf immer auf Werte zurückgeht, aber instinktiv blind sein kann wie der ursprünglich blinde Mutterinstinkt)” (Husserl, 2014: 359, Hua XLII). Such a claim not only suggests that “Husserl’s later account of absolute values takes the absolute value of our relation to another [person] as its basis and inspiration” (Leon-Carlyle, 2021: 41), but also challenges the possibility of a self-sufficient ethics of (pure) reason as it reveals the “irrationality of the absolute ought (Irrationalität des absoluten Sollens)” (Husserl, 2014: 384, Hua XLII) and the unexpected continuity between instinctive and affective life, on the one hand, and ethical life, on the other.Footnote 20 The maternal figure is meant precisely to embody and illustrate this continuity, as she acts out of instinct and love, and not out of reason alone, and is a good mother as such;Footnote 21 if her child is an absolute value to her, it is on the ground of affective rather than exclusively rational evaluation. The numerous occasions where Husserl speaks of maternal love take up the reference to maternal ethical behaviours that arise instinctively and thoughtlessly as evidence for the thesis that absolute duty begins in instinct and affect: maternal love is indeed, in the phenomenologist’s view, both “instinctiveFootnote 22”—in a sense that Husserl strives, but sometimes fails to fairly distinguish from a biological driveFootnote 23—and ethical.

The axiological consciousness is at the very heart of this transmutation of instinct into an ethical behaviour. Like Scheler,Footnote 24 Husserl acknowledges an indissoluble link between affectivity and valuation. In a research manuscript written around 1920 and recently published in the Studien zur Struktur des Bewusstseins, he reflects upon the difference between “instinctive feelings (Triebgefühlen)” and “axiological feelings (Wertgefühlen)” (that are distinct from perceptions of values or Wertnehmungen), and he significantly chooses the example of “instinctive (triebhaft)” mother love in order to suggest that the two kinds of feelings are nonetheless related, insofar as “the mother can also see that the child is a value in herself (Mutter kann auch sehen, dass das Kind ein Wert ist an sich)” (Husserl, 2020b: 459, Hua XLIII/3)Footnote 25 and operate, on the ground of her love for the child, an act of conscious and even rational valuation.

While Husserl’s late ethics has received important attention during the last decades, and the paradigmatic example of mother-love has often been highlighted, the relation between ethical mother love and mother instinct, as it provides itself the chief example of the instinctive relatedness to others, has been more rarely discussed.Footnote 26 It might be particularly illuminating to insist here on the remarkable convergence between the personalist orientation of Husserl’s late ethics (see Peucker, 2010) and the generative turn of his late phenomenology of intersubjectivity, within which, as shown above, the mother–child relationship also counts as the most fundamental link implied by the “generative connection (generativer Zusammenhang)” of subjectivities.

The ethical dimension of maternal behaviour might even be the very first trigger of Husserl’s attention to the mother–child relationship. Since the publication of his early lectures on ethics in 1988 (Husserliana, volume XXVIII), Ulrich Melle, the volume’s editor, provided some very precious insights into his late Freiburg ethics and into the reasons that led him to dismiss the Brentanian ethics of the highest practical Good. Husserl mentions indeed, on a sheet inserted in the manuscript of his 1919–20 lecture, Einleitung in die Philosophie, that it is as early as 1907 that Moritz Geiger addressed him with the “justified objection” that “it would be ridiculous to ask a mother to consider whether the promotion of her child is the best thing in her practical field” (Husserl, 2012: 146, Hua Mat IX, footnote).Footnote 27 As Melle suggests, Geiger’s objection also points to the incommensurability of values and to the fact that their objective ranking doesn’t unmistakably provide the right response for moral choices (objections that might also work, in fact, against Scheler).Footnote 28 Against Brentano, indeed, Husserl argues that what has to be done and what is best do not necessarily coincide: “Playing a Mozart sonata is more beautiful than washing the child, but the latter is a duty when the time is right now (Das Spielen einer Mozartschen Sonate ist schöner als das Waschen des Kindes, aber das letztere ist Pflicht, wenn es jetzt eben an der Zeit ist)” (Ms. A V 21, 122a/b, quoted in Melle, 1988: XLVII, now published in Husserl, 2014: 390, Hua XLII). It is precisely this incommensurability of (absolute) values that makes their objective ranking impossible and confers a tragic dimension to moral choices.Footnote 29 Accordingly, ethical life is inescapably made of dilemmas and sacrifices, and mothers appear as ethical models not only insofar as they (are supposed to) prefer what “has to be done” for their child to “what is best,” but also as far as they exemplarily lead a life of difficult choices (see Donohoe, 2010: 134; Leon-Carlyle, 2021), especially when they have more than one child.Footnote 30 Brentano’s “law of absorption,” according to which the higher practical Good “absorbs” the inferior ones, is challenged by such moral choices where two absolute values stand in an irreducible conflict.Footnote 31 Husserl’s prime example is the conflict between the (maternal) love of the child and the love for the country—a conflict that countless mothers of soldiers, including his wife Malvine, had faced at the time during the Great War.Footnote 32 Such a conflict cannot be solved through an objective ranking of values, since both are absolute values or, as Husserl puts it, “values of love (Liebeswerte)Footnote 33” that each command particular “duties of love (Liebespflichten)” (Husserl, 2012: 146, Hua Mat IX, footnote). Considering the ethical subject in her specific, irreducible and unique situation—since every person’s moral obligations are dictated by the domain of her love (“jedermann hat seine Liebessphäre und seine ‘LiebespflichtenFootnote 34”) (Husserl, 2012: 146, Hua Mat IX, footnote)—, Husserl doesn’t seem to fear the moral relativism or even the moral disorderFootnote 35 that such a claim could imply, seemingly considering that love is always “right”.Footnote 36 A more developed phenomenological analytic of love might nonetheless be required in order to support this assumption.

Scheler on the Antagonism between Maternal Instinct and Maternal Love

It is precisely while thoroughly elaborating a phenomenology of affectivity—and of love, in particular—in his Nature of Sympathy (first published in 1913 with the more precise title Zur Phänomenologie und Theorie der Sympathiegefühle und von Liebe und Hass (Phenomenology and Theory of Sympathy Feelings and of Love and Hatred)) that Scheler notably focuses on the mother–child relationship. In fact, it is the peculiarity of maternal love that draws his attention, insofar as it is a feeling that spans between the blindness of instinct and the conscious valuation of the beloved, and thus concerns the very transformation of blind affects into valuative affects.

First of all, given that “the bond between mother and child (der Konnex zwischen Mutter und Kind)” appears as “the typical case of identification (Einsfühlung),” the reference to maternal love allows Scheler to question and reject “the identification-theory of love, i.e., the formula that ‘love’ of another consists in assimilating the other’s self into one’s own by means of identification (Aufnahme des Ich dieses anderen ins eigene Ich durch Einsfühlung)”. Just like Husserl will do, Scheler pays special attention to the intercorporeality of pregnancy that this bond lies upon most of the times and which presents us with a “special, unique case in which the loved one really was once a spatial, corporeal (körperlich-räumlich) ‘part’ of the one who loves” (Scheler, 1973a: 37, GW 7; Scheler, 2008: 25). Yet, he firmly rejects Eduard von Hartmann’s claim that love is “just an extended form of egoism, or (more reasonably), an extension of the instinct of self-preservation beyond the immediate self (eine Ausdehnung des Egoismus oder (sinnvoller) des Selbsterhaltungstriebes über das eigene Ich hinaus),” and thus, “an ‘enlarged form of egoism’ extending to what was once part of the mother’s own body (Teil des eigenen Leibes)Footnote 37” (Scheler, 1973a: 37 and 192, GW 7; Scheler, 2008: 26 and 193). Love is neither primarily nor ultimately directed toward oneself, but is always essentially love of the other, love of another person; that is to say that narcissistic love is not true love.

This is one of the important reasons why the transition from instinct to love cannot be as smooth as Husserl might think. Scheler considers, indeed, that “there is no sort of continuous development from self-preservation (and its impulses) into maternal love. The psychic continuity lies, rather, between the reproductive and parental instincts (Fortpflanzungsinstinkt und Brutpflegeinstinkt)” (Scheler, 1973a: 38, GW 7; Scheler, 2008: 26f.). And even when the fundamental instincts of the living being are at stake, Scheler acknowledges an “antagonism” between self-preservation and reproduction (antagonism that can lead, for instance, to abortion or infanticide). The gap between instinct and love is then even more profound, since maternal love, as it exemplarily manifests itself in self-devotion and self-sacrifice, is not selfish (or narcissistic), but “ecstatic”Footnote 38 (Scheler, 1973a: 38, GW 7; Scheler, 2008: 27), thus expressing the mother’s intrinsic openness to the otherness of her child. What is more, while also paying attention to pregnancy and to the the biological dimension of procreation, Scheler refuses to derive maternal love from the physiological aspects of motherhood and to regard it as the ultimate expression of an innate biological instinct. And even if he sometimes argues for a “gradual transformation of the parental instinct into the conscious sentiment of mother-love (kontinuierlicher Übergang des Brutpflegeinstinktes in seelisch betonte Mutter-liebe),” (Scheler, 1973a: 37, GW 7; Scheler, 2008: 25) he also considers that “the continuity between the parental instincts and what we are first entitled to call mother-love is not so complete as is often asserted”. For here as well, an antagonism can occur, which means that “instinct and love very often run counter to one another (Instinkt und Liebe hier sehr häufig einander entgegenarbeiten)” (Scheler, 1973a: 38, GW 7; Scheler, 2008: 27).

This is undoubtedly one of Scheler’s most precious insights into mother love: to consider that the very essence of love, remarkably present in maternal love, goes against instinct; and that the tendency toward the identification (Einsfühlung) with the child which is specific to maternal instinct is contradicted by mother love.Footnote 39 Suggesting that mothers can and even must move from instinct to love—that is, from the tendency to identification with their offspring toward the valuing of the child as an autonomous person –, he contends that “the unremitting solicitude (die unaufhörlichen Fürsorglichkeiten) of those mothers who are most ‘motherly’ in this respect is often a positive hindrance to any kind of independent development of personality in the child, and frequently retards its mental and spiritual growth the more, in seeking to promote its physical welfare,” and he wonders: “Does it not seem as if the purely maternal instinct—unmixed with love—were seeking to draw the child back, as it were, into the protecting womb (als ob der pure—mit Liebe unvermischte—Instinkt der Mutter das Kind am liebsten wieder in den schützenden Leib gleichsam zurücknehmen möchte)?” (Scheler, 1973a: 38, GW 7; Scheler, 2008: 27). By contrast, Scheler insists, “it is maternal love which first checks this tendency, directing itself upon the child as an independent being, slowly making his way from the darkness of mere physical life into the increasing light of consciousness (Erst die Mutter-liebe ist es, die diese Tendenz aufhebt und auf das Kind als selbständiges Wesen hinzielt, das sich langsam aus der Dunkelheit des Organischen zu steigendem Bewußtseinslicht emporarbeitet)” (Scheler, 1973a: 38, GW 7; Scheler, 2008: 27).Footnote 40 Hence, the major resistance to the naturalization of maternal love and to its confusion with instinct and with the tendency toward identification comes from the fact that the mother loves the child as another person and thereby guides her toward self-consciousness and freedom. For Scheler, as A. R. Luther puts it, “love is a metaphysical act” that “discloses a dynamic interpersonal structure,” (Luther, 1972: 12 and 16) and it is as it possesses such a metaphysical, non-naturalizable dimension that maternal love cannot be grounded on a biological condition or propensity. Also, as persons capable of loving, mothers are not irremediably blinded by obscure, irrational instincts, as Kant might have thought: maternal love is not contrary or indifferent to morals.Footnote 41 Scheler resolutely parts with the view of mothers as harmful for the moral development of their child,Footnote 42 and pays attention instead to how, through love and care, mothers can transform their helpless, dependent child that was once “a part of them” into a person. This means—even though Scheler doesn’t explicitly stress this point—that unlike what happens for other kinds of interpersonal love, like erotic love or friendship, the mother loves the child as a person while also leading it to become a person.

Nonetheless, in spite of Scheler’s distinct contention that “the mother’s identification with her child” occurs “in the maternal and parental instinct, not in mother-love (im Falle nicht der Mutterliebe, sondern des Mutter- und Brutpflegeinstinkts)” (Scheler, 1973a: 84, GW 7; Scheler, 2008: 73), his use of concepts is not always perfectly consistent. He also speaks, indeed, of “the instinctive identification of mother-love (instinktive einsfühlende Mutterliebe)” (Scheler, 1973a: 106, GW 7; Scheler, 2008: 97f.), and praises “the ever-watchful parental instinct (den stetig lebendigen Brutpflegeinstinkt)” of the mother that makes her wake “at the slightest sound from her child (but not in response to much stronger stimuli from other sources)"Footnote 43 (Scheler, 1973a: 39, GW 7; Scheler, 2008: 28). By doing this, Scheler clearly continues to believe in the “intuitive psycho-somatic unity (vorbewusste vitalpsychische Einheit) of mother and child” (Scheler, 1973a: 39, GW 7; Scheler, 2008: 28), and doesn’t really allow imagining that this unity could be broken, deficient or even nonexistent (like in the case of post-partial depression or abusive mothers). He also weakens the separation between maternal love and maternal instinctFootnote 44 by seeing in the mother’s instinctive identification with the child the ground that radically distinguishes mother love from father love and hinders parental love from being homogeneous and unequivocal. The father is considered, indeed, to lack the instinctive power of identification with the child: it is for this reason, Scheler believes, that “we do not have a Vaterliebe (father-love) corresponding to Mutterliebe (mother-love); the word ‘father-love’ actually leaves us in doubt as to whether the father is the loving or the loved one, whereas ‘mother-love’ is absolutely definite in referring to the mother’s love for her child” (Scheler, 1973a: 173, GW 7; Scheler, 2008: 172). There is a strong assumption here that deserves to be highlighted: namely, that before even hoping for reciprocity,Footnote 45mothers have to love first.Footnote 46 Should “the ‘family’ as a whole [be] a fabric built out of love (ein Bauwerk der Liebe)” (Scheler, 1973a: 193, GW 7; Scheler, 2008: 194), in Scheler’s view it is always the mother who loves first and provides the fuel for this love community.Footnote 47

Conclusion: The Unexpected Convergence of Two Complementary Accounts

Husserl undoubtedly meets Scheler here, since he also speaks of family—more precisely (and the precision is not negligible) of “normal family”—as a “community of love” (Husserl, 2014: 512, Hua XLII).Footnote 48 Nonetheless, given that Husserl’s account of the mother–child relationship is mainly developed out of a concern with the genesis and forms of intersubjective relations rather than with the modalities of affectivity, he doesn’t provide us with an analysis of maternal love as developed as Scheler’s. His treatment of the mother–child relationship might appear though as more systematic—insofar as it is commanded by the more general concerns with the “generative connection” of subjectivities and with the teleological development of drive intentionality—, but it is also less attentive to its empirical variations and modulations. The two phenomenologists also polarize the mother–child relationship in a different manner when they approach it: Husserl’s descriptions focus most often on the child as an emerging subjectivity, while Scheler’s are rather primarily concerned with the mother as a loving subject. Also, Husserl does not strive to separate mother love from maternal instinct,Footnote 49 as he more willingly pleads for a continuity between drives and feelings which is an important sequence of the teleological unity of subjective life. However, whereas Scheler draws a sharper distinction between drives or instincts and feelings, insisting even on their potential antagonism, Husserl attempts to emancipate instinct from a mere biological or naturalistic meaning, as he assigns it quite a crucial role in his analysis of intersubjectivity, hence progressively inscribing it within a transcendental horizon. The Freiburg phenomenologist also leads further the ethical potentialities of maternal love, by regarding it as a paradigm for ethical behavior, while in Scheler’s view, maternal love doesn’t seem to fulfill the ultimate conditions of moral action by itself: “In all endeavour there is a content to be realized, which is inherent as its goal (or ‘purpose;’ when we will). Love does not have this at all. What does a mother seek to ‘realize (realisieren)’ when she gazes lovingly at her bonny child asleep?” (Scheler, 1973a: 146, GW 7; Scheler, 2008: 141). Also, when Scheler recalls that “Kant […] excluded love from the whole field of morally valuable conduct because it cannot be imposed as a duty, and because he thought it possible to base the concept of moral value upon obligation and duty alone” (Scheler, 1973a: 146, GW 7; Scheler, 2008: 141)Footnote 50, he seems to remain skeptical himself toward the idea of “duties of love (Liebespflichten),” which is so important in Husserl’s late ethics: he is, for instance, particularly sensitive to the fact that “love does not necessarily lead to goodwill and good-doing. One can also become angry, and hurt another out of love,” since “love is directed not to the well-being of someone but to the highest value of his person” (Scheler, 1954: 232, GW 2; Scheler, 1973b: 225). Also, in spite of their “common [Brentanian] matrix,” (Venier, 2015: 250) Husserl’s conception of “values of love (Liebeswerte)” is more attentive to the uniqueness of individual situations and moral conflicts than Scheler’s account, who still believes that, albeit their resistance to intellectualization,Footnote 51 values can be objectively ranked. In this regard, Scheler’s realism with respect to values implies a closer proximity toward Brentano’s ethics of the higher practical Good, which finds itself firmly rejected by Husserl after the Great War.

These important divergences must not overshadow, though, the fact that there is also a “profound theoretical vicinity between Husserl and Scheler,” (Venier, 2015: 250) which explains the proximity of their two pioneering phenomenological accounts of the mother–child relationship that seem to have been developed in an entirely independent manner. In effect, they both use the reference to this peculiar relationship as a guiding thread and tend to consider it as a paradigm, be it for a phenomenology of intersubjectivity (Husserl) or for a phenomenology of affectivity (Scheler), and they also both closely reinforce the ties between axiological consciousness and affective consciousness, providing the foundations of a new, personalist and yet non-formalist ethics.Footnote 52 Here, their common debt to Brentano reflects itself in their shared criticism of Kant’s view on ethics and affectivity.

A focus on Husserl’s and Scheler’s common attention to specific intersubjective situations like the mother–child relationship can also contribute to showing to what extent the proximity between Scheler and Heidegger (a rapprochement suggested and encouraged by Husserl himself,Footnote 53 and still present in contemporary readings)Footnote 54 is, to some regards, only apparent and even profoundly misleading: Heidegger’s analytic of Dasein clearly confronts us with an empirical underdetermination of the existential of being-with (Mitsein), which is approached, in Sein und Zeit, § 26, without using any particular guiding phenomenon and without prominently putting forth paradigmatic forms of togetherness.Footnote 55 It is also difficult to deny that Heidegger’s analytic of affectivity, quite little concerned with interpersonal feelings, would hardly allow developing a phenomenology of (interpersonal) love.Footnote 56 That is to say that, when the phenomenology of intersubjectivity and affectivity is at stake, Husserl and Scheler are far closer to one another than (they might have) expected.