Skip to main content
Log in

Common Ground in Non-face-to-face Communication: In Sensu Diviso or In Sensu Composito

  • Published:
Journal of Philosophical Logic Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Traditional definitions of common ground in terms of iterative de re attitudes do not apply to conversations where at least one conversational participant is not acquainted with the other(s). I propose and compare two potential refinements of traditional definitions based on Abelard’s distinction between generality in sensu composito and in sensu diviso.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Availability of data and materials

This declaration is not applicable.

References

  1. Akkoyunlu, E. A., Ekanadham, K., & Huber, R. V. (1975). Some constraints and tradeoffs in the design of network communications. SIGOPS Operating Systems Review, 9(5), 67–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Allan, K. (2013). What is common ground? In A. Capone, F. L. Piparo, & M. Carapezza (Eds.), Perspectives on linguistic pragmatics (pp. 285–310). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  3. Allan, K. (2023). The interdependence of common ground and context. In I. Kecskes (Ed.), Common ground in first language and intercultural interaction (pp. 7–25). De Gruyter.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  4. Bach, K., & Harnish, R. M. (1979). Linguistic communication and speech acts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Barwise, J. (1988). Three views of common knowledge. In Proceedings of the 2nd conference on theoretical aspects of reasoning about knowledge, TARK ’88, San Francisco, CA, USA (pp. 365–379). Morgan Kaufmann Publishers Inc.

  6. Bermúdez, J. L. (2003). Thinking without words. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  7. Braithwaite, R. B. (1932). The nature of believing. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 33(1), 129–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Brandenburger, A., & Dekel, E. (1987). Common knowledge with probability 1. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 16(3), 237–245.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  9. Clark, H. H., & Marshall, C. R. (1981). Definite reference and mutual knowledge. In A. K. Joshi, B. L. Webber, & I. A. Sag (Eds.), Elements of discourse understanding (pp. 10–63). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Cohen, D., & Yemini, Y. (1979). Protocols for dating coordination. In Proceedings of the fourth Berkeley conference on distributed data management and computer networks (pp. 179–188). Lawrence Berkeley Laboratory.

  11. Cresswell, M. J., & Von Stechow, A. (1982). “De re’’ belief generalized. Linguistics and Philosophy, 5(4), 503–535.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Eckardt, R. (2014). The semantics of free indirect discourse. Leiden: Brill Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Fagin, R., Halpern, J., Moses, Y., & Vardi, M. (1995). Reasoning about knowledge. Cambridge, MA, USA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Fagin, R., Halpern, J. Y., Moses, Y., & Vardi, M. Y. (1999). Common knowledge revisited. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 96(1), 89–105.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  15. Friedell, M. F. (1969). On the structure of shared awareness. Behavioral Science, 14(1), 28–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Geurts, B. (1997). Communication as commitment sharing: Speech acts, implicatures, common ground. Theoretical Linguistics, 45(1–2), 1–30.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Geurts, B. (2020). Common ground as a normative condition. Manuscript. https://www.academia.edu/43209457/Common_ground_as_a_normative_condition.

  18. Goldstein, S., Domenico, C., & Kirk-Giannini,. (2022). Contextology. Philosophical Studies, 179(11), 3187–3209.

  19. Gray, J. N. (1978). Notes on data base operating systems. In R. Bayer, R. M. Graham, & G. Seegmüller (Eds.), Operating systems: An advanced course (pp. 393–481). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  20. Halpern, J. Y., & Moses, Y. (1990). Knowledge and common knowledge in a distributed environment. Journal of the ACM, 37(3), 549–587.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  21. Harris, D. W. (2020). We talk to people, not contexts. Philosophical Studies, 177(9), 2713–2733.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Heal, J. (1978). Common knowledge. The Philosophical Quarterly, 28(111), 116–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Jeshion, R. (2010). Singular thought: Acquaintance, semantic instrumentalism, and cognitivism. In R. Jeshion (Ed.), New essays on singular thought (pp. 105–141). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  24. Kaplan, D. (1968). Quantifying in. Synthese, 19(1–2), 178–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Kölbel, M. (2011). Conversational score, assertion, and testimony. In J. Brown & H. Cappelen (Eds.), Assertion: New philosophical essays (pp. 49–77). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  26. Lederman, H. (2014). A theory of common ground. PhD thesis, Oxford University.

  27. Lewis, D. (1969). Convention: A philosophical study. Cambridge, MA, USA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Lewis, D. (1979). Attitudes de dicto and de se. The Philosophical Review, 88(4), 513–543.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Maier, E. (2009). Iterated de re: A new puzzle for the relational report semantics. In A. Riester, & T. Solstad (Eds.), Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 13 (pp. 347–355).

  31. Maier, E., & Semeijn, M. (2021). Extracting fictional truth from unreliable sources. In E. Maier & A. Stokke (Eds.), The language of fiction (pp. 186–220). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  32. Meggle, G. (2003). Common belief and common knowledge. In M. Sintonen, P. Ylikoski, & K. Miller (Eds.), Realism in action: Essays in the philosophy of the social sciences (pp. 251–258). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  33. Meyer, J. J. C., & van der Hoek, W. (1995). Epistemic logic for AI and computer science. Cambridge Tracts in Theoretical Computer Science. Cambridge University Press.

  34. Monderer, D., & Samet, D. (1989). Approximating common knowledge with common beliefs. Games and Economic Behavior, 1(2), 170–190.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  35. Panangaden, P., & Taylor, K. (1998). Concurrent common knowledge: Defining agreement for asynchronous systems. Distributed Computing, 6, 73–93.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  36. Quine, W. V. O. (1956). Quantifiers and propositional attitudes. Journal of Philosophy, 53(5), 177–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. Recanati, F. (2009). Singular thought: In defense of acquaintance. In R. Jeshion (Ed.), New essays on singular thought (pp. 141–188). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Rendsvig, R., & Symons, J. (2019). Epistemic logic. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, Summer 2019 edition.

  39. Schiffer, S. (1972). Meaning. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Semeijn, M. (2017). A Stalnakerian analysis of metafictive statements. In Proceedings of the 21st Amsterdam colloquium. ILLC.

  41. Semeijn, M. (2021). Fiction and common ground. A workspace account. PhD thesis, University of Groningen.

  42. Stalnaker, R. (2014). Context. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  43. Stalnaker, R. C. (1968). A theory of conditionals. In N. Rescher (Ed.), Studies in logical theory: American philosophical quarterly monograph series 2 (Vol. 6, pp. 98–112). Blackwell Publishers Ltd., Oxford.

  44. Stalnaker, R. C. (1970). Pragmatics. Synthese, 22(1–2), 272–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  45. Stalnaker, R. C. (1978). Assertion. In P. Cole (Ed.), Pragmatics (Vol. 9, pp. 315–32). New York Academic Press, New York.

  46. Stalnaker, R. C. (1984). Inquiry. Cambridge, MA, USA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Stalnaker, R. C. (2002). Common ground. Linguistics and Philosophy, 25(5–6), 701–721.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  48. Stinchcombe, M. (1988). Approximate common knowledge. Mimeograph. San Diego: University of California.

  49. Stokke, A. (2013). Lying and asserting. Journal of Philosophy, 110(1), 33–60.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  50. van Ditmarsch, H., van Eijck, J., & Verbrugge, R. (2009). Common knowledge and common belief. In J. van Eijck & R. Verbrugge (Eds.), Discourses on social software, texts in logic and games (pp. 99–122). Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Vanderschraaf, P., & Sillari, G. (2014). Common knowledge. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, spring 2014 edition.

  52. Williams, J. R. G. (2021). Publicity and common commitment to believe. Erkenntnis, 88(3), 1059–1080.

    Article  MathSciNet  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  53. Zucchi, A. (2021). On the generation of content. In E. Maier & A. Stokke (Eds.), The language of fiction (pp. 107–130). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

This research is supported by the Netherlands Organisation for Scientific Research (NWO): Vidi grant 276-80-004 (Emar Maier) and Rubicon grant Let’s stop talking about Holmes (Merel Semeijn).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

This declaration is not applicable.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Merel Semeijn.

Ethics declarations

Competing interests

There are no competing interests.

Ethical Approval

This declaration is not applicable.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

I thank Emar Maier, two anonymous Amsterdam Colloquium reviewers, and two anonymous Journal of Philosophical Logic reviewers for valuable comments that helped improve the paper. This research is supported by the Netherlands Organisation for Scientific Research (NWO): Vidi grant 276-80-004 (Emar Maier) and Rubicon grant Let’s stop talking about Holmes (Merel Semeijn).

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Semeijn, M. Common Ground in Non-face-to-face Communication: In Sensu Diviso or In Sensu Composito. J Philos Logic (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-024-09744-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-024-09744-9

Keywords

Navigation