Skip to main content
Log in

Consumer-side reference through promiscuous memory traces

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

What fixes the referents of episodic memories? While developed theories are lacking, it is generally assumed that the causal production of a memory, via memory traces, determines its referent. Recently, it has been pointed out that the “promiscuity” of memory traces poses a problem for this approach. Proposed solutions focus on finding some nonpromiscuous causal link. In this paper, I refine the problem posed by promiscuous memory traces and show that these solutions fail. By developing the question of mnemonic episodic reference within the framework of informational signs, I argue that no pure “producer-side” theory of reference will work. The only solution, I argue, is to abandon pure producer-side theories for theories which appeal to consumer-side factors, i.e., factors concerning how referring signs are used. Once it is admitted that mnemonic episodic reference depends on consumer-side factors, the natural question is whether producer-side factors (i.e., causal production) play any role at all in mnemonic episodic reference. I conclude by outlining two possible pure consumer-side theories for mnemonic episodic reference, one based on the work of Imogen Dickie and one based on the work of Ruth Millikan. Both theories explain how the referents of episodic memories are fixed without any appeal to a causal link, and, hence, are compatible with “post-causal” theories of memory, like simulationism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I will use the term “memory” to refer to mental states tokened when recalling, i.e., remembering, an event, and not to refer to any latent storage of past information, e.g., a memory trace. Presumably the same memory can be tokened on different occasions, albeit with changes due to information addition and loss.

  2. The relevant description perhaps includes not just what’s described explicitly, but also descriptive content implied by context, or associated in my mind with the linguistic description.

  3. Thanks to an anonymous referee for suggesting this approach.

  4. I do not intend the above as a knock-down refutation of a description theory of mnemonic episodic reference. It’s just meant to point out that a description theory is not an obvious choice. For a recent critique of description theories of reference for public language terms, see Gómez-Torrente (2019).

  5. Andonovski (2020) turns these worries about promiscuity, along with other lines of attack, into an argument against the very idea, presupposed by this paper, that episodic memories are referentially singular, i.e., refer to particular past-perceived events.

  6. Raatikainen (2020) provides a broad discussion of challenges to the causal theory of reference and the debate between it and the description theory.

  7. Both the notion of a sign and the notion of information have been the subject of rich theoretical development, including by the aforementioned philosophers and continuing today (e.g., Fresco et al., 2020). In my explication here, I aim to be precise about what I mean, without any pretension that I’m giving a complete account of either signs or information which fully engages with all the concerns in this theoretical literature. Further, I do not want to commit to the full details of any one view from this literature, as such a commitment would both take substantive space to explain and defend, and entangle me in debates not obviously relevant to the purpose at hand. In addition, these views don’t generally engage with the concerns of a causal theory of reference, a concern which requires articulating, as I do here, the distinct notion of a signal stream.

  8. This resistance to regimentation is a problem for causal theories of reference, but not for my aims here. I believe that this resistance hints at deeper conceptual issues to such theories and is just more reason to adopt alternatives, such as the consumer-side theories discussed in Sect. 5.

  9. Evans seems to hold this view, too. He’s not explicit about it. However, when he talks about memory as part of an information channel (e.g., Evans, 1982, p. 267), he talks about it as a mechanism for “retaining” information.

  10. This point must be stated carefully. As I’ll discuss in Sect. 3, contemporary causal theorists of all types often accept that memory is constructive. That is, they accept that, on retrieval, a trace can be combined with other sources of information (not causally originating in the same event) to form a memory, and that information can be lost within a trace over time.

  11. Both Robins and Langland-Hassan point out that very new memories won’t face this problem. For example, the first time you go to a party serving wine will form a new connection, party–wine, which will be unique to this event. However, this connection will become promiscuous as soon as you go to a second party with wine, leading to “forgetting through repetition”. Still, even here, the memory will involve some promiscuous trace, unless everything about the event is novel.

  12. Both Robins (2016b) and Najenson (2021) argue that work on optogenetic manipulates of memory (e.g., Abdou et al., 2018; Ramirez et al., 2013) provides evidence against this more radical version of constructivism.

  13. Thanks for an anonymous referee for pressing this issue.

  14. Shea (2018) questions whether neural circuitry can be divided cleanly into distinct producer and consumer systems and memory circuits might be a good example case, but a clean division of the systems themselves isn’t crucial for my points.

  15. The basic idea that hippocampal traces interact with traces in neocortex to facilitate the construction of episodic memories is standard in theories of memory traces (Sekeres et al., 2018). What sets CRISP apart is in holding that hippocampal traces are stable and persistent, instead of merely being transient and faciliating consolidation of stable traces in neocortex.

  16. For example, this forking could happen right at the memory itself. The memory might be produced from a single retained, nonpromiscuous episodic trace, but still involve a stream fork if additional information from generic or semantic memory traces is added in the retrieval of the memory.

  17. The name “unicept” is a play on the term “concept”. Millikan thinks concepts, as traditionally understand, wrongly subsume the distinct functions of unitrackers and unicepts. So, unicepts are like traditional concepts, minus the recognitional capacities.

  18. Evans (1982, p. 125) himself suggests an epistemic theory, but elsewhere clearly seems to intend signal stream traceback to play a role in fixing reference, thereby making his view a hybrid theory. He has further constraints on reference, namely, the constraint that the mode of identification used must successfully pick out the stream target, thereby allowing the subject to know which thing they are thinking about (Evans, 1982, p. 139). Dickie (2015) has developed a well-known version of the epistemic approach in terms of reliability, while Recanati (2012) has developed a broader epistemic formulation, with hybrid elements, in terms of “epistemically rewarding” relations and dominant causal sources of information.

  19. The obvious difference is that these streams go back to multiple events, and that some of them do not go back to the tracked event at all. However, the basic idea of tracking a single event through multiple streams remains.

  20. An anonymous referee suggests that, in this case, it seems I’d be even more unlucky if some other events, the true distal causal antecedents of my traces, did not match my memory. Thus, wouldn’t those end up being the true referent of my memory, on this theory? I think this objection is a second form of pessimism for the epistemic approach, although it’s not obviously fatal. If I use a wide range of traces, each with a wide range of distal causal antecedents, to reconstruct my crash, the way I intermix these traces to reconstruct the crash may make it very unlikely that the resulting memory matches any of those distal causal antecedents any better than the crash.

  21. Some have argued against the view that the circuits responsible for episodic memory function to reconstruct specific past-perceived events. For example, Schechtman (1994) argues that they function to produce coherent autobiographical narratives, while De Brigard (2014) argues that their true value is more broadly in how they enable hypothetical thinking.

  22. Thanks to an anonymous referee for suggesting this approach.

References

  • Abdou, K., Shehata, M., Choko, K., Nishizono, H., & Matsuo, M. (2018). Synapse-specific representation of the identity of overlapping memory engrams. Science, 360(6394), 1227–1231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andonovski, N. (2020). SINGULARISM about episodic memory. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 11(2), 335–365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barkasi, M. (2021). Are there epistemic conditions necessary for demonstrative thought? Synthese, 198(7), 6111–6138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barry, D. N., & Maguire, E. A. (2019). Remote memory and the hippocampus: A constructive critique. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 23(2), 128–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Basu, J., & Siegelbaum, S. A. (2015). The corticohippocampal circuit, synaptic plasticity, and memory. Cold Spring Harbor Perspectives in Biology, 5, a021733.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernecker, S. (2008). The metaphysics of memory. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bernecker, S. (2010). Memory: A philosophical study. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheng, S. (2013). The crisp theory of hippocampal function in episodic memory. Frontiers in Neural Circuits, 7(88), 1–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheng, S., & Werning, M. (2016). What is episodic memory if it is a natural kind? Synthese, 193, 1345–1385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Brigard, F. (2014). Is memory for remembering? Recollection as a form of episodic hypothetical thinking. Synthese, 191, 155–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (1981). Designation. Columbia University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dickie, I. (2015). Fixing reference. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Donnellan, K. S. (1970). Proper names and identifying descriptions. Synthese, 21(3–4), 335–358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1981). Knowledge and the flow of information. The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1988). Explaining behavior: Reasons in a World of causes. The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1982). Varieties of reference. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, D. E. (2012). The spike-timing dependence of plasticity. Neuron, 75, 556–571.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1966 [1892]). On sense and reference. In P. Geach and M. Black (Eds.), Translations from the philosophical writings of Gottlob Frege (2nd ed., pp. 56–78). Basil Blackwell.

  • Fresco, N., Ginsburg, S., & Jablonka, E. (2020). Functional information: A graded taxonomy of difference makers. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 11, 547–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Geach, P. (1969). The perils of Pauline. Review of Metaphysics, 23(2), 287–300.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gómez-Torrente, M. (2019). Roads to reference: An essay on reference fixing in natural language. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, M. B. (2013). Recall of spatial patterns stored in a hippocampal slice by long-term potentiation. Journal of Neurophysiology, 110, 2511–2519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1962/1892). Psychology: Briefer course. Collier Books.

  • Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laird, J. (1920). A study in realism. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langland-Hassan, P. (2022). Propping up the causal theory. Synthese, 200(95), 1–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langland-Hassan, P. (2023). Remembering and imagining: The attitudinal continuity. In A. Berninger & I. Vendrell Ferran (Eds.), Philosophical perspectives on memory and imagination (pp. 11–34). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. G. F. (2001). Out of the past: Episodic recall as retained acquaintance. In C. Hoerl & T. McCormack (Eds.), Time and memory (pp. 257–284). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C. B., & Deutscher, M. (1966). Remembering. Philosophical Review, 75(2), 161–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, M. (2010). Is memory preservation? Philosophical Studies, 148, 3–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian, K. (2011). Generative memory. Philosophical Psychology, 24(3), 323–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian, K. (2016). Mental time travel: Episodic memory and our knowledge of the personal past. The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian, K. (2022). Radicalizing simulationism: Remembering as imagining the (nonpersonal) past. Philosophical Psychology. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2022.2082934

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michaelson, E., & Reimer, M. (2022). Reference. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2022). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (1984). Language, thought and other biological categories. The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (2004). Varieties of meaning: The 2002 Jean Nicod lectures. The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (2017). Beyond concepts: Unicepts, language, and natural information. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Misra, P., Marconi, A., Peterson, M., & Kreiman, G. (2018). Minimal memory for details in real life events. Scientific Reports, 8(1), 16701.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Najenson, J. (2021). What have we learned about the engram? Synthese, 199, 9581–9601.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neisser, U. (1981). John Dean’s memory: A case study. Cognition, 9(1), 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Openshaw, J. & Michaelian, K. (forthcoming). Reference in remembering: Towards a simulationist account. Synthese.

  • Perrin, D. (2021). Embodied episodic memory: A new case for causalism? Intellectica, 74, 229–252.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raatikainen, P. (2020). Theories of reference: What was the question? In A. Bianchi (Ed.), Language and reality from a naturalistic perspective: Themes from Michael Devitt (pp. 69–103). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Raftopoulos, A., & Müller, V. (2006). Nonconceptual demonstrative reference. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 72(2), 251–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ramirez, S., Liu, X., Lin, P.-A., Suh, J., Pignatelli, M., Redondo, R. L., Ryan, T. J., & Tonegawa, S. (2013). Creating a false memory in the hippocampus. Science, 341(6144), 387–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2007). Perspectival thought: A plea for moderate relativism. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2012). Mental files. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Robins, S. (2016). Representing the past: Memory traces and the causal theory of memory. Philosophical Studies, 173, 2993–3013.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robins, S. K. (2016). Optogenetics and the mechanism of false memory. Synthese, 193, 1561–1583.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robins, S. K. (2020). Stable engrams and neural dynamics. Philosophy of Science, 87(5), 1130–1139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1911). Knowledge by acquaintance and knowledge by description. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 11, 108–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scarantino, A. (2015). Information as a probabilistic difference maker. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 93(3), 419–443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schacter, D. L., & Addis, D. R. (2007). The cognitive neuroscience of constructive memory: Remembering the past and imagining the future. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 362(1481), 773–786.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schechtman, M. (1994). The truth about memory. Philosophical Psychology, 7, 3–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sekeres, M. J., Winocur, G., & Moscovitch, M. (2018). The hippocampus and related neocortical structures in memory transformation. Neuroscience Letters, 680, 39–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shannon, C. (1948). A mathematical theory of communication. Bell System Technical Journal, 27(379–423), 623–656.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shea, N. (2018). Representation in cognitive science. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sinclair, A. H., Manalili, G. M., Brunec, I. K., Adcock, R. A., & Barense, M. D. (2021). Prediction errors disrupt hippocampal representations and update episodic memories. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 118(51), e2117625118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Soteriou, M. (2018). The past made present: Mental time travel in episodic recollection. In K. Michaelian, D. Debus, & D. Perrin (Eds.), New directions in the philosophy of memory. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sugar, J., & Moser, M.-B. (2019). Episodic memory: Neuronal codes for what, where, and when. Hippocampus, 29(12), 1190–1205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, J. (1998). Philosophy and memory traces: Descartes to connectionism. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tulving, E. (1972). Episodic and semantic memory. In E. Tulving & W. Donaldson (Eds.), Organization of memory (pp. 381–403). Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Werning, M. (2020). Predicting the past from minimal traces: Episodic memory and its distinction from imagination and preservation. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 11, 301–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Xiao, X., Dong, Q., Gao, J., Men, W., Poldrack, R. A., & Xue, G. (2017). Transformed neural pattern reinstatement during episodic memory retrieval. Journal of Neuroscience, 37(11), 2986–2998.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zylberberg, J., & Strowbridge, B. W. (2017). Mechanisms of persistent activity in cortical circuits: Possible neural substrates for working memory. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 40, 603–627.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to James Openshaw for extensive comments and discussion. Thanks also to the participants of the Bochum-Grenoble Memory Colloquium (April 12, 2022) and the Centre for Philosophy of Memory’s internal seminar (July 25, 2022), at which early versions of this material were presented. The two referees from this journal also provided helpful feedback which substantially improved the quality of the paper and pushed it in very productive directions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael Barkasi.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Barkasi, M. Consumer-side reference through promiscuous memory traces. Synthese 203, 86 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-024-04509-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-024-04509-y

Keywords

Navigation