Skip to main content
Log in

James Rachels and the morality of euthanasia

  • Article
  • Published:
Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

My fundamental thesis is that Rachels dismisses the traditional Western account of the morality of killing without offering a viable replacement. In this regard, I will argue that the substitute account he offers is deficient in at least eight regards: (1) he fails to justify the foundational principle of utilitarianism, (2) he exposes preference utilitarianism to the same criticisms he lodges against classical utilitarianism, (3) he neglects to explain how precisely one performs the maximization procedure which preference utilitarianism requires, (4) his account of the sanctity of life is subject to the very criticism he levels against the traditional position, (5) he cannot justify the exceptions he makes to his interpretation of the sanctity of life, (6) his account could easily be used to justify murder, (7) his embrace of autonomy as an ethical principle undermines his preference utilitarianism, and (8) he cannot maintain the moral identification of acts of killing and letting die.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The term ‘euthanasia’ as it is used in this paper will refer to the intended acts of killing a person that are performed at his or her behest, by someone other than that person. In particular, I will not examine the question of whether there is a meaningful moral difference between ‘physician assisted suicide’ or ‘medical aid in dying’ and euthanasia. Nor will I consider whether those in a persistent vegetative state or other incapacitated patients are persons, but instead will focus on the euthanizing of those who are deemed persons by all sides in the euthanasia debate. Nor will I attempt to specify which acts of killing are ‘active’ or ‘passive,’ or which means of life support or medical care are ‘ordinary’ or ‘extraordinary.’ It will only examine those acts acknowledged by all to be active means of procuring death.

  2. As is well known, utilitarian ethical theory is not homogeneous. For a good overview of the various schools of utilitarian thought see [1,2,3,4,5,6,7].

  3. Rachels’ article “Active and Passive Euthanasia,” first published in 1975, has had a significant influence on the field and has been widely anthologized and cited over 1200 times since its publication. See [8]. In addition, Rachels published two influential textbooks and anthologies which have had a significant influence on the turn from meta-ethics to more concrete ethical questions and which have sold several hundred thousand copies over the last 50 years. See [9, 10]. For a good collection of his later articles see [11]. For a critique of “applied ethics” as a discipline see [12].

  4. On classical utilitarianism and the development of preference utilitarianism see [13,14,15,16,17,18,19,20,21].

  5. For similar critiques of the sanctity of life account see [23,24,25,26]. For a critique of Singer on this point [27]. For a defense of the sanctity or inviolability of life approach see [28,29,30,31,32,33]. On the concept of dignity see [34,35,36].

  6. See [22, p. 6]. For a defense of a theologically centered approach see [37]. For a helpful analysis of Ramsey’s work see [38]. On the concept of harm see [39,40,41,42,43,44,45,46,47,48].

  7. On Schweitzer’s moral philosophy see [49,50,51].

  8. On this point see as well [52, 53]. On dignity and the ‘value of life’ see [54,55,56].

  9. Rachels critique here is similar to J.J.C. Smart’s well known critique of rule utilitarianism. See [57].

  10. On the concept of harm see as well [58,59,60,61,62].

  11. For an attempt to defend the utilitarian tradition from this type of criticism see [63].

  12. On this point see as well [64].

  13. On this point see as well [65]. For a response to Seay see [66, 67].

  14. In addition, at various points Rachels has argued that active euthanasia may actually be preferable than passive euthanasia: “If one simply withholds treatment, it may take the patient longer to die, and so he may suffer more than he would if more direct action were taken and a lethal injection given... This fact provides strong reason for thinking that, once the initial decision not to prolong his agony has been made, active euthanasia is actually preferable to passive euthanasia, rather than the reverse.” See [10, p. 79]. On this point see as well [68, pp. 281–85].

  15. On this point se as well [69].

  16. For a critique of psychological hedonism see [70].

  17. In particular, Rachels gives the examples of the troubles in Northern Ireland and the unhappiness associated with inter-denominational marriage. See [22, pp. 155–56]. In response, one could easily argue that the conflict in Northern Ireland was driven by profound social and political injustice rather than theological disagreements about scriptural interpretation, ecclesiology, soteriology, sacramental theology, and/or the nature of grace.

  18. On the shift towards preference utilitarianism in the twentieth century see [71].

  19. Unfortunately, Rachels never explains how an agent knows when to abandon reasoning and to defer to intuitions which is another significant gap in his argument.

  20. On this point see as well Rachels’ later paper [72].

  21. For a powerful example of how complicated this dynamic can be see [73].

  22. Significantly, there are times where Rachels supports violating a patients’ preference to die purportedly because dying is not in the patients’ best interests. This teleological approach however conflicts with his preference utilitarian interpretation of interests as being subjectively determined by each individual.

  23. Curiously, in the final chapter of The Elements of Moral Philosophy entitled “What Would a Satisfactory Moral Theory Be Like,” Rachels argues for an eclectic approach that borrows elements from a variety of ethical theories to create what he calls “Multiple-Strategies Utilitarianism:” “At any rate, there is some combination of virtues, motives, and methods of decision making that is best for me, given my circumstances, personality and talents – ‘best’ in the sense that it will optimize the chances of my having a good life, while at the same time optimizing the chances of other people having good lives. Call this optimum combination my best plan. The right thing for me to do is to act in accordance with my best plan” [10, p. 198]. As Christopher Lutz notes, however, “given the range of things that may be included in ‘good lives’ in contemporary culture, coupled with the flexibility of these ‘multiple strategies,’ it is difficult to see how Rachels’s ‘best plan’ differs from the relativism and subjectivism that Rachels had examined and rejected in the opening chapters of his book. The use of ‘multiple strategies’ that rely on contradictory theoretical foundations leaves the appearance that Rachels is teaching students to use the language of ethics to justify whatever decisions they have made, rather than helping them to discover a sound theoretical basis for making their decisions... we should say that Rachels’s ‘attempt to achieve a systematic understanding of the nature of morality and what it requires of us’ has been transformed... into an attempt to understand how to use the terms of morality for our own ends. By the standards set out at the beginning of Rachels’s book, his effort to understand the nature of morality has failed, and it has failed precisely because ‘the nature of morality’ that he investigates is a false subject” [74, pp. 77–78].

  24. For a good collection of articles challenging contemporary utilitarian approaches in contemporary bioethics see [75].

  25. On this point see [76, 77].

  26. For critiques of consequentialism along these lines see [78,79,80].

  27. As Gomez-Lobo notes, “in this case, what is absurd is the conclusion that sometimes one ought to do what is unjust. The conclusion is false because it is a covert contradiction. According to a universally admitted principle of justice (which, as the context shows, Smart implicitly accepts; otherwise he would not feel uneasy), it is always unjust to punish an innocent person. To claim that something is unjust, however, entails that it is something that ought not to be done. To claim simultaneously that it ought to be done generates a logical inconsistency. A way out for an act utilitarian would be to give up on the very idea that the demands of justice always ought to be satisfied. This move has unpalatable consequences however, especially for the innocent victims of injustice. If you and I were in their place, we would also demand that justice be upheld, regardless of consequences” [70, p. 116].

  28. On the ought implies can principle see [81,82,83].

  29. As Williams has argued, many would likely find cold comfort in being told he or she has lived a “moral life” after a lifetime of continual self-abnegation and abandoning everything that was meaningful and significant to us. See [1, pp. 116–117]. For this reason, J.L. Mackie has derided utilitarianism as an “ethics of fantasy.” See [84].

  30. Beauchamp and Childress offer their own example of a researcher who derives great satisfaction from inflicting pain on animals or on human subjects. As they note, this preference should be condemned and prevented from being satisfied. See [85].

  31. As Beauchamp and Childress note, “if an already prosperous group of persons could have more value added to their lives than could be added to the lives of the indigent in society, the utilitarian must recommend that the added value go to the prosperous group” [85, p. 394].

  32. For a defense of secrecy in consequentialism, see [86].

  33. For a defense of partiality see [87].

  34. In this regard, there has been considerable debate amongst utilitarian themselves as to whether one should try to produce the most good (or preference or interest satisfaction), or maximize the median amount of goodness, or some weighted function of the total good, and/or the standard deviation from the mean. For a helpful overview see [88].

  35. As Rachels notes, “Jack’s [the grandson’s] intention was honorable and Jill’s [the granddaughter’s] was not. Could we say on that account that what Jack did was right, but what Jill did was not right? No; for Jack and Jill did the very same thing” [22, p. 93].

  36. As Gomez-Lobo notes, “both a correct and mistaken calculation of the distance to the moon can produce an enjoyable state of consciousness in the astronomer if the mistake goes undetected, but surely there is value in getting it right and disvalue in being wrong, even if in both cases the subjective feeling is the same. One might object that in the long run, errors in astronomy do not produce a net balance of pleasure over pain for the astronomer, but this attitude is odd. It is unclear how the results of astronomical research should be linked to the subjective states of a particular researcher. It seems far more reasonable to say that errors should be avoided in astronomy simply because there is value in attaining astronomical truth as such” [70, p. 31].

  37. For an overview of the common law tradition on this point see [89].

  38. Singer is also uneasy in attributing the injustice involved in acts of murder to the harm suffered by the survivors rather than the victim. As he notes, “there is, of course, something odd about objecting to murder, not because of the wrong done to the victim, but because of the effect that the murder will have on others. One has to be a tough-minded classical utilitarian to be untroubled by this oddness” [21, p. 91]. Significantly, however, the survivors do not feel that the act of murder is wrong because the murderer makes them feel vulnerable. If the murderer is arrested or killed immediately after his or her act, the community still feels that a serious injustice has been perpetrated. For a further defense of the view that harm to the decedent should be central to our condemnation of homicide see [90, 91].

  39. In addition, as J.P. Moreland notes, inferring or knowing someone’s character may be difficult or even impossible for Rachels: “the inseparability of intentions and means in human action can also be seen by asking how it is possible for an action to reveal one’s character. Character is a relatively stable unity or structure of moral virtues that underlies and expresses itself in the moral acts or conduct of the person. A moral virtue is an ingrained habit or disposition of the embodied will. A habit is a disposition is a tendency to act in certain circumstances. Thus character is formed by and an expression of intentional actions. That is why one’s character is revealed by one’s actions and why actions shape character. On Rachel’s Humean analysis, actions are separate from intentions and vice versa. If that is the case, how is it that one can infer character from one’s actions? It would seem that no necessary connection exists” [92, p. 90]. It is interesting to note as well that Beauchamp and Childress have also urged such an approach in thinking through the rule of double effect. As they note, “we suggest that one constructive effort to retain an emphasis on intention without entirely abandoning the larger point of the RDE would focus on the way actions display a person’s motives and character” [85, p. 170].

  40. On this point see the comments of Dan Brock as well: “more important and perplexing, however, is how the necessary calculations can, even in principle, be made and whether the logical foundations necessary to the intelligibility of these calculations exist. Moral philosophers have paid surprisingly little attention to these two problems. Most discussions of utilitarianism in recent books and journals simply assume that it is possible to determine in any situation what is required by utility-maximization, and then go on to consider whether this always coincides with what is required by morality” [93, p. 245].

  41. On this point see [94,95,96].

  42. See [97]. While Rawls’s critique is addressed primarily towards classical hedonistic versions of utilitarianism his critique is also applicable to Rachels’s distinctive version of preference utilitarianism.

  43. With regard to this difficulty, Rachels is certainly not alone. Many other utilitarians, such as Peter Singer and Jonathan Glover, neglect the formidable task of measuring and ranking preferences or interests, as if they can develop normative principles despite this serious obstacle. One utilitarian, L.W. Sumner, might speak for many when he states comparing the utility of life and death: “The further response has been to show, in effect, that we do make such comparisons; therefore they must be possible – somehow or other” [98, p. 167]. This difficulty remains unaddressed in Sumner’s more recent work as well. See [99, 100]. On the problem of measurement see as well [101, 102].

  44. Rachels does not explicitly identify who confers value on life, but in most of his examples he claims the subject of biographical life does. Nevertheless, some ambiguity persists because in one case he supports a family member deciding the fate of a suffering sibling.

  45. See [22, pp. 154–56]. It is precisely this subjective sense of the value of life that John Harris emphasizes. Human beings are more valuable that other beings insofar as they are capable of valuing their own lives, and have the intellectual capacities to do this. According to Harris, the value of life “is the value we give to our lives” and one does this by shaping and forming one’s character through our choices and preferences [103, pp. 8–16]. For a good critique of this approach see [104,105,106]. For a defense of a form of utilitarianism that emphasizes objective well-being see [107]. In the last decade or so, Singer has also moved closer to embracing a more objective form of utilitarianism. On this point see [108].

  46. Here I would argue that something can be in an individual’s interest and thus protected by rights even if that individual does not take an interest in it. The interest need not be conscious or even then accessible to consciousness. On this point see [109].

  47. Rachels, who primarily employs the term “interest” rather than “preference” in his work, criticizes classical utilitarianism for merely trying to maximize happiness without considering an individual’s choice: “even if happiness could be increased in this way, it would be wrong to do so, because people should be allowed to make their own choices” [22, p. 155].

  48. As will be shown, at some point Rachels will have to justify exceptions to his principle, such as killing in self-defense or justified killing in wartime. For a critique of euthanasia as the impermissible killing of the innocent see [110]. On euthanasia as wrongful killing see [111, 112].

  49. Furthermore, Rachels evaluates the worth of Russell’s life in utilitarian terms that he has not justified. He concentrates on Russell’s age and concomitant inability to produce or enjoy much, or what Rachels characterizes as the “possibilities for Russell’s life.” Not only does he employ an unjustified utilitarian framework, he also contradicts the way that society views his life, or at least the intentional termination of his life. This subjectivism seems to plague most “quality of life” theories, which fail to explain society’s disapprobation of murder, regardless of the age of the victim. In addition, as David Wiggins notes, “If we ask what is so good, either absolutely or to me, about my mental life’s flowing on from now into the future, the answer... imports what makes me dear to myself – and with the idea of myself as a continuant [a substance which is a member of the natural kind ‘human being’] with certain moral or other qualities that make me fond of myself” [113, p. 152]. Commenting on this passage, J.P. Moreland and Norman Geisler summarize: “if we ask why biographical life is both possible and morally important, the answer will be that such a life is grounded in the kind of entity, a human being in this case, that typically can have that life. And the natural kind “human being” is not merely a biological notion, but a metaphysical notion which includes moral properties. Human beings have both biological and moral properties and, thus, are objects of intrinsic value simply as humans” [114, pp. 72–73].

  50. Again, because Rachels has explicitly criticized and rejected the traditional western account of the immorality of killing, he cannot use it as a basis when making exceptions to his rule that prohibits killing individuals involuntarily.

  51. On this point see [115].

  52. For a good treatment of the difficulties facing any “quality of life” approach see [116,117,118,119,120,121,122,123,124].

  53. Another difficulty that could be raised here is that Rachel’s biological vs. biographical distinction depends upon a form of Lockean or Cartesian body/self-dualism that is difficult to defend both empirically and metaphysically. A good example of this is Rachels’ claim that it is possible for a bigamist to live two distinct ‘biographical’ lives or that a person might ‘die’ and that their ‘unoccupied’ body might continue to live. This account conceives of persons as essentially minds or spirits that somehow mysteriously inhabit, possess, or occupy living biological organisms. This view also seems to have been held by John Locke. For example, see his discussions of the “Prince and the Cobbler” as well as the “Day Man and the Night Man.” In each of these cases, two distinct persons ‘inhabit’ or ‘occupy’ the same material body at different times. See [125]. Rachels is certainly not alone in holding such a view which has also been adopted (in some cases implicitly) by several others. For examples of contemporary body/self-dualism see [126,127,128,129]. Such an approach has been strongly criticized by Germain Grisez, John Finnis, Robert George, Patrick Lee, and Alfonso Gomez-Lobo amongst others. On this point see [130,131,132,133,134,135]. For a general critique of dualistic approaches see [136,137,138,139,140,141,142,143,144,145,146].

  54. As Leon Kass notes, “truth to tell, the ideal of rational autonomy, so beloved of bioethicists and legal theorists, rarely obtains in actual medical practice. Illness invariably means dependence, and dependence means relying for advice on physician and family. This is especially true with those who are seriously or terminally ill, where is frequently also depression or diminished mental capacity that clouds one’s judgment or weakens one’s mental resolve. With patients thus reduced – helpless in action and ambivalent about life – someone who might benefit from their death need not proceed by overt coercion. Rather, requests for assisted suicide can and will be subtly engineered” [147, p. 24]. On this point see as well [148,149,150,151,152,153,154,155,156,157,158,159,160,161,162]. For an attempt to address and alleviate this concern see [163, 164].

  55. On this conflict see [165].

  56. In addition, even if one does grant that a perfectly autonomous request for euthanasia has been made it is not clear at all how this honors, respects, or affirms someone’s autonomy insofar as it annihilates the very possibility of autonomous agency. As Gomez-Lobo notes, “it is clear that even an allegedly autonomous suicide is a deeply irrational action not only because of the attack on the basic human good of one’s life but because autonomy is turned against itself. Autonomy is exercised to end autonomy. It is a violation of autonomy to destroy autonomy, even autonomously. If autonomy is so valuable, we should not destroy it, either in ourselves or in others” [166, p. 71]. On this point see as well [167].

  57. On intention and side effects see Joseph Boyle: “side-effects are consequences or other aspects of one’s actions which are neither goals one seeks in action nor the precise states of affairs one is committed to realizing for the sake of those goals. They are properly regarded as outside one’s intention in acting because their occurrence does not contribute to one’s purposes; they are not part of what one wants to occur or of what, strictly speaking, serves one’s purposes.” See [168]. Ultimately, this is one of the most important differences underlying the two approaches. On double effect reasoning see [169,170,171,172,173,174,175,176,177,178,179,180,181,182,183,184,185]. For critiques see [186,187,188,189,190,191].

  58. On this point see as well [193,194,195,196,197,198,199,200,201].

  59. For a helpful discussion of the ordinary vs extraordinary and proportionate vs. disproportionate distinctions see [202].

  60. On this point see [203,204,205].

  61. On this point see as well Sullivan’s later response to Rachels [207].

  62. As Aquinas notes, an action is “not good simpliciter unless all the goodnesses concur.” On this point see [208]. As Ralph McInerny notes, “a single human act contains many parts which are only potentially many; some of them actually come to be separate wholes when something goes wrong” [209, p. 69]. On this point see as well [210].

  63. In particular, if the means is not suited or appropriate to the agent’s end, then the real object of his or her will may be disputed, or another end may be indicated. For instance, if someone immediately gave a potentially lethal dosage of morphine, say 300 mg, without titrating the dosage, or if someone used pancuronium bromide instead of morphine, this would likely reveal an intent to kill rather than relieve suffering. On this point see [210, 211].

  64. There are complex and difficult questions here about the nature of intention which cannot be fully addressed in this paper and will have to wait for another time. For Anscombe, what renders an act A and its consequence X intentional then is that an agent (1) has reasons for choosing act A that stem from A’s potential as a cause of X and (2) the agent wants the eventuality X. Anscombe will argue then that intending to do X entails ‘wanting’ to do X, in the motivational sense for which the “primitive sign of wanting is trying to get” [212, p. 68–70].

  65. On the question of omission see as well [213].

  66. I am assuming, of course, that there is no negligence or malice in the design or construction of the road. On this example see [214].

  67. Likewise, as Finnis notes, if this account were true then the choice to take one’s children for a walk rather than flying to Calcutta to care for homeless children would be as murderous as intentionally shooting them dead. See [132, pp. 64–65].

  68. See [215]. A well-known defense of this approach can also be found in [216]. To be fair, Singer’s criterion of comparable importance sets an important limit on sacrifice. There is a need for further argument and specification to establish what counts as a ‘comparable morally important’ good and how such goods may be precisely and accurately measured, quantified, and weighed in practical deliberation. It is not hard to see, however, how the utilitarian focus on maximization could quickly become overly demanding and would lead to actions that would more properly be considered supererogatory.

  69. In this regard, it is important to acknowledge that much of morality is outside the boundary of the law. For instance, gossiping about someone is morally wrong but it is not illegal anywhere. Nonetheless, I think a strong prima facie case can be made here that is implausible and unfair to attribute moral or legal responsibility to all the foreseen consequences of one’s actions.

  70. For a more compelling although still problematic defense see [85, pp. 188–93].

  71. For an overview of current practice in Belgium, the Netherlands, and Canada as well as emerging global trends see [217,218,219].

References

  1. Smart, J.J.C. and Williams, Bernard. 1973. Utilitarianism: For and Against. Eds. J.J.C. Smart and Bernard Williams. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  2. Lyons, David. 1965. Forms and Limits of Utilitarianism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Glover, Jonathan. 1990. Utilitarianism and its Critics, 193–251. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Capaldi, Nicholas. 2004. John Stuart Mill: A Biography. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Schultz, Bart. 2004. Henry Sidgwick—Eye of the Universe: An Intellectual Biography. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Perry, John. 2014. Where did Utilitarianism Come From? In God, the Good, and Utilitarianism: Perspectives on Peter Singer. ed. John Perry. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 15–53.

  7. Schultz, Bart. 2017. The Happiness Philosophers. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Rachels. 1975. Active and Passive Euthanasia. New England Journal of Medicine 292: 78–80.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Rachels. 1971. Moral Problems: A Collection of Philosophical Essays. New York: Harper Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Rachels. 2014. The Elements of Moral Philosophy, 8th ed. New York: McGraw Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Rachels. 2007. The Legacy of Socrates: Essays in Moral Philosophy. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  12. MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1984. Does Applied Ethics Rest on a Mistake? The Monist 67: 498–513.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Bentham. Jeremy. 1996. The Principles of Morals and Legislation. In The Collected Works of Jeremy Bentham. Eds. J.H. Burns and H.L.A Hart. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  14. Sidgwick, Henry. 1907. The Methods of Ethics, 7th ed. London: MacMillan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Mill, John Stuart. 2002. Utilitarianism. In Utilitarianism. Ed. George Sher. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

  16. Anscombe, G.E.M. 1958. Modern Moral Philosophy. Philosophy 33: 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Hare, R. M. 1963. Freedom and Reason. Oxford: Clarendon Press: 122

  18. Hare, R.M., 1981. Moral Thinking. Oxford: Clarendon Press: 191.

  19. Hare, R.M. 1993. Essays in Ethical Theory. Oxford: Clarendon Press: 229.

  20. Irwin, Terence. 2009. The Development of Ethics: From Kant to Rawls. Chapter 79. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  21. Singer, Peter. 2011. Practical Ethics, 3rd ed., 99–100. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Rachels, James. 1986. The End of Life: Euthanasia and Morality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Kuhse, Helga. 1987. The Sanctity of Life Doctrine in Medicine: A Critique. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Rachels, James. 1990. Created from Animals: Philosophical Implications of Darwinism. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Dworkin, Ronald. 1994. Life’s Dominion: An Argument about Abortion and Euthanasia. New York: Random House: 27.

  26. Singer. Peter. 1995. Is the Sanctity of Life Ethics Terminally Ill? Bioethics 9: 327–342.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Gensler, Harry. 2009. Singer’s Unsanctity of Human Life: A Critique. In Peter Singer Under Fire: The Moral Iconoclast Faces His Critics. Ed. Jeffrey A. Schaler. LaSalle IL: Open Court: 163–185.

  28. Grisez, Germain. 1970. Abortion: The Myths, the Realities, and the Arguments. New York: Corpus Publications: 65.

  29. Finnis, John. 2011. Natural Law and Natural Rights 2nd edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 86.

  30. Dyck, Arthur J. 2002. Life’s Worth: The Case Against Assisted Suicide. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans: 45–71.

  31. Gomez-Lobo, Alfonso. 2007. Inviolability at any age. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 17: 311–320.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Keown, John. 2013. The Law and Ethics of Medicine: Essays on the Inviolability of Life, 88–109. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Boyle, Joseph. 2020. Against “Assisted Death.” In Natural Law Ethics in Theory & Practice: A Joseph Boyle Reader, ed. D.C. Washington, 319–336. Catholic University of America Press.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Hershenov, David. 2016. Death and Dignity. In G.E.M. Anscombe and Human Dignity. Ed. John Mizzoni. Philadelphia: Neumann University Press.

  35. Rosen, Michael. 2012. Dignity: Its History and Meaning. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Sulmasy, Daniel P. 2013. The Varieties of Human Dignity: A Logical and Conceptual Analysis. Medicine Health Care & Philosophy 16: 937–944.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Ramsey, Paul. 1978. Ethics at the Edges of Life: Medical and Legal Perspectives, 146–147. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Smith, Patrick T. 2018. Ramsey on “Choosing Life” at the End of Life: Conceptual Analysis of Euthanasia and Adjudicating End of Life Care Options. Christian Bioethics 24: 151–172.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Hare, R., and M. 1972. Wrongness and Harm. In Essays on Moral Concepts, 92–109. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Boorse, Christopher. 1975. On the Distinction between Disease and Illness. Philosophy and Public Affairs 5: 49–68.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Childress, James F. 1976. Compensating Injured Research Subjects: The Moral Argument. The Hastings Center Report 6: 21–27.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Boorse, Christopher. 1977. Health as a Theoretical Concept. Philosophy of Science 44: 542–573.

    Google Scholar 

  43. MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1982. Risk, Harm, and Benefit Assessments as Instruments of Moral Evaluation. In Ethical Issues in Social Science Research. Eds. Tom L. Beauchamp, Ruth Faden, R. Jay Wallace, and Leroy Walters. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 176–177.

  44. Feinberg, Joel. 1987. Harm to Others: The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law, vol. I. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Finnis, John. 1987. Legal Enforcement of “Duties to Oneself”: Kant vs Neo-Kantians. Columbia Law Review 87: 433–456.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Raz, Joseph. 1988. The Morality of Freedom, 417–418. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Feinberg, Joel. 1989. Rights, Justice, and the Bounds of Liberty, 49–51. Princeton University Press: Princeton.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Seifert, Josef. 2004. The Philosophical Diseases of Medicine and their Cure, 52–56. Dordrecht: Springer Press.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Schweitzer, Albert. 1929. Civilization and Ethics, Part II of The Philosophy of Civilization. trans. C.T. Campion. London. A & C Black: 246–247.

  50. Schweitzer, Albert. 2009. Out of My Life and Thought: An Autobiography. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press: 156–157, 235–236.

  51. Barsam, Ara Paul. 2008. Reverence for Life: Albert Schweitzer’s Contribution to Ethical Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Rachels, James. 2002. The Value of Human Life. Philosophical Inquiry 24: 3–16.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Glover, Jonathan. 1977. Causing Death and Saving Lives. New York: Penguin Press 1977: 61–64.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Finnis, John. 1993. The “Value of Human Life” and the “Right to Death”: Some Reflections on Cruzan and Ronald Dworkin. Southern Illinois Law Review 17: 559–571.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Sulmasy, Daniel P. 2002. Death, Dignity, and the Theory of Value. Ethical Perspectives 9: 103–118.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Sulmasy, Daniel P. 2011. Speaking of the Value of Life. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 21: 181–199.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Smart, J.J.C. 1956. Extreme and Restricted Utilitarianism. The Philosophical Quarterly 6: 344–354.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Feinberg, Joel. 1978. Voluntary Euthanasia and the Inalienable Right to Life. Philosophy & Public Affairs 7: 93–123.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Li, Jack. 2002. Can Death Be a Harm to the Person Who Dies? Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Nagel, Thomas. 1979. Mortal Questions, 1–10. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Kamm, Frances M. 1993. Morality, Mortality. Vol. I: Death and Whom to Save from It, Chapter 1. New York: Oxford University Press.

  62. Garcia, J.L.A. 1999. Are Some People Better Off Dead? A Reflection. Logos 2: 68–81.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Jameison, Dale. 1984. Utilitarianism and the Morality of Killing. Philosophical Studies 45: 209–221.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Perrett, Roy. 1996. Killing, Letting Die, and the Bare Difference Argument. Bioethics 10: 131–139.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Seay, Gary. 2001. Do Physicians Have an Inviolable Duty Not to Kill? Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 26: 75–91.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Pellegrino, Edmund D. 2001. Physician Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia: Rebuttals of Rebuttals – The Moral Prohibition Remains. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 26: 93–100.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Garcia, J.L.A. 2007. Health versus Harm: Euthanasia and Physicians’ Duties. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 32: 7–24.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Rachels, James. 1984. Euthanasia and Physician’s Professional Commitments. The Southern Journal of Philosophy 22: 281–285.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Rachels, James. 1970. On Moral Absolutism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 48: 338–353.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Gomez-Lobo, Alfonso. 2002. Morality and the Human Goods: An Introduction to Natural Law Ethics. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press: 31.

  71. Finnis, John. 1983. The Fundamentals of Ethics. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press: 81–82.

  72. Rachels, James. 1994. More Impertinent Distinctions and a Defense of Active Euthanasia. In Killing and Letting Die. Eds. Bonnie Steinbock and Alastair Norcross. New York: Fordham University Press: 139–154.

  73. Henig, Robin Marantz. 2013. A Life or Death Situation. New York Times Magazine July 17, 2013.

  74. Lutz, Christopher. 2012. Reading Alasdair MacIntyre’s After Virtue, 77–78. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Laing, Jacqueline, and David Oderberg, eds. 1997. Human Lives: Essays on Consequentialist Bioethics. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Donagan, Alan. 1994. Is There a Credible Form of Utilitarianism? In The Philosophical Papers of Alan Donagan, Vol. II: Action, Reason, and Value. Ed. J.E. Malpas. Chicago: University of Chicago Press: 132–143.

  77. Scheffler, Samuel. 1994. The Rejection of Consequentialism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Grisez, Germain. 1978. Against Consequentialism. American Journal of Jurisprudence 23: 30–41.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Oderberg, David S. 2000. Moral Theory: A Non-Consequentialist Approach, 65–86. Oxford: Wiley Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Donagan, Alan. The Theory of Morality. Chicago: University of Chicago Press: 204.

  81. Kant, Immanuel. 1933. Critique of Pure Reason. Trans. Norman Kemp Smith. London: Routledge A807 (B835): 637.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Griffin, James. 1992. The Human Good and the Ambitions of Consequentialism. In The Good Life and the Human Good. Eds. E. F. Paul, F. D. Miller and J. Paul. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 131.

  83. Griffin, James. 1996. Value Judgement: Improving Our Ethical Beliefs. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 105.

  84. Mackie, J.L. 1977. Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. New York: Penguin Press 129: 133.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Beauchamp, Tom L. and Childress, James F. 2012. Principles of Biomedical Ethics 7th edition. New York: Oxford University Press: 359.

  86. Singer, Peter, and Katarzyna, de Lazari-Radek. 2010. Secrecy in Consequentialism: A Defense of Esoteric Morality. Ratio 23: 34–58.

    Google Scholar 

  87. Cottingham, John. 1986. Partiality, Favourtism, and Morality. The Philosophical Quarterly 36: 357–373.

    Google Scholar 

  88. Rescher, Nicholas. 1965. Distributive Justice. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill Co.: 25–41.

  89. Finnis, John. 2011. Intention and Side Effects. In Intention and Identity: Collected Essays, vol. II, 173–198. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  90. Feinberg, Joel. 1977. Harm and Self-Interest. In Law, Morality, and Society. Eds. P. Hacker and J. Raz. Oxford: Clarendon Press: 299–308.

  91. Devine, Phillip E. 1978. The Ethics of Homicide. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press: 18–23.

  92. Moreland, J.P. 1988. James Rachels and the Active Euthanasia Debate. JETS 31: 90.

    Google Scholar 

  93. Brock, Dan W. 1973. Recent Work in Utilitarianism. American Philosophical Quarterly 10: 245.

    Google Scholar 

  94. Finnis, John. 1996. Commensuration and Public Reason. In Incommensurability, Incomparability, and Practical Reason. Ed. Ruth Chang. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  95. Grisez, Germain, John Finnis, and Joseph Boyle. 1987. Nuclear Deterrence and Moral Realism, 254–260. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  96. Thomson, Judith Jarvis. 1993. Goodness and Utilitarianism. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 67: 145–159.

    Google Scholar 

  97. Rawls, John. 1999. A Theory of Justice revised edition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press: 557.

  98. Sumner, L.W. 1976. A Matter of Life and Death. Nous 10: 167.

    Google Scholar 

  99. Sumner, L.W. 2013. Assisted Death: A Study in Ethics & the Law. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  100. Sumner, L.W. 2017. Physician Assisted Death: What Everyone Needs to Know. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  101. Vendler, Zeno. 1993. Changing Places. In Hare and Critics, ed. Douglas Seanor and N. Fotion. Oxford: Clarendon Press: 171–183.

  102. Broome, John. 2008. Can There be a Preference Based Utilitarianism? In Justice, Political Liberalism, and Utilitarianism. Eds. Marc Fleurbaey, Maurice Salles, John A. Weymark. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 221–239.

  103. Harris, John. 1995. Euthanasia and the Value of Life. In John Keown, ed. Euthanasia Examined, 8–16. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  104. Callahan, Daniel. 1992. When Self Determination Run Amok. Hastings Institute Report 22: 52–55.

    Google Scholar 

  105. Callahan, Daniel. 2000. The Troubled Dream of Life. In Search of a Peaceful Death, ed. D.C. Washington, 91–120. Georgetown University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  106. Callahan, Daniel. 2005. A Case Against Euthanasia, in Contemporary Debates in Applied Ethics. ed. Andrew Cohen. Oxford: Wiley Blackwell: 179–190.

  107. Brink, David O. 1989. Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics. Chapter 8. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  108. Singer, Peter, and Katarzyna Lazari-Radek. 2014. The Point of View of the Universe: Sidgwick and Contemporary Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  109. Beauchamp, Tom L. 1999. The Failure of Theories of Personhood. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 9: 317.

    Google Scholar 

  110. Smith, Patrick T. 2019. On Physician-Assisted Death and the Killing of Innocents. International Philosophical Quarterly 59: 341–363.

    Google Scholar 

  111. Anscombe, G.E.M. 2005. Murder and the Morality of Euthanasia. In Human Life, Action, and Ethics. Ed. Luke Gormally and Mary Geach. Exeter: Imprint Academic: 261–277.

  112. Jones, David Albert. 2022. Anscombe on Euthanasia as Murder. In The Oxford Handbook of Elizabeth Anscombe. Ed. Roger Teichmann. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 271–292.

  113. Wiggins, David. 1980. Sameness and Substance. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press: 152.

  114. Moreland, J.P., and Norman Geisler. 1990. The Life and Death Debate: Moral Issues of Our Time, 72–73. New York: Greenwood Press.

    Google Scholar 

  115. Pellegrino, Edmund. 1996. The Place of Intention in the Moral Assessment of Assisted Suicide and Active Euthanasia. In Intending Death: The Ethics of Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia. Ed. Beauchamp, Tom L. New Jersey: Prentice Hall: 163–183.

  116. Grisez, Germain, and Joseph Boyle. 1979. Life and Death with Liberty and Justice: A Contribution to the Euthanasia Debate, 214–238. South Bend: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  117. Arkes, Hadley. 1997. Autonomy and the Quality of Life: The Dismantling of Moral Terms. Issues in Law and Medicine 2: 421–433.

    Google Scholar 

  118. Pellegrino, Edmund. 1998. The False Promise of Beneficent Killing. In Regulating How We Die: The Ethical, Medical, and Legal Issues Surrounding Physician Assisted Suicide. Ed. Emmanuel, Linda L. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press: 71–91.

  119. Sandoe, P. 1999. Quality of Life: Three Competing Views. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 2: 11–23.

    Google Scholar 

  120. Oderberg, David S. 2000. Applied Ethics: A Non-Consequentialist Approach, 60–71. Oxford: Wiley Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  121. Kass, Leon. 2002. Life, Liberty, and the Defense of Dignity: The Challenge of Bioethics, 247–253. San Francisco: Encounter Books.

    Google Scholar 

  122. Paterson, Craig. 2012. Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia: A Natural Law Approach, 106–109. London: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  123. DiBiase, John K. 2017. Euthanasia and Quality of Life: Critique of a Subjective Standard. National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 17: 417–424.

    Google Scholar 

  124. Keown, John. 2018. Euthanasia, Ethics, and Public Policy: An Argument Against Legalization, 2nd ed., 37–50. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  125. Locke, John. 1996. Of Identity and Diversity, Chapter XXVII of An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co.

    Google Scholar 

  126. Warren, Mary Anne. 1973. On the Moral and Legal Status of Abortion. The Monist 57: 43–61.

    Google Scholar 

  127. Tooley, Michael. 1983. Abortion and Infanticide. Oxford: Clarendon Press: 103.

  128. McMahan, Jeff. 1999. Cloning, Killing, and Identity. Journal of Medical Ethics 25: 77–86.

    Google Scholar 

  129. McMahan, Jeff. 2002. The Ethics of Killing: Problems at the Margins of Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 430.

  130. Grisez, Germain. 1983. The Way of the Lord Jesus, Vol. In I, Christian Moral Principles, ed. I.L. Quincy, 460–467. Franciscan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  131. Lee, Patrick. 2001. Personhood, Dignity, Suicide, and Euthanasia. National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 1: 334–339.

    Google Scholar 

  132. Finnis, John. 1995. A Philosophical Case Against Euthanasia, in Euthanasia Examined. Ed. John Keown., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 32.

  133. Biggar, Nigel. 2004. Aiming to Kill: The Ethics of Suicide and Euthanasia. London: Dartman, Longman & Todd: 35–36.

  134. Grisez, Germain. 1989. When do People Begin? Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 63: 27–47.

    Google Scholar 

  135. Lee, Patrick. 1998. Human Beings are Animals. In Natural Law and Moral Inquiry: Ethics, Metaphysics, and Politics in the Thought of Germain Grisez. Ed. Robert P. George. Washington DC: Georgetown University Press: 135–152.

  136. Eberl, Jason. 2002. Thomistic Principles and Bioethics. London: Routledge: 4–9, 24–42.

  137. Finnis, John. 2002. Abortion, Natural Law, and Public Reason. In Natural Law and Public Reason. Eds. Robert P. George and Christopher Wolfe. Washington DC: Georgetown University Press: 191.

  138. Geach, Peter. 1957. Mental Acts, 118–120. London: Routledge Press.

    Google Scholar 

  139. Van Inwagen, Peter. 2002. What Do We Refer To When We Say I? In Blackwell Guide to Metaphysics. Ed. Richard M. Gale. Oxford: Wiley Blackwell: 174–199.

  140. Hershenov, David. 2003. Can There be Spatially Coincident Entities of the Same Kind. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 33: 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  141. Lee, Patrick. 2004. Soul, Body, and Personhood. American Journal of Jurisprudence 49: 87–125.

    Google Scholar 

  142. Beckwith, Francis J. 2005. Of Souls, Selves, and Cerebrums. Journal of Medical Ethics 31: 56–60.

    Google Scholar 

  143. Hershenov. David. 2005. Persons as Proper Parts of Organisms. Theoria 71: 29–37.

    Google Scholar 

  144. George, Robert, and Patrick Lee. 2009. Body-Self Dualism in Contemporary Ethics and Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  145. Eberl, Jason. 2020. The Nature of Human Persons: Metaphysics and Ethics. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  146. Hershenov, David. 2021. Thinking Animals or Thinking Brains? Acta Analytica 36: 11–24.

    Google Scholar 

  147. Kass, Leon. 2002. “I Will Give No Deadly Drug:” Why Doctors Must Not Kill. In The Case Against Assisted Suicide. Ed. Foley, Kathleen M. and Hendin, Herbert. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press: 24.

  148. MacIntyre Alasdair. 1985. Medicine aimed at the care of persons rather than what? In Changing Values in Medicine. Eds. Cassell EJ and Siegler M. Frederick, MD: University Publications of America: 83–96.

  149. Gormally, Luke. 1992. The Aged: Non-Persons, Human Persons, and Justice. In The Dependent Elderly: Autonomy, Justice, and Quality of Care. Ed. Luke Gormally. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 181–189.

  150. Velleman, J. David. 1992. Against the Right to Die. The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 17: 665–681.

    Google Scholar 

  151. Pellegrino, Edmund. 1993. Compassion needs reason too. Journal of the American Medical Association 270: 874–875.

    Google Scholar 

  152. Foley, Kathleen M. 1995. Pain, Physician Assisted Suicide, and Euthanasia. Pain Forum 4: 163–178.

    Google Scholar 

  153. Silvers, Anita. 1998. Protecting the Innocent from Physician Assisted Suicide: Disability Discrimination and the Duty to Protect Otherwise Vulnerable Groups. In Physician Assisted Suicide: Expanding the Debate. Eds. Rosamond Rhodes and Margaret P. Battin. London: Routledge Press: 133–149.

  154. Hendin, Herbert. 1998. Seduced by Death: Doctors, Patients, and Assisted Suicide. New York: W.W. Norton & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  155. Hendin, Herbert. 1999. Suicide, Assisted Suicide, and Euthanasia. In The Harvard Medical School Guide to Suicide Assessment and Intervention. Ed. Douglas Jacobs. San Francisco: Jossey Bass Publishers: 540–561.

  156. Gorsuch, Neil. 2007. A Reply to Raymond Tallis on the Legalization of Physician Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia. The Journal of Legal Medicine 28: 327–332.

    Google Scholar 

  157. Hendin, Herbert, and Kathleen Foley. 2008. Physician Assisted Suicide in Oregon: A Medical Perspective. Michigan Law Review 106: 1613–1640.

    Google Scholar 

  158. Jones, David Albert. 2011. Is there a logical slippery slope from voluntary to non-voluntary euthanasia? Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 21: 379–404.

    Google Scholar 

  159. Yang, Y. Tony., and Farr Curlin. 2016. Why Physicians Should Oppose Assisted Suicide. Journal of the American Medical Association 315: 247–248.

    Google Scholar 

  160. Jones, D.A. 2018. Assisted Dying and Suicide Prevention. Journal of Disability & Religion 22: 298–316.

    Google Scholar 

  161. Arras, John D. 2019. Physician-Assisted Suicide: A Tragic View. In Bioethics Principles, Issues, and Cases. Ed. Lewis Vaughan. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press: 667.

  162. Keown, John. 2022. The Logical Link between Voluntary and Non-Voluntary Euthanasia. The Cambridge Law Journal 81: 84–108.

    Google Scholar 

  163. Brock, Dan W. 1992. Voluntary Active Euthanasia. Hastings Center Report 22: 10–22.

    Google Scholar 

  164. Brock, Dan W. 1999. A Critique of Three Objections to Physician Assisted Suicide. Ethics 109: 519–547.

    Google Scholar 

  165. Persson, Ingmar. 1983. Hare on Universal Prescriptivism and Utilitarianism. Analysis 43: 43–49.

    Google Scholar 

  166. Gomez-Lobo, Alfonso. 2015. Bioethics and the Human Goods. Washington DC: Georgetown University Press: 71.

  167. Cavanaugh, Thomas A. 2001. The Instability of the Standard Justification for Physician Assisted Suicide. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 10: 103–109.

    Google Scholar 

  168. Boyle, Joseph. 1991. Who is Entitled to Double Effect? The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 16: 479.

    Google Scholar 

  169. Foot, Philippa. 1967. The Problem of Abortion and the Doctrine of Double Effect. Oxford Review 5: 5–15.

    Google Scholar 

  170. Hart, H.L.A. 1978. Intention and Punishment. In Punishment and Responsibility: Essays in the Philosophy of Law. Oxford: Clarendon Press: 120.

  171. Fried, Charles. 1978. Right and Wrong. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press: 20–29.

  172. Boyle, Joseph. 1980. Toward Understanding the Principle of Double Effect. Ethics 90: 527–538.

    Google Scholar 

  173. Quinn, Warren. 1989. Actions, Intentions, and Consequences: The Doctrine of Double Effect. Philosophy and Public Affairs 18: 334–351.

    Google Scholar 

  174. Garcia, J.L.A. 1993. The New Critique of Anti-Consequentialist Moral Theory. Philosophical Studies 71: 1–32.

    Google Scholar 

  175. Aulisio, Mark. 1995. In Defense of the Intention/Foresight Distinction. American Philosophical Quarterly 32: 341–354.

    Google Scholar 

  176. Cavanaugh, Thomas. 1999. Double Effect and the End-Not-Means Principle: A Response to Bennett. Journal of Applied Philosophy 16: 181–185.

    Google Scholar 

  177. Sulmasy, Daniel, and Edmund Pellegrino. 1999. The rule of double effect: Clearing up the double talk. Archives of Internal Medicine 22: 545–550.

    Google Scholar 

  178. Kaczor, Christopher. 2001. Distinguishing Intention from Foresight: What is Included in a Means to an End? International Philosophical Quarterly 41: 77–89.

    Google Scholar 

  179. Anscombe, G.E.M. 2001. Action, Intention, and Double Effect. In The Doctrine of Double Effect: Philosophers Debate a Controversial Moral Principle. Ed. P. A. Woodward. South Bend: University of Notre Dame Press: 50–67.

  180. Foot, Philippa. 2002. Morality, Action, and Outcome. In Moral Dilemmas, 88–104. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  181. Cavanaugh, Thomas. 2006. Double Effect Reasoning: Doing Good and Avoiding Evil. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  182. Sulmasy, Daniel P. 2007. “Reinventing” the Rule of Double Effect. In The Oxford Handbook of Bioethics. Ed. Bonnie Steinbock. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 114–149.

  183. Garcia, J.L.A. 2007. The Doubling Undone? Double Effect in Recent Medical Ethics. Philosophical Papers 36: 245–270.

    Google Scholar 

  184. Oderberg, David. 2010. The Doctrine of Double Effect. In A Companion to the Philosophy of Action. Eds. T. O’Connor and C. Sandis. Oxford: Wiley Blackwell: 324–330.

  185. Stuchlik, Joshua. 2021. Intention and Wrong-doing: A Defense of Double Effect. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  186. Bennett, Jonathan. 1966. Whatever the Consequences. Analysis 26: 83–102.

    Google Scholar 

  187. McMahan, Jeff. 1994. Revising the Doctrine of Double Effect. The Journal of Applied Philosophy 11: 201–212.

    Google Scholar 

  188. Powers, Madison. 1995. Contemporary Defenses of the Doctrine of Double Effect. Revue Internationale de Philosophie 49: 341–356.

    Google Scholar 

  189. Brock, Dan. 1997. The Rule of Double Effect: A Critique of its Role in End-of-Life Decision Making. New England Journal of Medicine 337: 1768–1771.

    Google Scholar 

  190. McIntyre, Alison. 2003. Doing Away with Double Effect. Ethics 111: 219–255.

    Google Scholar 

  191. Miller, Franklin G., Robert D. Troug, and Dan W. Brock. 2010. Moral Fictions and Medical Ethics. Bioethics 24: 453–460.

    Google Scholar 

  192. Chandler, John. 1990. Killing or Letting Die – Putting the Debate in Context. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 68: 420.

    Google Scholar 

  193. Boyle, Joseph. 1977. On Killing and Letting Die. New Scholasticism 51: 433–452.

    Google Scholar 

  194. Foot, Philippa. 1980. Killing, Letting Die, and Euthanasia. Analysis 41: 159–160.

    Google Scholar 

  195. Kamm, Frances. 1983. Killing and Letting Die: Methodological and Substantive Issues. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 64: 297–312.

    Google Scholar 

  196. Kamm, Frances. 1996. Morality, Mortality, Vol. 2: Rights, Duties, and Status. New York: Oxford University Press: 17–142.

  197. Brody, Baruch. 1996. Withdrawal of Treatment versus Killing of Patients. In Intending Death: The Ethics of Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia. Ed. Tom L. Beauchamp. Upper Saddle NJ: Prentice Hall.

  198. Sulmasy, Daniel P. 1998. Killing and Allowing to Die: Another Look. Journal of Law, Medicine, and Ethics 26: 55–64.

    Google Scholar 

  199. Foot, Philippa. 2002. Killing and Letting Die. In Moral Dilemmas, 78–87. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  200. Jensen, Steven. 2011. Killing and Letting Die. In The Ethics of Organ Transplantation, ed. D.C. Washington, 170–192. Catholic University of America Press.

    Google Scholar 

  201. Sulmasy, Daniel P., and Mariele A. Courtois. 2019. Why the Common Sense Distinction between Killing and Allowing-to-Die is so easy to grasp but so hard to explain. The Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 28: 353–358.

    Google Scholar 

  202. Boyle, Joseph. 2017. A Catholic Approach to Withholding Medically Provided Food and Water. In Contemporary Controversies in Catholic Bioethics. Ed. Jason T. Eberl. Dordrecht: Springer: 425–441.

  203. Boyle, Joseph. 2004. Medical Ethics and Double Effect: The Case for Terminal Sedation. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 25: 51–60.

    Google Scholar 

  204. Bishop. Jeffrey P. 2006. Euthanasia, Efficiency, and the Historical Distinction between Killing a Patient and Allowing a Patient Die. Journal of Medical Ethics 32: 220–224.

    Google Scholar 

  205. Gorsuch, Neil. 2009. The Future of Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia, 48–76. Princeton University Press: Princeton.

    Google Scholar 

  206. Sullivan, Thomas D. 1977. Active and Passive Euthanasia: An Impertinent Distinction? Human Life Review 3: 43.

    Google Scholar 

  207. Sullivan, Thomas D. 1994. Coming To Terms: A Response to Rachels. In Killing and Letting Die, 2nd ed., 155–161. New York: Fordham University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  208. Aquinas, Thomas. 2006. Summa Theologiae: Volume 18, Principles of Morality: 1a2ae 18.4 ad 3. Ed. Thomas Gilby. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  209. McInerny, Ralph. 2012. Aquinas on Human Action: A Theory of Action. Washington DC: Catholic University of America Press: 69.

  210. Brock, Stephen L. 2021. Thomas Aquinas and the Theory of Action. Washington DC: Catholic University of America Press.

    Google Scholar 

  211. Sulmasy, Daniel P. 1996. The Use and Abuse of the Principle of Double Effect. Clinical Pulmonary Medicine 3: 86–90.

    Google Scholar 

  212. Anscombe, Elizabeth. 2000. Intention. In 68–70, ed. M.A. Cambridge, 68–70. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  213. Lockwood, Michael, and Elizabeth Anscombe. 1983. Sins of Omission? The Non-Treatment of Controls in Clinical Trials. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 57: 207–227.

    Google Scholar 

  214. Murphy, Jeffrie. 1973. The Killing of the Innocent. The Monist 57: 541.

    Google Scholar 

  215. Rachels, James. 1979. Killing and Starving to Death. Philosophy 54: 159–171.

    Google Scholar 

  216. Singer, Peter. 1972. Famine, Affluence, and Morality, Philosophy and Public Affairs 1: 229-243. Reprinted in Singer. 2002. Unsanctifying Human Life. Oxford: Blackwell Press: 145-56.

  217. David Albert Jones and Chris Gastmans, and Calum MacKellar. 2017. Eds. Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide: Lessons from Belgium. 2017. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  218. Dumsday, Travis. 2021. Assisted Suicide in Canada: Moral, Legal, and Policy Considerations. Vancouver: University of British Columbia Press.

    Google Scholar 

  219. Sprung, C.L., M.A. Somerville, L. Radbruch, N.S. Collet, G. Duttge, J.P. Piva, M. Antonelli, D.P. Sulmasy, W. Lemmens, and E.W. Ely. 2018. Physician Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia: Emerging Issues from a Global Perspective. Journal of Palliative Care 33: 197–203.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Timothy J. Furlan.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

I do not have any conflicts of interests.

Ethical approval

This research did not involve any human participants or animals.

Informed consent

There was no need for informed consent as no human participants were involved.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Furlan, T.J. James Rachels and the morality of euthanasia. Theor Med Bioeth 45, 69–97 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-024-09658-2

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-024-09658-2

Keywords

Navigation