Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-45l2p Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-28T07:01:28.871Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Feeling Responsible: On Regret for Others’ Harms

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 March 2024

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This paper investigates the moral emotion of being socially, but non-agentially connected to a harm. I propose understanding the emotion of an affiliated onlooker as a species of regret called ‘social-regret’. Breaking from existing guilt- and shame-based accounts, I argue that social-regret can be a fitting, expressive, and revelatory reactive attitude that opens the way for deliberation over accountability for others’ harms. When we feel social-regret, our attention is directed towards the moral salience of our social relations and the expectations that undergird them, as well as possibilities for ameliorative action. I consider several existing accounts of affiliated onlookers’ emotions (including embarrassment, guilt, and shame), and I highlight the advantages of supplementing these with a regret-based account. Social-regret provides a novel way to understand negative, self-directed emotions in response to others’ harms as rational, expressive, and potentially reason-giving experiences.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NCCreative Common License - ND
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/), which permits non-commercial re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is unaltered and is properly cited. The written permission of Cambridge University Press must be obtained for commercial re-use or in order to create a derivative work.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Royal Institute of Philosophy

1. Introduction

In The Theory of Moral Sentiments, Adam Smith raises the following maxim which he takes to be self-evident: generally speaking, one is only deserving of praise or blame on account of actions for which one is morally responsible (Smith, Reference Smith and Haakonssen2002, p. 109 [II.iii.intro.3]). According to this principle, we should not blame others for contingent events, accidental harms, or unforeseen or unintended outcomes. Smith is also keenly aware, however, that our moral sentiments do not always adhere to this rule. He identifies two notable irregularities. The first is that we tend to decrease sentiments of praise or blame for intended, but incomplete actions; that is, we ‘diminish our sense of the merit or demerit of those actions which arose from the most laudable or blamable intentions, when they fail of producing their proposed effects’ (Reference Smith and Haakonssen2002, p. 114 [II.iii.2.1]). Second, we also tend to enlarge sentiments of praise or blame ‘beyond what is due to the motives or affections from which they proceed’ in light of outcomes (Reference Smith and Haakonssen2002, p. 114 [II.iii.2.1]). In other words, our moral sentiments are susceptible to seemingly irrational escalation and diminution on the basis of resultant or consequential luck – how things turn out.Footnote 1

Smith notes that even those who are unaffected by and uninvolved in an action are liable to experience these heightened moral sentiments: ‘Nor is this irregularity of sentiment felt only by those who are immediately affected by the consequences of any action. It is felt, in some measure, even by the impartial spectator’ (Reference Smith and Haakonssen2002, p. 114 [II.iii.2.2]). He goes on to explore several powerful, self-directed moral sentiments that respond to significant relations and group memberships (such as feelings of national pride and shame), and observes that the intensity of these self-directed moral sentiments is often disproportionate to one's own causal contributions to the outcomes in question.Footnote 2

Over two hundred and fifty years later, the question of moral emotions by association rose to prominence after World War II in discussions of German guilt, and continues to occupy centre stage in contemporary debates over identity, legacies of oppression, environmental degradation, and divestment. How am I to feel when my close family member inflicts harm through bigoted behaviour? What about my neighbour, or fellow citizen? How should I feel regarding the actions of my ancestors? Many people hold strong views about the appropriateness (or inappropriateness) of self-directed moral emotions – guilt and shame, especially – for the wrongdoings of others. One can imagine two extremes: on the one side, the dismissal of self-directed, negative emotions for anything other than one's own conduct as pathological; and on the other side, excessive and unproductive feelings of guilt and shame for events far beyond one's own control.

The object of this article is to reframe the negative emotions of affiliated onlookers in order to find a middle way between these two extremes. My basic claim is that some of the moral sentiments associated with harms brought about by one's social relations are not curiously persistent pathologies, but instead fitting reactive attitudes with morally and politically salient epistemic and conative outcomes.Footnote 3 Taking these affective responses seriously, we might ask: What does the emotion of an affiliated onlooker express? Where does it pull our attention? How does it predispose us to behave?

The moral emotion that I have in mind is experienced by an affiliated onlooker – that is, someone who is a third party to a harm and does not satisfy standard conditions for moral or collective responsibility, but nonetheless feels implicated in that harm in virtue of her social connection with the harm's perpetrator. Existing scholarship tends to analyse the emotions of affiliated onlookers in terms of guilt and shame (May, Reference May1992; Gilbert, Reference Gilbert1997; Jaspers, Reference Jaspers and Ashton2001; Oshana, Reference Oshana2006; Christensen, Reference Christensen2013), most recently in Amy Sepinwall's defence of the rationality of ‘faultless guilt for a loved one's wrong’ (Sepinwall, Reference Sepinwall2022, p. 210). Supplementing these accounts, I aim to elucidate the emotion of social proximity to wrongdoing in terms of regret in the tradition of Bernard Williams’ concept of agent-regret. In doing so, I hope to shed light on a different dimension of the affective phenomenon in question than is captured in guilt- or shame-based accounts, and to draw wider conceptual distance between the emotions of affiliated onlookers and the emotions of perpetrators.

Here is my basic proposal: when one's social relations and/or (members of) one's social groups behave badly, one may be susceptible to a species of regret that I call ‘social-regret’. Social-regret provides a new name for what Marina Oshana calls the ‘phenomenological experience of [moral] taint’ (Oshana, Reference Oshana2006, p. 364). We feel social-regret when we are not agentially involved in harmful actions, but rather connected through significant social relations to another's harm. To lay the groundwork for a regret-based account, I will begin by describing a scenario in which an individual is connected to a harm purely by affiliation, and in which regret of some kind is a plausible response. I then situate social-regret in relation to other forms of regret and identify three typical features of central cases. Next, I argue that social-regret has notable epistemic and conative outcomes – specifically, it can draw attention to our social relations and the expectations that undergird them, and open the way for novel deliberation over accountability going forward. Finally, I conclude by considering several existing accounts of the emotion of affiliated onlookers: embarrassment, guilt (of various kinds), and shame (of various kinds). I give both conceptual and practical reasons for favouring a regret-based account for the cases under consideration, and I end with the suggestion that social-regret better avoids connotations of culpability where guilt- and shame-based accounts tempt them rhetorically, and so may help to head off common defensive dismissals of the emotion in question as a symptom of a pathologically bleeding heart. Because the language of regret more clearly grants premises of non-culpability and non-agency, regret may be a more attractive conceptual resource for enjoining others to be receptive to their moral emotions and to take accountability for harms that are not, strictly speaking, their own.

2. Between Spectator and Agent

It has long been recognized that emotions can redirect our attention by influencing the perceived salience of information about ourselves (de Sousa, Reference de Sousa1987; Elgin, Reference Elgin, Brun, Doğuoğlu and Kuenzle2007; Roberts, Reference Roberts2013) and those who fall within our ‘circle of concerns’ (Nussbaum, Reference Nussbaum2013, p. 11), or the community and social environment(s) in which we are enmeshed. My suggestion is that social-regret refocuses our attention on the moral salience of our social relations and affectively opens space for deliberation over accountability.

Consider the following situation:

In her high school history class Martha learns about the American deployment of atomic weapons during World War II. She is viscerally disturbed by the sheer scale of devastation wrought by the bombings, as well the fact that it was her own country that carried them out. When Martha brings up the subject with her parents, they tell her that her maternal grandfather (now deceased) was an engineer who worked on the Manhattan Project. His contributions to the wartime effort to develop and weaponize atomic energy were, as far as her parents understand it, indispensable. Martha's affective discomfort heightens. She already felt somewhat connected to and unsettled by the bombings on account of her nationality, but now she feels that she has a different and alarming relationship to them. Recalling her teacher's arguments that the use of atomic weapons may have saved lives on the Pacific front, Martha tries to rationalize that her grandfather may not have done anything blameworthy, and that his actions were his own, not hers. Even so, the uncomfortable feeling persists. Her cognizance of her grandfather's actions presses upon her.

Some would describe this as a case of moral taint, in which one's moral record, personality, and/or psyche are marred by the conduct of associated parties (Oshana, Reference Oshana2006; Appiah, Reference Appiah, May and Hoffman1991; May, Reference May, May and Hoffman1991). There is wide disagreement over whether and how moral taint relates to moral responsibility.Footnote 4 For the purposes of this paper, I will set the question of whether and when moral taint generates moral obligations on the part of affiliated persons to the side in order to focus on the way that moral taint can be experienced through reactive attitudes.Footnote 5 This is to ask where the emotion of vicarious harm – e.g., learning of a family member's harmful prejudices, or a workplace's unethical investments, or a friend's cruel decision – pulls us epistemically and conatively.

Martha knows that she is obviously not to blame for the deployment of atomic weapons long before she was born. Nevertheless, she feels connected to the bombings in at least two ways: first (and faintly) as an American citizen, and second (and more urgently) through her grandfather. Given her distinctive positionality vis-à-vis the harms associated with the bombings, what kind of moral emotion is it appropriate for Martha to feel? I do not mean ‘appropriate’ in the normative sense of how Martha ought to feel. I follow Deborah Tollefsen's position that ‘[t]he notion of appropriateness in discussions of the emotions is one of rational acceptability rather than morally obligatory or compulsory’ (Reference Tollefsen2006, p. 225). Put another way, we can understand the appropriateness of an emotion in terms of what D'Arms and Jacobson call the ‘fittingness’ of an emotional response, which refers to the harmony between evaluative features of an emotion and its object (D'Arms and Jacobson, Reference D'Arms and Jacobson2000). In what follows, I take it as given that there are criteria under which certain moral emotions are fitting in this evaluative sense, and that the absence of those conditions can render affective responses unfitting.Footnote 6

A starting point can be found in the category of ‘counterfactual emotions’, a term that Kahneman and Tversky use to denote a class of emotions that are dependent ‘on a comparison of reality with what might or should have been’ (Reference Kahneman, Tversky, Kahneman, Slovic and Tversky1982, p. 206). Regret is a counterfactual emotion in that it involves reference to alternative possibilities. Note that one need not have a specific alternative reality in mind when experiencing regret. Counterfactuals might simply negate certain elements of a state of affairs; for example, one can regret going to college without having a clear sense of what one would have preferred to do instead.

It is plausible that Martha might appropriately feel regret for the actions of the United States military despite her lack of agential contribution. In its most general sense – what Williams calls ‘regret in general’ (Williams, Reference Williams1981, p. 27), or what Carla Bagnoli calls ‘evaluator-regret’ (Bagnoli, Reference Bagnoli2000, p. 176) – one can feel regret for practically any harm, including those that took place before one was born.Footnote 7 Still, although it is true that evaluator-regret is fitting for Martha's situation since it ‘can in principle apply to anything of which one can form some conception of how it might have been otherwise, together with consciousness of how things would then have been better’ (Williams, Reference Williams1981, p. 27), it seems far too general to say that Martha feels the regret of a mere onlooker or spectator. As R. Jay Wallace notes, ‘[u]ninvolved third parties do not have the same special reasons for regretting… [and] they can only feel a more generic pain or distress that it is in principle open to anybody to experience’ (Reference Wallace2013, p. 39). Martha is not merely an onlooker, like a random passer-by who happens to witness a car accident. Her relationship with her grandfather means that she is something more than a spectator, albeit something other than a perpetrator.

Williams famously argues that we can rationally feel ‘agent-regret’ for harms that we bring about non-culpably. To take Williams’ example, a lorry driver who injures a child in an unlucky and non-culpable accident may fittingly experience a unique kind of regret as a result of his agential relation to that accident – that is, ‘there is something special about his relation to the happening, something which cannot merely be eliminated by the consideration that it was not his fault’ (Reference Williams1981, p. 28). In Bagnoli's words, ‘the distinction between agent-regret and evaluator-regret is primarily drawn in terms of subject matter: the agent regrets his actions or his deliberation, while the evaluator regrets some state of affairs brought about by somebody else’ (Reference Bagnoli2000, p. 176). But unlike Williams’ lorry driver, Martha is not agentially connected to the harm in question ex hypothesi. Agent-regret is a consequence of first-person, agential involvement in a harm for which one is not culpable, and for this reason it is unfitting for Martha's situation.Footnote 8

Social-regret falls somewhere between these first- and third-person perspectives. I propose that we think of Martha as an ‘affiliated onlooker’ so as to underscore that her regret has a different character than that of an agent or unaffiliated spectator both. Here are three typical features of the kinds of cases under consideration: (1) one knows and is aware that a harm has occurred; (2) one knows and is aware that the harm in question is reasonably attributable to the actions of a social affiliate (individual, social group, institution) and not reasonably attributable to oneself; and (3) one knows and is aware of the affiliation between oneself and that social affiliate. To apply this to Martha's case, we can say: Martha knows and is aware that (1) the dropping of the atomic bombs brought about great harm, that (2) the harm is in some way attributable to her grandfather's contributions, and (3) that she is affiliated with her grandfather.

These are not necessary or sufficient conditions. I am sceptical of the idea that one can be morally obliged to feel specific emotions, though I concede that there are circumstances in which it would be strange (even abhorrent) for an individual to not feel any sort of counterfactual emotion whatsoever. These features are simply meant to clarify the conditions under which the distinctiveness of social-regret (as compared to other forms of regret) is most clearly discernible. (1) holds that a harm has occurred. Not all regret involves harm; regret in its most general sense is appropriate in almost any case in which one would prefer to live in a world in which things turned out differently in some respect. For example, take the case of an envious restaurant diner who regrets her order after catching sight of a neighbour's meal that looks much more delicious than her own. It would be an exaggeration to say that a harm has occurred. Rather, the diner simply wishes that she lived in the world in which she had ordered the fish. I will set such benign situations aside.

(2) specifies that the harm is reasonably attributable to an individual or social group, broadly conceived. On this point, it might be objected that social practices, as opposed to social affiliates, are the proper objects of social-regret. This is Howard McGary's approach, for example, in his discussion of the conditions for vicarious liability (Reference McGary1986, p. 158). But shared social practices imply the existence of a social group that shares those practices, so long as we include implicit, informal, and unstructured groups in our understanding of what a social group is.Footnote 9 In other words, a capacious understanding of social groups will not overlook harms generated by shared practices, and so (2) refers to social affiliation broadly construed.Footnote 10

(2) also specifies that the harm is not directly or reasonably attributable to the actions of the subject who experiences social-regret. This means that the harm in question is not a reasonably predictable outcome of an individual's behaviours, interests, or desires. The set of core cases of social-regret is narrower than the set of cases involving non-agential or remote causation. A cocaine buyer may be a non-agential, distal cause of violence related to systems of drug production and trafficking, but that violence is a predictable outcome of the buyer's desires, interests, and behaviour, whereas social-regret is fitting when there is no such link. Consider, in contrast to the cocaine buyer, an athlete on a sports team who discovers that her teammates are doping. Though it could be said that the athlete's teammates took performance enhancing drugs for the sake of her interests, or that the athlete's desire to win played a causal role in her teammates’ decisions to dope, the harm in question is not a straightforward expression of her interests, desires, or behaviours, since cheating is not fundamental (and is perhaps anathema) to group membership on a sports team.

Finally, (3) accounts for the subject's feeling of being connected to or associated with the harm. When one feels social-regret, one typically considers oneself (at least implicitly) to be affiliated with the relevant social group or individual. If, for some reason, one is unaware of such an affiliation, social-regret is unlikely to occur. One complication is that sometimes ignorance of social affiliation is actively maintained, as Charles Mills argues in his analysis of white ignorance (Mills, Reference Mills, Tuana and Sullivan2007). For example, in Ashley W. Doane's words, ‘whites tend not to see themselves in racial terms and not to recognize the existence of the advantages that whites enjoy in American society’ (Doane, Reference Doane, Doane and Bonilla-Silva2003, pp. 13–14). If one refuses to acknowledge specific facets of one's social situatedness or identity, then one may avert social-regret even after learning of the harms caused by an affiliated party. (3) suggests that the experience of social-regret can be evaded by denying or maintaining ignorance of one's affiliations with a given harm.Footnote 11

These three features can also be used to explain the relationship between evaluator-regret, agent-regret, and social-regret. An individual feeling evaluator-regret typically satisfies (1); an individual feeling agent-regret typically satisfies (1) and a modified version of (2), such that the harm in question is reasonably attributable to the subject herself; and an individual feeling social-regret typically satisfies all three conditions.

3. What Does Social-Regret Do?

So far, I have described some of the basic features of social-regret and situated it among other forms of regret. But what does social-regret do? That is, what potential insights and practical opportunities arise from experiences of social-regret?

Social-regret, like other moral emotions such a guilt, shame, and indignation, can be an expressive and revelatory experience. The counterfactual reasoning inherent to regret means that it can be understood as ‘a way of expressing concern and of conferring value’ (Bagnoli, Reference Bagnoli2000, p. 169). More specifically, social-regret expresses that one values unrealized alternatives, and it may shed light on the principles implied by those alternatives.Footnote 12 It can also alert us to the existence of implicit, but previously unarticulated in-group expectations that have been violated. Wallace argues that a key characteristic of reactive emotions that sets them apart from other attitudes is their close connection to the expectations to which we hold others. ‘[T]o hold someone to an expectation’, Wallace writes, ‘… is to be susceptible to a certain range of emotions if the expectation is violated, or to believe that it would be appropriate for one to feel those emotions if the expectation is violated’ (Wallace, Reference Wallace1994, p. 23). In a similar way, we are susceptible to social-regret because we hold and are held by others to normative expectations.

To be sure, we are not always conscious of the details of the expectations to which we hold others or to which we are held, and we may even hold inaccurate views about them. Emotions can intervene on such ambiguity by ‘rendering previously ignored features and previously unknown patterns salient’ (Elgin, Reference Elgin, Brun, Doğuoğlu and Kuenzle2007, p. 45), and ‘provid[ing] orientations that render particular facets of things salient’ (Reference Elgin, Brun, Doğuoğlu and Kuenzle2007, p. 33). Someone who discovers new and unexpected feelings of romantic jealousy when a friend begins dating someone else might be prompted to realize that the story she tells herself about their relationship is untrue. Here, her feeling belies her self-perception. Just as such a person might ask herself, ‘Do I feel jealousy because I am in love with my friend?’, an individual experiencing social-regret is well positioned to ask after the details of a harm and the moral salience of the social relation in question – for example, whether the harm evinces a violation of an in-group expectation or self-applied commitment.

A natural question is whether social-regret alerts us to real reparative obligations. At this stage, however, it is important not to expect too much of the emotion. Social-regret is not sufficient for (or even a reliable indicator of) ameliorative duties. But it does influence our attention and behaviour in ways that open space for novel deliberations over accountability. For the purposes of introducing the concept of social-regret, I will remain neutral on the question of the content and grounding of the potential ameliorative duties and accountability practices that might come into view via social-regret in different contexts.Footnote 13 We can speak to the epistemic and conative outcomes of social-regret – that it affectively prompts us to learn more about the situation that gave rise to it, and to reflect upon one's relationship to the person or group on account of whom one experiences it – even without committing to a specific account of concomitant responsibilities.

Ascribing these outcomes to social-regret does not mean that everyone who experiences it will actually weigh the moral salience of their social connection to a harm. Like anger, pride, guilt, jealousy, and other emotions, social-regret can be suppressed, ignored, denied, deferred, or drowned out by other affects, emotions, desires, projects, commitments, and obligations. As Myisha Cherry argues, the action tendencies of emotions – that is, the ‘behavior[s] that a person is likely to engage in, given the [emotion]’ (Reference Cherry2021, p. 11) – are defeasible, but nonetheless carry moral and political stakes:

Emotions motivate us to act in a certain way. They can also influence our beliefs and desires. Yes, we can act or not act, and the emotion can only do its thing through us and in partnership with us. If I say the action tendency of anger is to approach a target, I simply mean that the anger motivates us to do so. What we eventually do is up to us. (Cherry, Reference Cherry2021, p. 14)

This is a helpful way to think about social-regret. The action tendencies of social-regret are those of investigation and reflection upon social relations and relata, and these arise out of affects of pressure, discomfort, attentiveness, alarm, and persistent curiosity, like that of rubbernecking drivers who cannot help but look at an accident. It is through this shift in attention that significant moral and political outcomes (including, perhaps, the taking on of responsibility and/or accountability for others’ harm) are made possible.

4. Why Regret?

In what remains I will argue that there are both conceptual and rhetorical reasons for analysing the emotion of social proximity to harm in terms of regret over (or alongside with) existing accounts of embarrassment, guilt, or shame.

4.1 Embarrassment

It is first helpful to distinguish between social-regret and embarrassment. It is true that in some circumstances the actions of social affiliates cause embarrassment. Consider, for example, Gabriele Taylor's account of embarrassment at the behaviour of a fellow countryman:

[A] countryman of mine behaves badly (in my view) in front of a foreign audience. I feel embarrassed. Why? He is being seen as a poor specimen, or so I imagine. Because of our shared nationality this verdict affects me as well. But I object to being so seen, so in some way I have to dissociate myself from my countryman, or correct the impression. Here the tension arises not because I actually identify with him, but because I believe that such identification is forced upon me by the audience on the basis of our connection. (Taylor, Reference Taylor1985, p. 72)

Several of the facts in Taylor's case fit the profile of social-regret: she sees that (1) a harm has occurred, that (2) the harm is done by a social affiliate and not herself, and that (3) she is affiliated with the actor in some way. Note, however, the importance of the audience: Taylor's embarrassment arises from the fact that her countryman is seen by an audience who also sees (or might see) that the two are affiliated. ‘In embarrassment’, Taylor goes on to say, ‘concern is always with one's own position vis-à-vis others’ (Reference Taylor1985, p. 75). In this case, identification with the foolish actor is ‘forced upon’ her by the thought that the audience could (hypothetically) turn their gaze in her direction and see her in an undesirable light.

This is not the concern that underlies social-regret, which can occur without reference to the spectre of a seeing audience, actual or imaginary. This is not to deny that embarrassment is sometimes a fitting response to the wrongdoings of social affiliates, but only to assert that there is a separate affect of social interconnection with wrongdoing that is not reducible to concern for being identified with a wrongdoer by others. The basic case for social-regret is this claim: that there is an affective weight of a social affiliate's wrongdoing apart from concerns about being seen to be affiliated. Martha, for example, need not expect that others will see her in a negative light because of her grandfather when she experiences social-regret for his actions. Of course, there may be specific situations in which they would, or in which Martha becomes especially attuned to others’ attention. Were Martha to travel to the Hiroshima Peace Memorial, for example, she might understandably be apprehensive about sharing her family's history with descendants of those directly affected by the bombings, or feel broadly conspicuous for being affiliated with the nation that enacted them. But such interpersonal awareness is not the core of her initial emotional reaction to learning of her grandfather's contributions to the development of nuclear weapons, which consisted simply of a felt sense of social proximity to harm. Put another way, social-regret is not a kind of dismay over the implications of another's harm for one's own standing.

4.2 Guilt and Collective Guilt

Insofar as guilt involves holding oneself to a demand and judging that one has fallen short of that demand (Wallace, Reference Wallace1994), it follows that guilt (understood as a self-directed negative assessment of one's own conduct) is not an appropriate moral emotion for cases of non-agential social proximity to wrongdoing.Footnote 14 Still, one might turn to guilt-like emotions by way of what Tollefsen calls ‘collective emotions’, which are felt ‘in response to the actions of groups’ (Reference Tollefsen2006, p. 222). Collective guilt has been argued to fittingly arise out of a variety of connections to wrongdoing, ranging from situations in which a single in-group member causes harm to those in which the collective qua collective is morally responsible. Some have even proposed that it is fitting to experience guilt in situations in which an agent merely benefits from ongoing group-based inequality (Branscombe and Doosje, Reference Branscombe, Doosje, Branscombe and Doosje2004, p. 6), and Christensen coins the term ‘innocent guilt’ to refer to the keen awareness of the ethical claim generated by the suffering of others to which one has not contributed (Christensen, Reference Christensen2013). Several of these more capacious concepts of collective guilt appear to be fitting moral responses for someone in Martha's situation.

These forms of guilt are broader than the subset of cases at issue here. Collective guilt is not only appropriate in cases of moral taint by mere association, but can also fittingly arise out of a diversity of agential linkages between a group member and a harm, such as when an individual has failed to prevent a harm (Lickel, Schmader, and Barquissau, Reference Lickel, Schmader, Barquissau, Branscombe and Doosje2004, p. 42), benefits from a harm (Iyer, Leach, and Pedersen, Reference Iyer, Leach, Pedersen, Branscombe and Doosje2004, p. 266), or is a member of a collective that is culpable qua collective (Christensen, Reference Christensen2013, p. 369). In short, collective guilt is not restricted to purely social affiliation to wrongdoing, while my goal is to demarcate the distinctiveness of the emotion that is fitting when an individual is connected to a harm solely in virtue of social relations, and where that individual does not otherwise bear individual or collective liability.

Margaret Gilbert's analysis of ‘membership guilt’ comes close to capturing the specific moral emotions of affiliated onlookers in terms of guilt. Gilbert and Priest argue that it can be appropriate for members of a plural subject (which Gilbert elsewhere uses interchangeably with the term ‘social group’Footnote 15) to feel membership guilt in response to the misconduct of their group, even when personal guilt is inappropriate (Gilbert and Priest, Reference Gilbert, Priest, Bazargan-Forward and Tollefsen2020, p. 32). Since plural subjects are sets of jointly committed persons, membership guilt can be considered to be ‘self’-directed towards the plural subject, as opposed to the individual self. To similar effect, Sepinwall argues that ‘faultless guilt’ can fittingly ‘emerge from a sense of shared agency that partly constitutes their relationship with the wrongdoer’, and that we ought to affirm and ‘perhaps even support efforts to enact the moral and material responses that [experiences of faultless guilt] produce (e.g., offers of repair)’ (Sepinwall, Reference Sepinwall2022, p. 215). By grounding her account of faultless guilt in shared agency, Sepinwall is able to draw connections to moral emotions precipitated by diffused agential connections to complex systems that produce harm, such as structural injustice and white supremacy.

Although Gilbert and Sepinwall's respective analyses are highly convincing, an important reason for seeking out an alternative account that takes regret, not guilt, as its genus is that Gilbert's concept of membership guilt and Sepinwall's concept of faultless guilt do not apply to social affiliates that are not members of plural subjects with shared agency.Footnote 16 A regret-based account is able to accommodate cases that involve social affiliates with whom joint action or shared agency is impossible. This is readily discernible in cases of social-regret for the conduct of now-deceased ancestors. Martha, for example, experiences social-regret with regard to the actions of her grandfather, with whom she does not (and could not, for the time period in question) share agency. Understanding this case through social-regret allows us to see Martha's moral emotion as akin to, but distinct from the moral emotions of harms involving joint agency.

4.3 Shame

According to Helen Block Lewis, the distinction between guilt and shame lies in the fact that the object of guilt is one's behaviour, while the object of shame is one's self, and this distinction has been enormously influential in philosophical conversations around moral emotion (H.B. Lewis, Reference Lewis1971).Footnote 17 Shame is a plausible moral emotion for Martha because, like regret, it can be appropriate when an individual is non-culpable, lacks an agential connection to the harm in question, and is connected to the harm through group membership. For example, May argues that shame is an appropriate affective response to moral taint associated with group-level wrongs or faults that result in collective omissions (May, Reference May1992, p. 121), and Oshana argues that ‘the [morally] tainted person would feel shame if she felt as she ought to feel’ (Reference Oshana2006, p. 364).

Still, I worry that shame does not adequately capture situations like Martha's. Let us distinguish two facets of shame: its ‘value-oriented’ dimension and its ‘other-oriented’ dimension (Laing, Reference Laing2022). The former has to do broadly with taking oneself to be deficient with regard to a norm, standard, or expectation, while the latter has to do broadly with one's concern with others’ ‘evaluatively laden psychological states of which one is the object’ (Reference Laing2022, p. 235).Footnote 18 Depending on the examples and accounts at hand, sometimes shame involves a feeling of ‘fall[ing] short of a standard of excellence’, and sometimes it involves a feeling of being viewed in a negative light, and/or apprehension about being ‘cut off and rejected, made an object of scorn and ridicule’ by others, and sometimes a mixture of both (Rawls, Reference Rawls1999, p. 423).Footnote 19

Cases of social-regret do not fit either picture. To take a value-oriented approach, the moral emotions of social connection to wrongdoing need not involve feeling or thinking ‘that one falls short of some value or standard’ (Laing, Reference Laing2022, p. 236); nor, by an other-oriented approach, need they involve losing face in the eyes of others or the threat of suffering social avoidance. Martha, for example, does not feel that she falls short of a standard, and (as discussed above in the discussion of embarrassment) does not anticipate being seen in a negative light by others. Her emotion is neither self-evaluative nor oriented towards others’ psychological states. Even Laing's recently proposed middle way between the value-oriented and other-oriented poles of shame, according to which shame involves ‘feel[ing] oneself to merit social avoidance or rejection by others’, does not fit the emotion of purely social proximity to wrongdoing (Reference Laing2022, p. 250). Martha does not take herself to merit social avoidance; rather, she feels herself to be inordinately connected to a harm partially brought about by someone close to her.Footnote 20

One might nevertheless suspect that social-regret falls under the umbrella of shame, understood in its most general sense as simply the feeling of being distressingly connected to something undesirable. I agree that under this expansive definition Martha can be understood to feel shame. But consider these additional reasons to favour the regret-based account offered above. The first reason is that under such a broad conception of shame, regret (in general) is also a species of shame, as well as guilt and many other negative, counterfactual emotions. If we say that it is fitting for Martha to feel shame without qualification, then we appeal to a rather broad swathe of our emotional lives and cover over the subtle affective relationship under consideration here.

To avoid this outcome, one might specify an anomalous species of shame – perhaps ‘vicarious shame’ or ‘shame by association’ – just as I have appealed to species of regret (agent-regret, social-regret). Working within the genus of shame, it could be argued, tracks closer to ordinary language. But ordinary language cuts both ways, and this brings us to a second reason to seek an alternative account: shame is often associated with self-disapprobation and/or feelings of guilt in our everyday lives.Footnote 21 Where my focus is on non-culpable and non-contributory relations to another's harm, the language of shame tempts connotations of moral disapprobation – in Taylor's words, ‘[a] person feeling shame judges herself adversely’ – whether related to self-evaluation or consciousness of others’ evaluations of the self, or both (Reference Taylor1985, p. 68).Footnote 22 The emotion I have called social-regret, however, is distinctive because it occurs even when no such self-disapprobation or perceived disapprobation by others is present. What is at stake is not one's own moral or social status, but instead the felt force of an affiliate's deeds.

A related reason to separate the emotions of an affiliated onlooker from shame is that shame is often said to carry troubling affective costs. Many scholars already worry over the tendency for shame to become pathologized and give rise to self-destructive behaviours.Footnote 23 If we say that it is fitting to feel shame for the wrongdoings of affiliated persons and groups, then we risk radically multiplying opportunities for fitting shame, thereby exacerbating concerns about overburdening. Moreover, the action tendencies of shame typically involve retreat from social contact.Footnote 24 Reframing the emotional experience of an affiliated onlooker away from shame is an opportunity to reassess the way in which that emotion makes a claim upon us. My suggestion is that regret, while hardly immune from pathologies, gives us a less morally-charged and affectively demanding way of accounting for the emotions of affiliation with wrongdoing, and that it consists of social action tendencies – as I say above, investigation and reflection upon social relations and relata.Footnote 25 I will grant that there is an affective resemblance between social-regret and shame, and I do not deny that there are shame-based accounts that can help make sense of the emotions of affiliated onlookers. By thinking through this emotion in other terms, however, we might better prepare ourselves to be moved towards productive social responses to an affiliate's harm.

This brings us to a final consideration in favour of distinguishing social-regret from shame: a regret-based account may, in certain contexts, avoid the tendency for guilt- or shame-based accounts to be dismissed as irrational, pathological, or excessive. Rhetorics of shame and guilt can elicit sharp and unproductive resistance, and it is easy to conflate species of guilt or shame that do not imply fault with species of guilt or shame that do (Young, Reference Marion2011). Individuals in situations like Martha's may understandably be reluctant to describe their feelings in terms that generally connote fault, liability, or stigma. As Jacquet emphasizes, ‘[s]hame is a painful emotion’ that invites a range of possible defensive reactions (Reference Jacquet2015, p. 151). Gilbert makes much the same point about guilt: ‘feeling guilt is unpleasant, and may have an inherently punishing character’ (Reference Gilbert, Priest, Bazargan-Forward and Tollefsen1997, p. 83). Though Gilbert goes on to claim that the unpleasantness of guilt can serve as a ‘stimulus to improvement in group action and the moral quality of group life’ (Reference Gilbert, Priest, Bazargan-Forward and Tollefsen1997, p. 83), that same unpleasantness can just as easily (and perhaps more frequently) elicit defensiveness, denials, and refusals. Tollefsen illustrates this in her description of Mississippi Senator Thad Cochran's refusal to sign his name to a resolution of apology for the Senate's past failure to pass anti-lynching legislation:

When asked by a reporter why his name was absent from the list of sponsors Cochran said: ‘I'm not in the business of apologizing for what someone else did or didn't do. I deplore and regret that lynching occurred and that those committing them weren't punished, but I'm not culpable’. (Tollefsen, Reference Tollefsen2006, p. 228)

Note that the senator's resistance to apologize for the harms of the (past) Senate is grounded in his intuition that apologies imply wrongdoing,Footnote 26 as if to say, ‘Apologies are for wrongdoings, and I have done no wrong, and so I will give no apology’. The associations between apologizing and culpability tempt the senator to conflate being affiliated with a harm with being at fault in a harm, and then to dismiss the moral emotions and associated obligations following from the former as excessive and unfitting in light of the evidence that he does not satisfy conditions for the latter. This defensive reaction against the language of guilt is part of what Karl Jaspers acknowledges when he writes that ‘in a way which is rationally not conceivable, which is even rationally refutable, I feel co-responsible for what Germans do and have done’ (Jaspers, Reference Jaspers and Ashton2001, p. 74). Admittedly, Jaspers is unique in that he does not dismiss feelings of guilt beyond those related to one's individual conduct as irrational, but in this passage he openly admits to the intuition that his own emotions, when described and understood as a form of guilt, are irrational. So long as we are primed to associate guilt with one's own culpable actions and shame with the moral or social status of the self, adjacent guilt- and shame-like feelings for others’ conduct will intuitively appear excessive and irrational.

The senator's reaction illustrates the way in which some might recoil at the idea that they ought to feel guilt or shame for others’ harms, no matter how insistent moral philosophers may be that certain species of guilt and shame do not imply as much. Anecdotally, my own experience is that many non-philosophers and philosophers alike are reflexively dismissive of moral emotions bearing the name ‘guilt’ or ‘shame’ in the absence of personal wrongdoing or character deficiencies. Relying solely on these terms makes it far too easy for some (sometimes in bad faith, sometimes not) to dismiss or suppress feelings of moral implicatedness via social affiliations.

But here is the rub: note that the senator is more comfortable using the language of regret ‘I deplore and regret that lynching occurred and that those committing them weren't punished’ – to respond to the wrongdoing of others. If our feelings of social proximity to wrongdoing have anything to teach us, as I suspect they do, then it will be important to speak about them in ways that allow us to sit with them long enough to move through them. Drawing a more obvious terminological distinction between, on the one hand, the emotions proper to individuals who are linked to harm solely in virtue of their affiliations, and, on the other hand, those proper to individuals with other morally charged connections to wrongdoing (agency, omission, benefit, shared responsibility, solidarity, and more) can better protect the former from being wrongly judged to be pathological cases of the latter. When we work through negative, retrospective reactions to others’ harm in terms of social-regret, a wider sense of social interconnection with persons, groups, institutions, and legacies comes into view. Harms that would otherwise appear to be another's to repent for and repair may, in some cases, emerge as opportunities for moral deliberation and shared accountability.

5. Conclusion

I have identified social-regret as an affective phenomenon that is distinct from both agent-regret and spectator-regret, and argued that it redirects our attention counterfactually towards valued alternative possibilities, the moral salience of the relation(s) in question, and the details of their harm. We would do well to explore new, alternative ways of describing the emotions of social proximity to harm, and the concept of social-regret is one such alternative. To be clear, this does not mean abandoning previous analyses of moral taint, guilt, or shame, many of which have explanatory value beyond the scope of the cases I focus on here. Instead, my goal is to offer a novel account through the lens of regret that can find its place alongside these existing accounts, that accommodates a larger set of cases than those involving joint agency, and that might circumvent some of the more entrenched moral associations of the language of guilt and shame.Footnote 27

Footnotes

1 For thorough analysis of Smith's discussion of these two irregularities, see Russell (Reference Russell1999).

2 ‘Upon account of our own connexion with [our nation], its prosperity and glory seem to reflect some sort of honour upon ourselves. When we compare it with other societies of the same kind, we are proud of its superiority, and mortified in some degree, if it appears in any respect below them’ (2002, p. 268 [VI.ii.2.2]).

3 I will not delineate sharply between wrongdoing and harm in this article. Others’ wrongdoing and others’ (non-culpable) harm can both give rise to the emotion that I have in mind, and the cases that I discuss involve both.

4 Anthony Appiah, for example, characterizes moral taint as affecting the public-facing moral integrity of an agent, and the purging of taint as a fundamentally symbolic act, as opposed to a moral obligation (Reference Appiah, May and Hoffman1991). Against this view, Oshana argues that moral taint ‘does not only emerge where the opinion of others matters’, but rather concerns the authenticity of one's own self-conception (Reference Oshana2006, p. 370). Oshana argues that those bearing moral taint are straightforwardly responsible for the ‘refusal to assess oneself and one's attitude toward one's community, and to choose one's identity on the basis of this assessment’ (Reference Oshana2006, p. 362), and also that certain forms of inherited moral taint ‘demarcat[e] a sphere of responsibility over which none of the standard criteria for responsibility need obtain’ (Reference Oshana2006, p. 367). Similarly, Larry May distinguishes between three kinds of moral taint: 1) taint ‘based on one's associations regardless of whether one is even aware that one has such associations’, 2) taint ‘based on associations one could distance oneself from’, and 3) taint ‘based on associations which one could end, but which, if ended, would still not make any difference in the world’ (Reference May, May and Hoffman1991, p. 250). Of these, May argues that the second and third forms of moral taint can appropriately give rise to moral responsibilities, in that the individual bearing taint is responsible for their chosen response to their affiliates’ harms.

5 I follow P.F. Strawson (Reference Strawson1962) in understanding reactive attitudes to refer broadly to attitudes (including emotions) experienced in response to interpersonal behaviour.

6 I am primarily concerned here with the ‘shape’ of Martha's emotion, as opposed to its ‘size’ (D'Arms and Jacobson, Reference D'Arms and Jacobson2000, p. 73). Note that even unfitting experiences of social-regret, like other unfitting emotions, can be epistemically revelatory.

7 Daniel Jacobson challenges Williams’ premise that regret is generally appropriate for anyone to feel upon learning of a harm, and argues instead that ‘all regret is agential’ (Reference Jacobson and Shoemaker2013, p. 100). In lieu of the language of regret for third-party onlookers to a harm, Jacobson prefers that of dismay. Jacobson's disagreement with Williams follows in part from his commitment to the views that 1) sentiments (as distinguished from emotions) are natural psychological kinds (Reference Jacobson and Shoemaker2013, p. 102n9) and that 2) regret is ‘a sentiment concerned with the agent's own errors’ (Reference Jacobson and Shoemaker2013, p. 102). In lieu of adjudicating this criticism, I will adopt Williams’ broad notion of ‘regret in general’, while remaining open in principle to the idea that the phenomenon under consideration could also be elucidated in terms of dismay, rather than regret. For additional objections to Williams’ classification of agent-regret in relation to regret in general, see Wallace (Reference Wallace2013, pp. 32–45).

8 Daniel Telech has recently argued that ‘if agent-regret is fitting, when it is, owing in part to causal agency being an expression of one's practical identity, then we might expect different kinds of “faultless blows” to our practical identities to render fitting responses structurally similar to agent-regret’ (Reference Telech, Szigeti and Talbert2022, p. 236). Building from Williams’ theory of practical identity, Telech proposes ‘relation-regret’ as an ‘anguished response to harm caused by a person to whom one is intimately related as a co-member of a group partly constitutive of one's practical identity’ (Reference Telech, Szigeti and Talbert2022, p. 249). I understand social-regret to name a very similar, if not the same, phenomenon, and I take my arguments in favour of a regret-based account in Section 4 to support Telech's account.

9 Due to limitations of space, I cannot fully present an account of which social relations can serve as vectors for social-regret, and therefore will only state my view that one can experience social-regret on account of a diversity of relations (including those that lack shared agency) without support. There are important differences between, for example, cases in which one supports or objects to one's group's actions, or benefits from an affiliate's harms, or participates in similar practices to those that brought about the harm, or in which a single member of a group causes harm as compared to the group as a whole causing harm. Only by first sketching the contours of social-regret can we later turn to the challenge of explaining how it tracks across contrasting social-metaphysical profiles. One promising approach to this problem can be developed out of Williams and Korsgaard's respective concepts of ‘practical identity’, which both lend themselves to the idea that social-regret is neither enabled nor precluded by metaphysical features of social groups, but rather by the self-application of social affiliations to one's practical identity. In other words, my view is that one is susceptible to social-regret on account of vectors that play outsized roles in the relational constitution of one's practical identity. See also Telech's view that practical identity is constituted by both ‘(a) subsumption under and (b) self-application of normatively significant (for the self in question) categories’ (Reference Telech, Szigeti and Talbert2022, p. 249).

10 For more on the interplay between social practices, social identity, and group affiliation, see Haslanger (Reference Haslanger2018).

11 That said, the concept of social-regret will need to be adjusted for situations of racial affiliation because, for example, complicity with and enrichment from systems of racial domination are not straightforwardly non-agential social affiliations, even if they are not always straightforwardly agential. As Marzia Milazzo argues, structures of white supremacy are sometimes depicted as ‘exist[ing] outside of white people's agency even as what continues to perpetuate whiteness is not mainly white people's unconscious habits, but their active interest in maintaining power’ (Reference Milazzo2017, p. 565). For present purposes I will restrict myself to unambiguously non-agential cases like that of Martha.

12 As Bagnoli rightly points out, ‘reasons for valuing do not always provide overriding reasons. … That is, to say that something is valuable does not imply that the agent has any reason to bring it about’ (Bagnoli, Reference Bagnoli2000, p. 178). This means that one can feel regret (and social-regret) even when there are overriding reasons for avoiding valued unrealized alternatives.

13 Possible starting points for justifying ameliorative duties for others’ harm include Christopher Kutz on responsibilities arising out of cooperative structures of interaction (Kutz, Reference Kutz2000, pp. 118–39); Philip Pettit on the criteria for moral agency qua group (Pettit, Reference Pettit2007, pp. 172–77); Stephanie Collins and András Szigeti on accountability deficits (Collins, Reference Collins2017; Szigeti, Reference Szigeti, Bazargan-Forward and Tollefsen2020); Iris Marion Young on ‘forward-looking responsibility’ for cumulative outcomes of structural processes (Young, Reference Marion2011); May on responsibility for shared attitudes (May, Reference May1992); and Anthony Appiah on outcome-independent symbolic reparation (Appiah, Reference Appiah, May and Hoffman1991), among many other approaches.

14 For a more thorough examination of Wallace's account of guilt, see also Tollefsen (Reference Tollefsen2006, p. 225).

16 In the case of membership guilt, this can be partially explained by Gilbert's stated focus on ‘collective guilt feelings over what the collective itself has done’, and not on ‘guilt over what one of our members has done, given that this person was acting as one of us’ (Gilbert, Reference Gilbert2002, p. 130). Sepinwall openly focuses her account on ‘intimates’ (Reference Sepinwall2022, p. 215), and though she takes up white guilt as a related phenomenon, her analysis largely restricts itself to cases of shared agency.

17 For example, May claims that shame is ‘directly related to a person's conception of herself or himself, rather than to explicit behavior (which is what guilt most commonly attaches to)’ (Reference May1992, p. 120). Similarly, Vice argues that guilt ‘is a reaction to what one has done, not primarily to who one is’ (Reference Vice2010, p. 328), and Haggerty voices much the same: ‘Shame is directly about the self. In guilt, however, it is not the self but the act that is the central focus of negative evaluation’ (Reference Haggerty2009, p. 304). A notable exception to this general trend is Wallace, who discusses shame for one's actions (as opposed to the self) at length (Wallace, Reference Wallace1994).

18 Gabriele Taylor includes both dimensions in her influential 1985 analysis of shame: ‘There are basically two elements in each case of shame. There is firstly the self-directed adverse judgement of the person feeling shame: she feels herself degraded, not the sort of person she believed, assumed, or hoped she was or anyway should be. … Secondly, there is the notion of the audience’ (Reference Taylor1985, p. 64). Williams foregrounds the other-oriented dimension: ‘The basic experience connected with shame is that of being seen, inappropriately, by the wrong people, in the wrong condition’ (Williams, Reference Williams1993, p. 79).

19 E.g., feeling shame at one's private thoughts need not involve social avoidance or sanction by others (though it could be understood as anticipating or imagining such encounters). On the other hand, one might feel shame in response to unjust ostracization, despite not actually taking oneself to be deficient. The way in which value-oriented and other-oriented analyses interrelate is a topic of disagreement among philosophers. See, for example, Calhoun (Reference Calhoun2004), O'Hear (Reference O'Hear1977), Rawls (Reference Rawls1999), Thomason (Reference Thomason2018), and Laing (Reference Laing2022).

20 It is worth noting that ‘feeling shame’ is distinct from ‘being ashamed’ understood as a doxastic attitude, such that describing oneself as ‘being ashamed’ of a social affiliate does not necessarily report an emotional state. I understand ‘being ashamed of x’ to name a moral judgement concerning x, and ‘feeling shame for x’ to name an affective response to x. The focus of this article is on the latter.

21 As Sepinwall puts it, ‘guilt and shame often co-travel, with the former causing the latter’ (Sepinwall, Reference Sepinwall2022, p. 207). Thomason also holds that ‘shame is something of a moral companion to guilt’ (Reference Thomason2018, p. 1). Wallace spells out how the two can arise together without contradiction: ‘In addition to feeling guilt about my failure to act in accordance with the demands to which I hold myself, I may feel moral shame because I lack the moral excellences that I aspire to’ (Reference Wallace1994, p. 37). See also Rawls (Reference Rawls1999, p. 391).

22 ‘[I]n shame’, Michael Lewis argues, ‘the entire self is no good, as captured in the expression “I am a bad person”’ (Reference Lewis, Gilbert and Andrews1998, p. 128).

23 For example, John Kekes argues that ‘whatever value there is in shame can be achieved in less self-destructive ways’ (Reference Kekes1988, p. 282). See Thomason (Reference Thomason2018, pp. 128–31) for a survey of criticisms on the destructive nature of shame. Nussbaum extends these worries to a social context: ‘[B]oth emotions [disgust and shame] are associated with forms of social behavior in which a dominant group subordinates and stigmatizes other groups. … [T]he prominent use of shame in punishment and lawmaking seems tantamount to inviting people to discriminate and stigmatize’ (Reference Nussbaum2006, pp. 336–37). Nussbaum also considers the tendency for shame to give way to ‘narcissistic rage’ or ‘shame-driven rage’ (Reference Nussbaum2006, pp. 209–10).

24 In Jennifer Jacquet's words, ‘shaming is so serious and causes such pain that the transgressor would rather live as an outsider or would rather not live at all’ (Reference Jacquet2015, p. 151).

25 For more on the potential for our emotions to mislead us in systematic and self-concealing ways, see Goldie (2008).

26 I do not grant this premise.

27 This article has benefitted in more ways than I can list here from thorough feedback from anonymous reviewers. I am grateful for those reviewers’ time, suggestions, and philosophical intuitions.

References

Appiah, Anthony, ‘Racism and Moral Pollution’, in May, Larry and Hoffman, Stacey (eds.), Collective Responsibility: Five Decades of Debate in Theoretical and Applied Ethics (Savage: Rowman & Littefield, 1991), 219–38.Google Scholar
Bagnoli, Carla, ‘Value in the Guise of Regret’, Philosophical Explorations, 3:2 (2000), 169–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Branscombe, Nyla R. and Doosje, Bertjan, ‘International Perspectives on the Experience of Collective Guilt’, in Branscombe, Nyla R. and Doosje, Bertjan (eds.), Collective Guilt: International Perspectives (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Calhoun, Cheshire, ‘An Apology for Moral Shame’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 12:2 (2004), 127–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cherry, Myisha, The Case for Rage: Why Anger is Essential to Anti-Racist Struggle (New York: Oxford University Press, 2021).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christensen, Anne-Marie, ‘The Role of Innocent Guilt in Post-Conflict Work’, Journal of Applied Philosophy, 30:4 (2013), 365–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collins, Stephanie, ‘Filling Collective Duty Gaps’, Journal of Philosophy, 114:11 (2017), 573–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
D'Arms, Justin and Jacobson, Daniel, ‘The Moralistic Fallacy: On the “Appropriateness” of Emotions’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 61:1 (2000), 6590.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Sousa, Ronald, The Rationality of Emotion (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1987).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Doane, Ashley W., ‘Rethinking Whiteness Studies’, in Doane, Ashley W. and Bonilla-Silva, Eduardo (eds.), White Out: The Continuing Significance of Racism (New York: Routledge, 2003), 318.Google Scholar
Elgin, Catherine Z., ‘Emotion and Understanding’, in Brun, Georg, Doğuoğlu, Uvli, and Kuenzle, Dominique (eds.), Epistemology and Emotions (Burlington: Ashgate, 2007), 3350.Google Scholar
Gilbert, Margaret, On Social Facts (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilbert, Margaret, ‘Group Wrongs and Guilt Feelings’, The Journal of Ethics, 1:1 (1997), 6584.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilbert, Margaret, ‘Collective Guilt and Collective Guilt Feelings’, The Journal of Ethics, 6:6 (2002), 115–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilbert, Margaret and Priest, Maura, ‘Collective Moral Responsibility and What Follows for Group Members’, in Bazargan-Forward, Saba and Tollefsen, Deborah (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Collective Responsibility (New York: Routledge, 2020), 2337.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldie, Peter, ‘Misleading Emotions’, in Brun, Georg, Doğuoğlu, Uvli, and Kuenzle, Dominique (eds.), Epistemology and Emotions (Burlington: Ashgate, 2008), 149–65.Google Scholar
Haggerty, Daniel, ‘White Shame: Responsibility and Moral Emotions’, Philosophy Today, 53:1 (2009), 304–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haslanger, Sally, ‘What is a Social Practice?’, Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 82 (2018), 231–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Iyer, Aarti, Leach, Colin Wayne, and Pedersen, Anne, ‘Racial Wrongs and Restitutions: The Role of Guilt and Other Group-Based Emotions’, in Branscombe, Nyla R. and Doosje, Bertjan (eds.), Collective Guilt: International Perspectives (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 262–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jacobson, Daniel, ‘Regret, Agency, and Error’, in Shoemaker, David (ed.), Oxford Studies in Agency and Responsibility Volume 1 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013), 95125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jacquet, Jennifer, Is Shame Necessary? New Uses for an Old Tool (New York: Pantheon Books, 2015).Google Scholar
Jaspers, Karl, The Question of German Guilt, Ashton, E.B. (trans.), (New York: Fordham University Press, 2001).Google Scholar
Kahneman, Daniel and Tversky, Amos, ‘The Simulation Heuristic’, in Kahneman, Daniel, Slovic, Paul, and Tversky, Amos (eds.), Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1982), 201–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kekes, John, ‘Shame and Moral Progress’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 13:1 (1988), 282–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kutz, Christopher, Complicity: Ethics and Law for a Collective Age (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2000).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laing, James, ‘Making Sense of Shame’, Philosophy, 97:2 (2022), 233–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, Helen Block, Shame and Guilt in Neurosis (New York: International Universities Press, 1971).Google ScholarPubMed
Lewis, Michael, ‘Shame and Stigma’, in Gilbert, Paul and Andrews, Bernice (eds.), Shame: Interpersonal Behavior, Psychopathology, and Culture (New York: Oxford University Press, 1998), 126–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lickel, Brian, Schmader, Toni, and Barquissau, Marchelle, ‘The Evocation of Moral Emotions in Intergroup Contexts: The Distinction Between Collective Guilt and Collective Shame’, in Branscombe, Nyla R. and Doosje, Bertjan (eds.), Collective Guilt: International Perspectives (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 3555.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
May, Larry, ‘Metaphysical Guilt and Moral Taint’, in May, Larry and Hoffman, Stacey (eds.), Collective Responsibility: Five Decades of Debate in Theoretical and Applied Ethics (Savage: Rowman & Littlefield, 1991), 239–54.Google Scholar
May, Larry, Sharing Responsibility (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1992).Google Scholar
McGary, Howard, ‘Morality and Collective Liability’, Journal of Value Inquiry, 20 (1986), 157–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Milazzo, Marzia, ‘On White Ignorance, White Shame, and Other Pitfalls in Critical Philosophy of Race’, Journal of Applied Philosophy, 34:4 (2017), 557–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mills, Charles, ‘White Ignorance’, in Tuana, Nancy and Sullivan, Shannon (eds.), Race and Epistemologies of Ignorance (Albany: SUNY Press, 2007), 1138.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha C., Hiding from Humanity: Disgust, Shame, and the Law (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2006).Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha C., Political Emotions: Why Love Matters for Justice (Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University, 2013).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O'Hear, Anthony, ‘Guilt and Shame as Moral Concepts’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 77:1 (1977), 7386.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oshana, Marina, ‘Moral Taint’, Metaphilosophy, 37:34 (2006), 353–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettit, Philip, ‘Responsibility Incorporated’, Ethics, 117:2 (2007), 171201.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice: Revised Edition (Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University, 1999).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roberts, Robert C., Emotions in the Moral Life (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, Paul, ‘Smith on Moral Sentiment and Moral Luck’, History of Philosophy Quarterly, 16:1 (1999), 3758.Google Scholar
Sepinwall, Amy, ‘Shared Guilt among Intimates’, International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 30:3 (2022), 202–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Adam, The Theory of Moral Sentiments, Haakonssen, Knud (ed.), (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strawson, P.F., ‘Freedom and Resentment’, Proceedings of the British Academy, 48 (1962), 187211.Google Scholar
Szigeti, András, ‘The Discursive Dilemma and Collective Responsibility’, in Bazargan-Forward, Saba and Tollefsen, Deborah (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Collective Responsibility (New York: Routledge, 2020), 297312.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, Gabriele, Pride, Shame, and Guilt: Emotions of Self-Assessment (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1985).Google Scholar
Telech, Daniel, ‘Relation-Regret and Associative Luck: On Rationally Regretting What Another Has Done’, in Szigeti, Andras and Talbert, Matthew (eds.), Morality and Agency: Themes from Bernard Williams (New York: Oxford University Press, 2022), 233–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomason, Krista K., Naked: The Dark Side of Shame and Moral Life (New York: Oxford University Press, 2018).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tollefsen, Deborah, ‘The Rationality of Collective Guilt’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 30:1 (2006), 222–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vice, Samantha, ‘How Do I Live in This Strange Place?’, Journal of Social Philosophy, 41:3 (2010), 323–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wallace, R. Jay, Responsibility and the Moral Sentiments (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1994).Google Scholar
Wallace, R. Jay, The View From Here: On Affirmation, Attachment, and the Limits of Regret (New York: Oxford University Press, 2013).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Bernard, ‘Moral Luck’, in Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers 19731980 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), 2039.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Bernard, Shame and Necessity (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marion, Iris Young, Responsibility for Justice (New York: Oxford University Press, 2011).Google Scholar